Skip to main content

Full text of "A history of the literature of ancient Greece;"

See other formats







HANDBOUND 
AT THE 


Θ 


UNIVERSITY OF 
TORONTO PRESS 











a 
ν Ὁ ἃ 
PA Ἡρὼ 
ἀν νυ 
Ἔ 


a 






t 
4 


~ 


) 
ds a 





Digitized by the Internet Archive 
in 2007 with funding from 
Microsoft Corporation 


http://www.archive.org/details/historyofliteratO2mluoft 


HISTORY OF THE LITERATURE 


OF 


ANCIENT GREECE. 





VOLUME II. 


Von. II. | . a 





ELS 


HISTORY OF THE LITERATURE 


OF 


ANCIENT GREECE. 


\ 2d 
ot ῷ «" 


By K. re MULLER 


LATE PROFESSOR IN THE UNIVERSITY OF GOTTINGEN. 
eis Δ Kt DA +he Geyman many ger β΄ 
vy C.. δ, Lewis ὃ, “yew, Donaldson 
ae 
CONTINUED AFTER THE AUTHOR'S DEATH BY 


JOHN WILLIAM DONALDSON, D.D 


CLASSICAL EXAMINER IN THE UNIVERSITY OF LONDON; 


AND LATE FELLOW OF TRINITY COLLEGE, CAMBRIDGE. 


ΙΝ. THREE VOLUMES. 


VOL. II. A a 


LONDON : 
LONGMANS, GREEN, AND CO. 


Sg gue ge Μὴ μα 


τω» 


μι μὰ 


CONTENTS 


OF 


THE SECOND VOLUME 





SECOND PERIOD—(CONTINUVED). 





CHAPTER XXVII. 
ORIGIN AND STRUCTURE OF THE OLD COMEDY. 


. The comic element in Greek poetry due to the worship of Bacchus 
Also connected with the Comus at the lesser Dionysia : Phallic songs 
Beginnings of dramatic comedy at Megara : asia Chionides, &c . 
The perfectors of the old Attic comedy". . . ᾿ 
The structure of comedy. What it has in common with tragedy 

. Peculiar arrangement of the chorus; Parabasis . aos 
. Dances, metres, and style . ΤΣ ἐν δε, 


CHAPTER XXVIII. 
ARISTOPHANES. 


. Events of the life of Aristophanes ; the mode of his first appearance . 
His dramas : the Detaleis; the mee ge : 5 25 

The Acharnians analyzed . 5 ἘΠῚ 

The Knights . 

The Clouds 

The Wasps 

. The Peace 

. The Birds 

. The Lysistrata ; Thesmophivichake 

. The Frogs 


. The Leclesiazuse ; the Second Plutus. " Pransition be the middle δον , 


CHAPTER XXIX. 


THE OTHER POETS OF THE OLD COMEDY—THE MIDDLE AND NEW 


COMEDY. 


81. Characteristics of Cratinus . . . . .. 
2. Eupolis 


3. Peculiar ἠδ ουεῖν, of Gentes tds connexion with Sicilian sienctiy 


vl 


§ 4. 
5. 


6, The middle Attic comedy ; poets of this class akin to those of the Sicilian 


f 


8. 
9. 


+3. 
4, 
5. 
6. 


CONTENTS. 


Sicilian comedy originates in the Doric farces of Megara 
Events in the life of Epicharmus ; general tendency and nature of his comselgee 


comedy in many of their pieces . . . 0 «© © + «wae 
Poets of the new comedy the immediate successors of bass of the middle 

comedy. How the new comedy becomes naturalized at Rome . .. - 
Public morality at Athens atthe time of the new comedy . . .. - + 
Character of the new comedy in connexion therewith 


CHAPTER XXX. 


LYRIC AND EPIC POETRY DURING THIS PERIOD. 


. The Dithyramb becomes the chief form of Athenian lyric ee Lasus 


of Hermione . ey 
. New style of the Githjesa ΕΥΡΈΣΝΝ “ Melediideas Philoxenus. 

Cinesias. Phrynis. Timotheus. Polyeidus. . . . #...~. 
Mode of producing the new dithyramb : its contents and character . 
Reflective lyric poetry . τος TY SOME! De ΟΣ ον 
Social and political elegies. The Zyde of Antimachus essentially different 
Epic poetry. Panyasis. Cheerilus. Antimachus. οἰ G6. ieee 


CHAPTER XXXI. 


POLITICAL ORATORY AT ATHENS PREVIOUSLY TO THE INFLUENCE 


OF RHETORIC. 


§ 1. Importance of prose at this period . He τ 
2. Oratory at Athens rendered necessary by the aamicovebionl Savin of oovasies 
ment . . . ἐὰν te , 
3. Themistocles ; Petiians sawer of their τῆνος Ξ 5 
4, Chaxacteristics of their oratory in relation to their oniniiek ‘ol modek of 
thought ... Tere δον, ς΄ ὩΣ 
5. Form and style of their ceded pe en TANS, 910 a ade 
CHAPTER XXXII. 
THE RHETORIC OF THE SOPHISTS, 
§ 1. Profession of the Sophists: essential elements of their doctrines, The 
principles of Protagoras . . 
2. Opinions of Gorgias. Pernicious effects of his doctrines cmpestatind as they 
were carried out by his disciples . . . : 
3. Important services of the Sophists in forming a cake wiyfas ‘aiftepeat ree 
dencies of the Sicilian and other Sophists in this respect . . . . + 
ig, he rhotoric of Gorgias...) 4. ap 0 5 so oe 


ΣΙΝ Jorms of expression <. 01. aloes. la a a 


CONTENTS. vu 


CHAPTER XXXIITI, 


THE BEGINNINGS OF REGULAR POLITICAL AND FORENSIC ORATORY 
AMONG THE ATHENIANS, 


PAGE 
$1. Antiphon’s career and employments . . . ...... . + + 103 
2. His school-exercises, the Tetralogies . . . ars. Sr nae FO 


3. His speeches before the courts ; character of his ‘oratory a ae at ae ee 
4, 5. More particular examination of his style . . . . Sater esY ΡΣ 5... 
G. Andocides; hislifeand character . . οὖ. =. + + + e + et + 13 


CHAPTER XXXIV. 
THE POLITICAL HISTORIOGRAPHY OF THUCYDIDES. 


81, The life of Thucydides ; his training that of the age of Pericles . . . . 116 
2. His new method of treating history . . cg em ka 

3, 4. The consequent distribution and ὐδοιίνομε οὔ his siktnstals oat ee AO 

5. His mode of treating these materials ; his research and criticism . . . 124 

6, 7. Accuracy and intellectual dharastec OF his ἡ οι του ee oe τὰς 

8, 9. The speeches considered as the soul of hishistory . . . . . τ. 127 
10, 11. His mode of expression and the structure of his sentences . . . . 132 


CHAPTER XXXYV. 
THE NEW CULTIVATION OF ORATORY BY LYSIAS. 


§ 1. Events which followed the Soe ψήνας ἃ war. The adventures of Lysias. 
Leading epochs of his life. . . ah ital erry creat babs ΔΕΙ͂Ν 
2, The earlier sophistical rhetoric of ia ER TE Sk ek 30 
3. The style of this rhetoric preserved in his later sy Aaa ἰἠθϑοῖδι ΠΣ ὙΔΕ 
4, Change in the oratory of Lysias produced by his own impulses and εἰ his 


employment as a writer of speeches for private individuals . . 143 
5. Analysis of his speech against Agoratus . . . . . +. + + «© + + 0144 
6. General view of his extant orations . . . . + © «+ + © «© «© « 146 


CHAPTER XXXVI. 
ISOCRATES. 


§ 1. Early training of Isocrates ; but slightly influenced by Socrates. . . 148 
2. School of Isocrates ; its ἐπεξ repute; his attempts to influence the polities 


of the day without thoroughly understanding them . . . . . . . 149 

3. The form of a speech the principal matter in hisjudgment . . . . . 152 
τά, New development which he gave to prose composition . . . + - » 153 
5. His structure of periods . . . . « teehee ad sacs) s begs 185 
6. Smoothness and evenness of his style. . . cobs ἔων μα εἰν cal FST 


7. He prefers the panegyrical oratory to the Sucaie Ue Pa ΤΡ ae 158 


Ψ1Π CONTENTS. 


CHAPTER XXXVII. 


THE NEW BEGINNING OF ATTIC TRAINING—-FOUNDATION OF THE 


SOCRATIC SCHOOLS. 
PAGE 


. Socrates ; his literary importance . . . 161 
; i cakotratio tendency of Athenian literature dase: the Pelopooneeiaain war 162 
- How far Socrates was the founder of dialectical reasoning and moral 


philosophy . . » ‘tn econ cy at 


. Imperfect Socratic schools; ἐ Bucleides ahd the Massel οἰ ἐμ 
. Antisthenes and the Cynics . . 5 1 τς ee te tt .ΞΞ 
. Aristippus and the Cyrenaicas . . «+ + 6 ees es sl 


CHAPTER XXXVIII. 


XENOPHON AND CTESIAS. 


§ 1. Life and adventures of Xenophon . . « 4 s ss so se « 6) aGB 
2. The practical design of his writings . . bi) τ -1 bc) Fe fie eine ee 
8. His Grecian History ; its merits and defesien Το τ 
4, The Anabasis . . οὐ σέο ee 
5. The Memorials and iy te of Sebaaten % οἷν on ᾿οσρξον is elie See 
6. The Cyropedia and Agesilaus « ss ν τὸ +s τῶ « σῷ “asin s 0) GS 
7. Xenophon’s minor tracts. . . ὦ gg ag re ol ee eo 
8. The leading characteristics of his shale: yee a et 
9. Ctesias, a contemporary of Xenophon; his works . . . .. . . . 200 

CHAPTER XXXIX. 
PLATO. 

§ 1. Importance of Plato’ 8 writings even in a shine pointofview . . . . 202 
2. lifeof Plato . . . Pees ee 
8. His political character pa pe Dat ΤΥ ΑΝ τ + tn) ἐς ΠΣ 
4, His literary relations to his contemporaries and ξαδορλβειβες Lei ΝΝ 
5. Why he wrote in dialogues . . . Ὧν π΄. 
6. Chronological order and scientific iconanseeeens of his wee os 6 eo 
7, Plato’adialectios © 2. 61 8 et tt νον Oe 
8, His ethical system. . wb wwe αἰ ΤΑΣ. Oo ΞΕ 
9. His physical speculations. . . s 8 8 te se 0 ag Ξ Ξ--ὲ-Ὁ 

10. Peculiarities and excellences of his style thw 3 See 3 ol 
CHAPTER XL. 
ARISTOTLE. 

§ 1. Life of Aristotle . . . ee ee CSU ρς ΞΟ 
2. General view of his writings: Tren Tete Ξ 
8. His metaphysics and Loe oe Nk fae Προς ΞΕ 
ἘΠΕ Fs , τ TE ὃ 


CONTENTS. 
πο] TIO gS kk ke tn ek me ee 
6. Moral philosophy Sra τ Se Ra PRR τέξει λα. eae 
7. Politics ; 
8. Natural history wad general physis ~ keels ee 
9. Miscellanies. . . Poa ὡς SOE RS Ὁ 


10. Deeded aivle οἱ hie writiags έν σέ ΣΝ 


CHAPTER XLI. 
DEMOSTHENES. 


$1. Life of Demosthenes . . ‘ 
2. Harangues to the people, chiedly relating to Philip of ἜῬΕΤΤΝ : 
3. Orations on public causes. . ἢ 
4, Speeches against Aischines . . . . . 
5. Speeches in the law courts on private causes . 
6. Style and characteristics of Demosthenes . 


CHAPTER XLII. 
ORATORS CONTEMPORARY WITH DEMOSTHENES. 


§ 1. The contemporaries of Demosthenes, with the exception of Iseus, may be 
classed as patriots and Macedonizers . . 3 aiirnkeeaaestl.s 
2. Orators of the Alexandrian canon. Iseus . . . . «© « + © « ε 
3. Party of the patriots (a) ὍΡΟΝ : 
4, (Ὁ) Hypereides. . . . 
5. Macedonian party (a) Bechines. ΤΕΥ 
6. (6) Deinarchus. .. Shs) aekocae Se} 


CHAPTER XLITI. 


- RHETORICAL HISTORIANS AND PROVINCIAL ANTIQUARIES. 


§ 1. Connexion between Rhetoric and History. School of Isocrates 
2. Ephorus . ΠΡΟ αι re apr Tes, of Ese ied el» 
3. Theopompus . . Sie SN eh. φν ὃ, πὰ RS ρα 
4, Sicilian school : κω δ PRT Me? dt RP ere Te Rr’ ΜΝ 
5. Philistus 


ὃ, Writers of the Atthides . 


CHAPTER XLIV. 


MEDICAL LITERATURE—WRITINGS ATTRIBUTED TO HIPPOCRATES. 


81, Life of Hippocrates . . 
2. Origin and growth of aitiel literdture snags the γον 


8. Genuine works of Hippocrates . ; 
πο WORKS: . sis + . ὡς ὦ 
5, Spurious works. ΟΣ eh 
6. Publication of the Tinposcetie écllpetion Ἐν cee re 


7. Style and literary merits of Hippocrates . 


311 
325 
330 
334 
340 
342 


348 
349 
351 
356 
363 
369 


372 
374 
377 
382 
384 
388 


IA me oo bo καὶ 


CONTENTS. 


THIRD PERIOD OF GREEK LITERATURE. 
CHAPTER XLV. 


THE SCHOOL OF ALEXANDRIA—POETS. 


PAGE 
Alexandria and the Ptolemies . . + oe aan 

. Alexandrian poets ; their proper Ginanifieation nal avieasebe: ν τό Ὁ 
. Philetas in Alexandria, and Aratusin Macedonia . . . . . . «© « 422 
Callimachus . . PP MrPermerirrerrry 1 

. Lycophron and the tciisdinns ΕἾ woh ᾿ς ‘ 435 


. The epic and didactic poets, Apollonius, Bhianns, ποδός best Nicander 441 
. The bucolic poets, Theocritus, Bion, and Moschus. . . « «© « «© « 449 
. The parodists and phlyacographers. . «1 «© « «© + «© © « «6 « « 402 


CHAPTER XLVI. 


PROSE WRITERS OF ALEXANDRIA. 


. Classification of the prose writers of Alexandria: Demetrius the Phalerian 466 


2. (a) Grammarians and critics: Zenodotus of Ephesus, bares a 3 of 

Byzantium, and Aristarchus of Samothrace . . . . 469 
5. The recension of Homer../ .5 «᾿ς τ ὉΠ ΠΥ 
4, (Ὁ) Historians and chronologists . . . oe ea or 
5. Translations of Egyptian, Chaldean, and ites annla Fae’ 484 
6. (c) Pure and applied mathematics: Euclid, ee Apolloagag of 


Perga, Eratosthenes, and Hipparchus . . . ὶ δ ει ee στο ς΄ 





ERRATA. 


Page 236, line 11, for ‘ Gorgias’ read ‘ the Gorgias.’ 
Page 314, lines 23, 24, for ‘eight or nine’ read ‘ eighteen,’ 
Page 387, note 1, line 2, for ‘“A@ams’ read ‘*A@wus.’ 


A 


HISTORY OF THE LITERATURE 


OF 


ANCIENT GREECE; 


DOWN TO THE DEATH OF ISOCRATES. 


TRANSLATED FROM THE GERMAN MANUSCRIPT OF 


K. 0. MULLER, 


LATE PROFESSOR IN THE UNIVERSITY OF GOTTINGEN ; 


BY 
SIR GEORGE CORNEWALL LEWIS, Barr., Μ.Ρ,, 
LATE STUDENT OF CHRIST CHURCH, OXFORD ; 


AND 


JOHN WILLIAM DONALDSON, DD, 


LATE FELLOW OF TRINITY COLLEGE, CAMBRIDGE. 





HISTORY 


OF THE 


LITERATURE OF ANCIENT GREECE. 


SECOND PERIOD (Continued). 





CHAPTER XXVII. 


ORIGIN AND STRUCTURE OF THE OLD COMEDY. 


§ 1. The comic element in Greek poetry due to the worship of Bacchus. § 2. Also 
connected with the Comus at the lesser Dionysia: Phallic songs. § 3. Begin- 
nings of dramatic comedy at Megara: Susarion, Chionides, &c. ὃ 4. The per- 
fectors of the old Attic comedy. § 5. The structure of comedy. What it has in 
common with tragedy. § 6. Peculiar arrangement of the chorus ; Parabasis. 
§ 7. Dances, metres, and style. 


mo I. AVING followed one species of the drama, Tragedy, 

through its rise, progress, and decay, up to the time 
when it almost ceases to be poetry, we must return once more 
to its origin, in order to consider how it came to pass that the 
other species, Comedy, though it sprang from the same causes, 
and was matured by the same vivifying influences, nevertheless 
acquired so dissimilar a form. 

The opposition between tragedy and comedy did not make 
its first appearance along with these different species of the 
drama: it is as old as poetry itself. By the side of the noble 
and the great, the common and the base always appear in the 
guise of folly, and thus make the opposed qualities more con- 
spicuous. Nay more, in the same proportion as the mind 
nurtured and cultivated within itself its conceptions of the 
perfect order, beauty, and power, reigning in the universe and 
exhibiting themselves in the life of man, so much the more 
capable and competent would it become to comprehend the 

Vot. 11. B 





2 ORIGIN AND STRUCTURE OF THE OLD COMEDY. 


weak and perverted in their whole nature and manner, and to 
penetrate to their very heart and centre. In themselves the 
base and the perverted are certainly no proper subject for 
poetry: when, however, they are received among the con- 
ceptions of a mind teeming with thoughts of the great and 
the beautiful, they obtain a place in the world of the beautiful 
and become poetic. In consequence of the conditional and 
limited existence of our race, this tendency of the mind is 
always conversant about bare realities, while the opposite one 
has, with free creative energy, set up for itself a peculiar do- 
main of the imagination. Real life has always furnished 
superabundant materials for comic poetry; and if the poet in 
working up these materials has often made use of figures which 
do not actually exist, these are always intended to represent — 
actual appearances, circumstances, men, and classes of men: 
the base and the perverted are not invented; the invention 
consists in bringing them to light in their true form. A chief 
instrument of comic representation is Wit, which may be de- — 
fined to be,—a startling detection and display of the perverted — 
and deformed, when the base and the ridiculous are suddenly — 
illuminated by the flash of genius. Wit cannot lay hold of | 
that which is really sacred, sublime, and beautiful: in a certain — 
sense, it invariably degrades what it handles; but it cannot 
perform this office unless it takes up a higher and safer ground 
from which to hurl its darts. Even the commonest sort of 
wit, which is directed against the petty follies and mistakes of 
social life, must have for its basis a consciousness of the pos- 
session of that discreet reserve and elegant refinement which — 
constitute good manners. The more concealed the perversity, 
the more it assumes the garb of the right and the excellent; so 
much the more comic is it when suddenly seen through and 
detected, just because it is thus brought. most abruptly into 
contrast with the true and the good. 

We must now break off these general considerations, which 
do not properly belong to the problem we have to solve, and 
are only designed to call attention to the cognate and cor- 
responding features of tragic and comic poetry. If we return 
to history, we meet with the comic element even in epic poetry, 
partly in connexion with the heroic epos, where, as might be 








WORSHIP OF BACCHUS. 3 


expected, it makes its appearance only in certain passages,! and 


partly cultivated in a separate form, as in the Margites. Lyric 


poetry had produced in the iambics of Archilochus masterpieces 


_ of passionate invective and derision, the form and matter of 


which had the greatest influence on dramatic comedy. It was 
not, however, till this dramatic comedy appeared, that wit and 
ridicule attained to that greatness of form, that unconstrained 


freedom, and, if we may so say, that inspired energy in the 


representation of the common and contemptible which every 
friend of antiquity identifies with the name of Aristophanes. 
At that happy epoch, when the full strength of the national 
ideas and the warmth of noble feelings were still united with 
the sagacious, refined, and penetrating observation of human 
life, for which the Athenians were invariably distinguished among 
the other Greeks, Attic genius here found the form in which 
it could not merely point out the depraved and the foolish as 
they appeared in individuals, but even grasp and subdue them 
when gathered together in masses, and follow them into the 
secret places where the perverted tendencies of the age were 
fabricated. 

It was the worship of Bacchus again which rendered the 
construction of these great forms possible. It was by means of 
it that the imagination derived that bolder energy to which we 
have already ascribed the origin of the drama in general. The 


nearer the Attic comedy stands to its origin, the more it has of 
that peculiar inebriety of mind which the Greeks showed in 


everything relating to Bacchus; in their dances, their songs, 
their mimicry, and their sculpture. The unrestrained enjoy- 
ments of the Bacchic festivals imparted to all the motions of 
comedy a sort of grotesque boldness and mock dignity which 
raised to the region of poetry even what was vulgar and common 
in the representation: at the same time, this festal jollity of 





? As in the episode of Thersites and the comic scene with Agamemnon, above, 
chap. V. §8. The Odyssey has more elements of the satyric drama (as in the story 
of Polyphemus) than of the comedy proper. Satyric poetry brings rude, unintel- 
lectual, half-bestial humanity into contact with the tragical ; it places by the lofty 
forms of the heroes not human perverseness, but the want of real humanity, whereas 
comedy is conversant about_the deterioration of civilized humanity. With regard 
to Hesiod’s comic vein, see above, chap. XI. ὃ 3. ; and for the Margites, the same 
chap. § 4. 

B 2 


4 ORIGIN AND STRUCTURE OF THE OLD COMEDY. 


comedy at once broke through the restraints of decent beha- 
viour and morality which, on other occasions, were strictly 
attended to in those days. ‘ Let him stand out of the way of 
our choruses,’ cries Aristophanes,' ‘who has not been initiated 


into the Bacchic mysteries of the steer-eating Cratinus.’ The _ 


great comedian gives this epithet to his predecessor in order to 
compare him with Bacchus himself. A later writer regards 
comedy as altogether a product of the drunkenness, stupe- 
faction, and wantonness of the nocturnal Dionysia ;? and though 
this does not take into account the bitter and serious earnest- 
ness which so often forms a background to its bold and un- 
bridled fun, it nevertheless explains how comedy could throw 
aside the restraints usually imposed by the conventions of 
society. The whole was regarded as the wild drollery of an 
ancient carnival. When the period of universal inebriety and 
licensed frolic had passed away, all recollection of what had 
been seen and done was dismissed, save where the deeper 
earnestness of the comic poet had left a sting in the hearts of 
. the more intelligent among the audience.* 

§ 2. The side of the multifarious worship of Bacchus to 
which comedy attached itself, was naturally not the same as 
that to which the origin of tragedy was due. Tragedy, as we 
have seen, proceeded from the Lena, the winter feast of 
Bacchus, which awakened and fostered an enthusiastic sympathy 
with the apparent sorrows of the god of nature. But comedy 
was connected, according to universal tradition, with the lesser 
or country Dionysia, (τὰ μικρὰ, τὰ κατ᾽ ἄγρους Διονύσια.) the 
concluding feast of the vintage, at which an exulting joy over 
the inexhaustible exuberant riches of nature manifested itself in 
wantonness and petulance of every kind. In such a feast the 
comus or Bacchanalian procession was a principal ingredient: it 
was, of course, much less orderly and ceremonious than the 


comus at which Pindar’s Epinician odes were sung, (chap. XV. - 





1 Frogs, v. 356. 

? Eunapius, Vite Sophist. p. 32, ed. Boissonade, who explains from this the re- 
presentation of Socrates in the Clouds. During the comic contest the people kept 
eating and tippling ; the choruses had wine given to them as they went on and 
came off the stage. Philochorus in Athenzus, xi. p. 464 F. 

3 The σοφοί, who are opposed to the γελῶντες, Aristoph. Ecclesiaz. 1155. 





PHALLIC SONGS. 5 


§ 3. p. 221,) but very lively and tumultuous, a varied mixture 
of the wild carouse, the noisy song, and the drunken dance. 
According to Athenian authorities, which connect comedy at 
the country Dionysia immediately with the comus,' it is indu- 
bitable that the meaning of the word comedy is ‘a comus song,’ 
although others, even in ancient times, describe it as ‘a village 
song,” not badly as far as the fact is concerned, but the ety- 
-mology is manifestly erroneous. 

With the Bacchic comus, which turned a noisy festal banquet 
into a boisterous procession of revellers, a custom was from the 
earliest times connected, which was the first cause of the origin 
of comedy. The symbol of the productive power of nature was 
carried about by this band of revellers, and a wild, jovial song 
was recited in honour of the god in whom dwells this power of 
nature, namely, Bacchus himself, or one of his companions. 
Such phallophoric or ithyphallic songs were customary in 
various regions of Greece. The ancients give us many hints 
about the variegated garments, the coverings for the face, such 
as masks or thick chaplets of flowers, and the processions and 
songs of these comus singers.* Aristophanes, in his Acharnians, 
gives a most vivid picture of the Attic usages in this respect: 
in that play, the worthy Diczopolis, while war is raging around, 
alone peacefully celebrates the country Dionysia on his own 
farm; he has sacrificed with his slaves, and now prepares for 
the sacred procession ; his daughter carries the basket as Cane- 
phorus; behind her the slave holds the phallus aloft; and, 
while his wife regards the procession from the roof of the house, 
he himself begins the phallus song, ‘ O Phales, boon companion 
of Bacchus, thou nightly reveller !’ with that strange mixture of 
wantonness and serious piety which was possible only in the 
elementary religions of the ancient world. 





1See the quotations chap. XXI. § 5. ὁ κῶμος καὶ of κωμῳδοί. The feast of the 
great or city Dionysia is thus described, but it is obvious that the connexion pro- 
ceeded from the country Dionysia. 

2 From κώμη. The Peloponnesians, according to Aristotle, Poet. c. 3, used this 
etymology to support their claim to the invention of comedy, because they called 
villages κώμαι, but the Athenians δῆμοι. 

8 Atheneus, xiv. p. 621, 2, and the lexicographers Hesychius and Suidas, in 
various articles relating to the subject. Phallophori, Ithyphalli, Autokabdali, 
Tambiste, are the different names of these merryandrews, 


6 ORIGIN AND STRUCTURE OF THE OLD COMEDY. 


It belonged especially to the ceremonies of this Bacchic feast 
that after singing the song in honour of the god who was the 
leader of the frolic, the merry revellers found an object for 
their unrestrained petulance in whatever came first in their way, 
and overwhelmed the innocent spectators with a flood of witti- 
cisms, the boldness of which was justified by the festival itself. 
When the phallophori at Sicyon had come into the theatre with 
their motley garb, and had saluted Bacchus with a song, they 
turned to the spectators and jeered and flouted whomsoever 
they pleased. How intimately these jests were connected with 
the Bacchic song, and how essentially they belonged to it, may 
be seen very clearly from the chorus in the Frogs of Aristo- 
phanes. ‘This chorus is supposed to consist of persons initiated 
at Eleusis, who celebrate the mystic Dionysus Iacchus as the 
author of festal delights and the guide to a life of bliss in the 
other world. But this Iacchus is also, as Dionysus, the god of 
comedy, and the jokes which were suitable to these initiated 
persons, as an expression of their freedom from all the troubles 
of this life, also belonged to the country Dionysia, and attained 
to their highest and boldest exercise in comedy : this justifies 
the poet in treating the chorus of the Myste as merely a mask 
for the comic chorus, and in making it speak and sing much 
that was suitable to the comic chorus alone, which it resembled 
in all the features of its appearance.’ And thus it is quite in 
the spirit of the old original comedy that the chorus, after 
having in beautiful strains repeatedly celebrated Demeter and 
Iacchus, the god who has vouchsafed to them to dance and joke 
with impunity, directly after, and without any more immediate 
inducement, attacks an individual arbitrarily selected : ‘ Will ‘Ye, 
that we join in quizzing Archedemus ?” &c.? 

§ 3. This old lyric comedy, which did not differ much either 
in origin or form from the Iambics of Archilochus, may have 
been sung in various districts of Greece, just as it maintained 
its ground in many places even after the development of the 





1 See below, chap. XXVIII. § ro. 

2 When Aristotle says (Poet. 4) that comedy originated ἀπὸ τῶν ἐξαρχόντων τὰ 
φαλλικά, he alludes to these unpremeditated jokes, which the leader of the Phallus 
song might have produced, 


MEGARA. v 


dramatic comedy.’ By what gradations, however, dramatic 
comedy was developed, can only be inferred from the form of 
this drama itself, which still retained much of its original 
organization, and from the analogy of tragedy: for even the 
ancients laboured under a great deficiency of special tradition 
and direct information with regard to the progress of this branch 
of the drama. Aristotle says that comedy remained in obscurity 
at the first, because it was not thought serious or important 
enough to merit much attention ; that it was not till late that 
the comic poet received a chorus from the archon as a public 
matter ; and that previously, the choral-dancers were volunteers.” 
The Icarians, the inhabitants of a hamlet which, according to 
the tradition, was the first to receive Bacchus in that part of 
the country, and doubtless celebrated the country Dionysia 
with particular earnestness, claimed the honour of inventing 
comedy ; it was here that Susarion was said, for the first time, 
to have contended with a chorus of Icarians, who had smeared 
their faces with wine-lees, (whence their name, τρυγῳδοὶ, or 
*lee-singers,’) in order to obtain the prize, a basket of figs and 
a jarof wine. It is worth noticing, that Susarion is said to 
have been properly not of Attica, but a Megarian of Tripodiscus.* 
This statement is confirmed by various traditions and hints 
᾿ from the ancients, from which we may infer that the Dorians of 
Megara were distinguished by a peculiar fondness for jest and 
ridicule, which produced farcical entertainments full of jovial 
merriment and rude jokes. If we consider, in addition to this, 
that the celebrated Sicilian comedian Epicharmus dwelt at 





1 The existence of a lyrical tragedy and comedy, by the side of the dramatic, has 
been lately established chiefly by the aid of Beotian inscriptions, (Corpus Inscript. 
Grecar. No. 1584,) though it has been violently controverted by others. But 
though we should set aside the interpretation of these Bceotian monuments, it ap- 
pears even from Aristotle, Poet. 4, (τὰ φαλλικὰ ἃ ἔτι καὶ viv ἐν πολλαῖς τῶν πόλεων 
διαμένει νομιζόμενα,) that the songs, from which the dramatic comedy arose, still 
maintained their ground, as the ἰθύφαλλοι also were danced in the orchestra at 
Athens in the time of the orators. Hyperides apud Harpocrat. ν. ᾿Ιθύφαλλοι. It 
is clear that the comedies of Antheus the Lindian were also of this kind, according 
to the expressions of Athenzeus, (x. p. 445); ‘he composed comedies and many other 
things in the form of poems, which he sang as leader to his fellow-revellers who bore 
the phallus with him.’ 

2 Poet. 5. Comp. above, chap. XXIII. 8 1. 

3 See Miiller’s Dorians, Book IV. ch. 7. ὃ τ. 


8 ORIGIN AND STRUCTURE OF THE OLD COMEDY. 


Megara in Sicily, (a colony of the Megarians who lived near 
the borders of Attica,) before he went to Syracuse, and that the 
Sicilian Megarians, according to Aristotle, laid claim to the 
invention of comedy, as well as the neighbours of the Athenians, 
we must believe that some peculiar sparks of wit were contained 
in this little Dorian tribe, which, having fallen on the sus- 
ceptible temperaments of the other Dorians, and also of the 
common people of Attica, brought the talent for comedy to a 
speedy development, 

Susarion, however, who is said to have flourished in Solon’s 
time, about Ol. 50, somewhat earlier than Thespis,’ stands quite 
alone in Attica; a long time elapses before we hear of any 
further cultivation of comedy by poetsof eminence. This will 
not surprise us if we recollect that this interval is filled up by 
the long tyranny of Peisistratus and his sons, who would feel it 
due to their dignity and security not to allow a comic chorus, 
even under the mask of Bacchic inebriety and merriment, to 
utter ribald jests against them before the assembled people of 
Athens ; as understood by the Athenians of those days, comedy 
could not be brought to perfection save by republican freedom 
and equality. This was the reason why comedy continued so 
long an obscure amusement of noisy rustics, which no archon 
superintended, and which no particular poet was willing to 
avow : although, even in this modest retirement, it made some 
sudden advances, and developed completely its dramatic form. 
Consequently, the first of the eminent poets received it in a 
definite and tolerably complete form.’ This poet was Cu1on1pEs, 
whom Aristotle reckons the first of the Attic comedians, 
(omitting Myllus and some other comedians, though they also 
left their works in writing), and of whom we are credibly in- 
formed‘ that he began to bring out plays eight years before the 
Persian war. (Ol. 73, B.c. 488). He was followed by Maenzs, 
also born in the Bacchic village Icaria, who for a long time 





1 Parian marble. Ep. 39. 2 See above, ch. XX. § 3. 
3 Aristot. Poet. 5. ἤδη δὲ σχήματά τίνα αὐτῆς ἐχούσης ol λεγόμενοι αὐτῆς ποιηταὶ 
μνημονεύονται. 
*Suidas, v. "Χιωνίδης. Consequently, Aristotle, Poet. 3, (or, according to F. 
Ritter, a later interpreter,) must be in error when he places Chionides a good deal 
later than Epicharmus, 


CRATINUS—THEOPOMPUS. 9 


delighted the Athenians with his cheerful and multifarious 
fictions. To the same age of comedy belongs Ecruantipss, 
who was so little removed from the style of the Megarian farce, 
that he expressly remarked in one of his pieces,—‘ He was not 
bringing forward a song of the Megarian comedy ; he had grown 
ashamed of making his drama Megarian.’! 

§ 4. The second period of comedy comprises poets who 
flourished just before and during the Peloponnesian war. Cra- 
tinus died Ol. 89, 2. B.c. 423, being then very old; he seems 
to have been not much younger than Aischylus, and occupies a 
corresponding place among the comic poets; all accounts of 
his dramas, however, relate to the latter years of his life; and 
all we can say of him is, that he was not afraid to attack 
Pericles in his comedies at a time when that statesman was in 
the height of his reputation and power? Crares raised himself, 
from being an actor in the plays of Cratinus, to the rank of a 
distinguished poet: a career common to him with several of the 
ancient comedians. TrLecLerpes and Hermrrpvs also belong to 
the comic poets of the time of Pericles. Evroxis did not begin 
to bring out comedies till after the beginning of the Pelopon- 
nesian war (Ol. 87, 3. B.c. 429); his career terminated with 
that war. AristropHaNEs made his first appearance under 
another name in Ol. 88, τ. B.c. 427, and under his own name, 
Ol. 88, 4. B.c. 424; he went on writing till Ol. 97, 4. B.c. 388. 
Among the contemporaries of this great comic poet, we have 
also Purynicuvs (from Ol. 87, 3. B.c. 429); Pxato (from Ol. 88, 
I. B.C. 427 to Ol. 97, 1. B.c. 391, or even longer) ; PHERECRATES 
(who also flourished during the Peloponnesian war) ; AMEIPSIAs, 
who was sometimes a successful rival of Aristophanes ; Leucon, 
who also frequently contended with Aristophanes; Droc.zs, 
Puitytiius, Sannyrion, Strarris, Tarorompvs, who flourished 
towards the end of the Peloponnesian war and subsequently, 





1 Μεγαρικῆς 
κωμῳδίας dow’ οὐ δίειμ᾽ " ἠσχυνόμην 
τὸ δρᾶμα Μεγαρικὸν ποιεῖν. 
According to the arrangement of this fragment, (quoted by Aspasius on Aristot. 
Eth. Nic. iv. 2,) by Meineke, Historia Critica Comicorum Grecorum, p. 22, which 
is undoubtedly the correct one. 
? As appears from the fragments referring to the Odeion and the long walls. 


10 ORIGIN AND STRUCTURE OF THE OLD COMEDY. 


form the transition to the middle comedy of the Athe- 
nians.’ 

We content ourselves for the present with this brief chrono- 
logical view of the comic poets of the time, because in some 
respects it is impossible to characterize these authors, and in 
others, this cannot be done till we have become better acquainted 
with Aristophanes, and are able to refer to the creations of this 
poet. Accordingly, we will take a comparative glance at some 
of the pieces of Cratinus, Eupolis, and some others, after we 
have considered the comedy of Aristophanes: but must remark 
here beforehand that it is infinitely more difficult to form a con- 
ception of a lost comedy from the title and some fragments, 
than it would be to deal similarly with a lost tragedy. In the 
latter, we have in the mythical foundation something on which 
we may depend, and by the conformation of which the edifice 
to be restored must be regulated; whereas comedy, with its 
greater originality, passes at once from one distant object to 
another, and unites things which seem to have no connexion 
with one another, so that it is impossible to follow its rapid 
movements merely by the help of some traces accidentally 
preserved. 

§ 5. Before we turn to the works of Aristophanes, we must 
make ourselves acquainted with comedy in the same way that 
we have already done with tragedy, in order that the technical 
forms into which the poet had to cast his ideas and fancies may 
stand clearly and definitely before our eyes. These forms are 
partly the same as in the tragic drama,—as the locality and its 
permanent apparatus were also common to both; in other 
respects they are peculiar to comedy, and are intimately con- 
nected with its origin and development. 

To begin with the locality, the stage and orchestra, and, on 
the whole, their meaning, were common to tragedy and comedy. 

The stage (Proscenion) is, in comedy also, not the inside of 





1 According to the researches of Meineke, Hist. Orit. Com. Grecorum. Callias, 
who lived before Strattis, was likewise a comedian: his γραμματικὴ τραγῳδία 
could not have been a serious tragedy, but must have been a joke; the object and 
occasion of it, however, cannot easily be guessed at. The old grammarians must 
have been joking when they asserted that Sophocles and Euripides imitated this 
γραμματικὴ τραγῳδία in some piece or other. 


POINTS COMMON WITH TRAGEDY. 11 


a house, but some open space, in the background of which, on 
the wall of the scene, were represented public and private build- 
ings. Nay, it appeared to the ancients so utterly impossible to 
regard the scene as a room of a house, that even the new 
comedy, little as it had to do with actual public life, neverthe- 
less for the sake of representation, as we have remarked above, 
(chap. XXII. § 5,) made the scenes which it represents public : 
it endeavours, with as little sacrifice of nature as it may, so to 
arrange all the conversations and events that they may take 
place in the street and at the house-doors. The generally 
political subjects of the old comedy rendered this much less 
difficult ; and where it was absolutely necessary to represent an 
inner chamber of a house, they availed themselves of the 
resource of the Eccyclema. 

Another point, common to tragedy and comedy, was the 
limited number of the actors, by whom all the parts were to be 
performed. According to an authority,’ (on which, however, we 
cannot place perfect reliance,) Cratinus raised the number to 
three, and the scenes in most of the comedies of Aristophanes, 
as also in the plays of Sophocles and Euripides, can be per- 
formed by three actors only. The number of subordinate per- 
sons in comedy has made the change of parts more frequent and 
more varied. Thus, in the Acharnians, while the first player 
acted the part of Diczopolis, the second and third actors had to 
undertake now the Herald and Amphitheus, then again the 
ambassador and Pseudartabas; subsequently the wife and 
daughter of Diczeopolis, Euripides, and Cephisophon; then the 
Megarian and the Sycophant, and the Beotian and Nicarchus.? 
Tn other pieces, however, Aristophanes seems to have introduced 
a fourth actor (as Sophocles has done in the Gidipus at Colonus) ; 
the Wasps, for example, could hardly have been performed with- 
out four actors.° 

The use of masks and of a gay and striking costume was also 





1 Anonym. de Comedia, p. xxxii. Comp. Aristot. Poet. 5. 

3 The little daughters, who are sold as pigs, were perhaps puppets ; their koi, koi, 
and the other sounds they utter, were probably spoken behind the scenes as a para- 
scenion. 

3 In the Wasps, Philocleon, Bdelycleon, and the two slaves Xanthias and Sosias, 
are frequently on the stage at the same time as speaking persons. 


12 ORIGIN AND STRUCTURE OF THE OLD COMEDY. 


common to tragedy and comedy ;. but the forms of the one 
and the other were totally different. To conclude from the 
hints furnished by Aristophanes, (for we have a great want of 
special information on the subject,) his comic actors must have 
been still more unlike the histriones of the new comedy, of 
Plautus and Terence; of whom we know, from some very 
valuable and instructive paintings in ancient manuscripts, that 
they adopted, on the whole, the costume of everyday life, and 
that the form and mode of their tunics and palliums were the 
same as those of the actual personages whom they represented. 
The costume of Aristophanes’ players must, on the other hand, 
have resembled rather the garb of the farcical actors whom we 
often see depicted on vases from Magna Grecia, namely, close- 
fitting jackets and trousers striped with divers colours, which 
remind us of the modern Harlequin; to which were added 
great bellies and other disfigurations and appendages purposely 
extravagant and indecorous, the grotesque form being, at the 
most, but partially covered by a little mantle: then there were 
masks, the features of which were exaggerated even to carica- 
ture, yet so that particular persons, when such were brought 
upon the stage, might at once be recognised. It is well known 
that Aristophanes found great difficulty in inducing the mask- 
makers (σκευοποιοὶ) to provide him with a likeness of the uni- 
versally dreaded demagogue, Cleon, whom he introduces in his 
Knights. The costume of the chorus in a comedy of Ari- 
stophanes went farthest into the strange and fantastic. His 
choruses of birds, wasps, clouds, &c., must not of course be 
regarded as having consisted of birds, wasps, &c. actually repre- 
sented, but, as is clear from numerous hints from the poet 
himself, of a mixture of the human form with various ap- 
pendages borrowed from the creatures we have mentioned ;* and 
in this the poet allowed himself to give special prominence to 
those parts of the mask which he was most concerned about, 
and for which he had selected the mask: thus, for example, in 

the Wasps, who are designed to represent the swarms of Athe- 
nian judges, the sting was the chief attribute, as denoting the 





1 Like the Atvo. with beasts’ heads (Alsop’s fables) in the picture described by 
Philostratus. Imagines, I. 3. 


ARRANGEMENT OF CHORUS. 13 


style with which the judges used to mark down the number of 
their division in the wax-tablets; these waspish judges were 
introduced humming and buzzing up and down, now thrusting 
out, and now drawing in an immense spit, which was attached 
to them by way of a gigantic sting. Ancient poetry was suited, 
by its vivid plastic representations, to create a comic effect by 
the first sight of its comic chorus and its various motions on the 
stage; as in a play of Aristophanes (the Τῆρας), some old men 
come on the stage, and casting off their age in the form of a 
serpent’s skin (which was also called ynpac), immediately after 
conducted themselves in the most riotous and intemperate 
manner. 

§ 6. Comedy had much that was a eee its own in the 
arrangement, the movements, and the songs of the chorus. The © 
authorities agree in stating the number of persons in the comic 
chorus, at twenty-four: it is obvious that the complete chorus 
of the tragic tetralogy, (consisting of forty-eight persons,) was 
divided into two, and comedy kept its moiety undivided. Con- 
sequently, comedy, though in other respects placed a good deal 
below tragedy, had, nevertheless, the advantage of a more nu- 
merous chorus by this, that comedies were always represented 
separately, and never in tetralogies; whence it happened also, 
that the comic poets were much less prolific in plays than the 
tragic. This chorus, when it appeared in regular order, came 
on in rows of six persons, and as it entered the stage sang the 
parodos, which, however, was never so long or so artificially 
constructed as it was in many tragedies. Still less considerable 
were the stasima, which the chorus sings at the end of the scene 
while the characters are changing their dress: they only serve 
to finish off the separate scenes, without attempting to awaken 
that collected thought and tranquillity of mind which the tragic 
stasima were designed to produce. Deficiencies of this kind in 
its choral songs, comedy compensated in a very peculiar manner 
by its parabasis. 

The parabasis, which was an address of the chorus in the 
᾿ middle of the comedy, obviously originated in those phallic traits, 





1 With all Aristophanes’ long career, only 54 were attributed to him, of which 
four were said to be spurious—consequently, he only wrote half as many plays as 
Sophocles. Compare above, chap. XXIV. § 2. 


14 ORIGIN AND STRUCTURE OF THE OLD COMEDY. 


to which the whole entertainment was due; it was not ori- 
ginally a constituent part of comedy, but improved and worked 
out according to rules of art. The chorus, which up to that 
point had kept its place between the thymele and the stage, and 
had stood with its face to the stage, made an evolution, and 
proceeded in files towards the theatre, in the narrower sense of 
the word; that is, towards the place of the spectators. This 
is the proper parabasis, which usually consisted of anapzestic 
tetrameters, occasionally mixed up with other long verses; it 
began with a short opening song, (in anapeestic or trochaic verse,) 
which was called kommation, and ended with a very long and 
protracted anapeestic system, which, from its trial of the breath, 
was called pnigos (also makron). In this parabasis the poet 
makes his chorus speak of his own poetical affairs, of the object 
and end of his productions, of his services to the state, of his 
relation to his rivals, and so forth. If the parabasis is com- 
plete, in the wider sense of the word, this is followed by a 
second piece, which is properly the main point, and to which 
the anapeests only serve as an introduction. The chorus, namely, 
sings a lyrical poem, generally a song of praise in honour of 
some god, and then recites, in trochaic verses, (of which there 
should, regularly, be sixteen,) some joking complaint, some re- 
proach against the city, some witty sally against the people, 
with more or less reference to the leading subject of the play: 
this is called the epirrhema, or ‘ what is said in addition.” Both 
pieces, the lyrical strophe and the epirrhema, are repeated anti- 
strophically. It is clear, that the lyrical piece, with its anti- 
strophe, arose from the phallic song; and the epirrhema, with 
its antepirrhema, from the gibes with which the chorus of revel- 
lers assailed the. first persons they met. It was natural, as the 
parabasis came in the middle of the whole comedy, that, instead 
of these jests directed against individuals, a conception more 
significant, and more interesting to the public at large, should 
be substituted for them; while the gibes against individuals, 
suitable to the original nature of comedy, though without any 
reference to the connexion of the piece, might be put in the 
mouth of the chorus whenever occasion served.! 





1 Such parts are found in the Acharnians, v. 1143-1174, in the Wasps, 1265- 


DANCES. 15 


As the parabasis completely interrupts the action of the 
comic drama, it could only be introduced at some especial pause ; 
we find that Aristophanes is fond of introducing it at the point 
where the action, after all sorts of hindrances and delays, has 
got so far that the crisis must ensue, and it must be determined 
whether the end desired will be attained or not. Such, however, 
is the laxity with which comedy treats all these forms, that the 
parabasis may even be divided into two parts, and the anapzes- 
tical introduction be separated from the choral song ;’ there may 
even be a second parabasis, (but without the anapzstic march,) 
in order to mark a second transition in the action of the piece. 
Finally, the parabasis may be omitted altogether, as Aristo- 
phanes, in his Lysistrata, (in which a double chorus, one part 
consisting of women, the other of old men, sing so many sin- 
gularly clever odes,) has entirely dispensed with. this address to 
the public.* 

§ 7. It is a sufficient definition of the comic style of dancing 
to mention that it was the kordaz, i. 6. a species of dance which 
no Athenian could practise sober and unmasked without incur- 
ring a character for the greatest shamelessness.* Aristophanes 
takes great credit to himself in his Clouds (which, with all its 
burlesque scenes, strives after a nobler sort of comedy than his 
other pieces) for omitting the kordaz in this play, and for having 
laid aside some indecencies of costume.’ Everything shows 
that comedy, in its outward appearance, had quite the character 
of a farce, in which the sensual, or rather bestial, nature of 
man was unreservedly brought forward, not by way of permission 





1291, in the Birds, 1470-1493, 1553-1565, 1694-1705. We must not trouble our- 
selves with seeking a connexion between these verses and other parts. In fact, it 
needed but the slightest suggestion of the memory to occasion such sallies as these. 

1 Thus in the Peace, and in the Frogs, where the first half of the parabasis has 
coalesced with the parodos and the Iacchus-song, (of which see above, §2.). As 
Tacchus has been already praised in this first part, the lyrical strophes of the second 
part (v. 675 foll.) do not contain any invocation of gods, and such like, but are full 
of sarcasms about the demagogues Cleopbon and Cleigenes. We find the same de- 
viation, and from the same reasons, in the second parabasis of the Knights, 

2 As in the Knights. 

3 The parabasis is wanting in the Ecclesiazuse and the Plutus, for reasons which 
are stated in chap. XXVIII. § rr. 

4 Theophrast. Charact. 6. comp. Casaubon. 

5 Aristophanes, Clouds, 537 foll. 


16 ORIGIN AND STRUCTURE OF THE OLD COMEDY. 


only, but as a Jaw and rule. So much the more astonishing, 
then, is the high spirituality, the moral worth, with which the 
great comedians have been able to inspire this wild pastime, 
without thereby subverting its fundamental characteristics. Nay, 
if we compare with this old comedy the later conformation of 
the middle and new comedy, with the latter of which we are 
better acquainted, and which, with a more decent exterior, 
nevertheless preaches a far laxer morality, and if we reflect on 
the corresponding productions of modern literature, we shall 
almost be induced to believe that the old rude comedy, which 
concealed nothing, and was, in the representation of vulgar life, 
itself vulgar and bestial, was better suited to an age which 
meant well to morality and religion, and was more truly based 
on piety, than the more refined comedy, as it is called, which 
threw a veil ‘over everything, and, though it made vice ludicrous, 
failed to render it detestable.’ 
To return, however, to the kordax, and to connect with it a 
remark on the rhythmical structure of comedy; we learn acci- 
_dentally that the trochaic metre was also called kordax,’ doubtless 
because trochaic verses were generally sung as an accompaniment 
to the kordax dances. The trochaic metre, which was invented 
along with the iambic by the old iambographers, had a sort of 
lightness and activity, but wanted the serious and impressive 
character of the.iambus. It was especially appropriated to 
cheerful dances ;* even the trochaic tetrameter, which was not 
properly a lyrical metre, invited to motions like the dance. 
The rhythmical structure of comedy was obviously for the most 
part built upon the foundation of the old iambic poetry, and 
was merely extended and enlarged much in the same way as the 
Kolian and Doric lyrical poetry was adapted to tragedy, namely, 
by lengthening the verses to systems, as they are called, by a 
frequent repetition of the same rhythm. The asynartetic verses, 
in particular, ὁ. e., loose combinations of rhythms of different 





' Plutarch, in his comparison of Aristophanes and Menander, (of which an epitome 
has been preserved,) expresses an entirely opposite opinion, but this is only a proof 
how very often the later writers of antiquity mistook the form for the substance, 

® Aristotle, quoted by Quintilian, ix. 4. Cicero Orat. 57. 

8 Chap. XI. § 8, 22. 

4 Aristophan. Peace, 324 foll. 


LANGUAGE OF COMEDY. 17 


kinds, such as dactylic and trochaic, which may be regarded as 
forming a verse and also as different verses, belong only to the 
iambic and comic poetry ; and in this, comedy, though it added 
several new inventions, was merely continuing the work of 
Archilochus.’ 

That the prevalent form of the dialogue should be the same 
in tragedy and comedy, namely, the iambic trimeter, was natural, 
notwithstanding the opposite character of the two kinds of poetry; 
for this common organ of dramatic colloquy was capable of the 
most various treatment, and was modified by the comic poets in 
a manner most suitable to their object. The avoidance of spon- 
dees, the congregation of short syllables, and the variety of the 
czesuras, impart to the verse of comedy an extraordinary light- 
ness and spirit, and the admixture of anapezests in all feet but the 
last, opposed as this is to the fundamental form of the trimeter, 
proves that the careless, voluble recitation of comedy treated 
the long and short syllables with greater freedom than the tragic 
art permitted. In order to distinguish the different styles and 
tunes, comedy employed, besides the trimeter, a great variety of 
metres, which we must suppose were also distinguished by different 
sorts of gesticulation and delivery, such as the light trochaic te- 
trameter so well suited to the dance, the lively iambic tetra- 
meter, and the anapzestic tetrameter, flaunting along in comic 
pathos, which had been used by Aristoxenus of Selinus, an old 
Sicilian poet, who lived before Epicharmus. 

In all these things comedy was just as inventive and refined 
as tragedy. Aristophanes had the skill to convey by his rhythms 
sometimes the tone of romping merriment, at others that of 
vestal dignity ; and often in jest he would give to his verses and 
his words such a pomp of sound that we lament he is not in 
earnest. In reading his plays we are always impressed with 
the finest concord between form and meaning, between the tone 
of the speech and the character of the persons ; as, for example, 
the old, hot-headed Acharnians admirably express their rude 





1 For the sake of brevity, we merely refer to Hephestion, cap. xv. p. 83 foll, 
Gaisf. and Terentianus, v. 2243. 
Aristophanis ingens micat sollertia, 
Qui sepe metris multiformibus novis 
Archilochon arte est emulatus musica. Comp. above, chap. XI. § 8. 


Wer. If, c 


18 ORIGIN AND STRUCTURE OF THE OLD COMEDY. 


vigour and boisterous impetuosity in the Cretic metres which 
prevail in the choral songs of the piece. 

But who could with a few words paint the peculiar instrument 
which comedy had formed for itself from the language of the 
day? It was based, on the whole, upon the common con- 
versational language of the Athenians,—the Attic dialect, as it 
was current in their colloquial intercourse; comedy expresses 
this not only more purely than any other kind of poetry, but 
even more so than the old Attic prose:' but this every day col- 
loquial language is an extraordinarily flexible and rich instru- 
ment, which not only contains in itself a fulness of the most 

energetic, vivid, pregnant, and graceful forms of expression, but 
can even accommodate itself to the different species of language 
and style, the epic, the lyric, or the tragic ; and, by this means, 
impart a special colouring to itself? But, most of all, it gained 
a peculiar comic charm from its parodies of tragedy; here a 
word, a form slightly altered, or pronounced with the peculiar 
tragical accent, often sufficed to recal the recollection of a pa-— 
thetic scene in some tragedy, and so to produce a ludicrous 
contrast. 





1 We only remind the reader that the connexions of consonants which distin- 
guish Attic Greek from its mother dialect the Ionic, rr for oo, and ῥῥ for ps, occur 
every where in Aristophanes, and even in the fragments of Cratinus, but are not 
found in Thucydides any more than in the tragedians ; although even Pericles is 
said to have used these un-Ionic forms on the bema. Eustathius on the /liad, 
x. 385, p. 813. In other respects, too, the prose of Thucydides has far more epic 
and Ionic gravity and unction than the poetry of Aristophanes,—even in particular 
forms and expressions. 

2 Plutarch very justly remarks, (Aristoph. et Menandri comp. 1,) that the diction 
of Aristophanes contains all styles, from the tragic and pathetic (ὄγκος) to the 
vulgarisms of farce, (σπερμολογία καὶ φλυαρία ;) but he is wrong in maintaining 
that Aristophanes assigned these modes of speaking to his characters arbitrarily 
and at random, 


19 


CHAPTER XXVIII. 


ARISTOPHANES. 


§ 1. Events of the life of Aristophanes ; the mode of his first appearance. ὃ 2. His 
dramas: the Detaleis ; the Babylonians ; § 3. the Acharnians analyzed ; § 4. the 
Knights ; ὃ 5. the Clouds ; ὃ 6. the Wasps; ὃ 7. the Peace; ὃ 8. the Birds; 
§ 9. the Lysistrata ; Thesmophoriazuse ; ὃ το. the Frogs; ὃ 11. the Ecclesia- 
zuse ; the second Plutus. Transition to the middle comedy. 

§ 1. RISTOPHANES, the son of Philippus, was born at 

Athens about Ol. 82. B.c. 452.’ We should know more 
about the events of his life had the works of his rivals been pre- 
served ; for it is natural to suppose that he was satirized in them, 
much in the same way as he has attacked Cratinus and Eupolis 
in his own comedies. As it is, we can only assert that he 
passed over to Aigina with his family, together with other Attic 
citizens, as a Cleruchus or colonist, when that island was 
cleared of its old inhabitants, and that he became possessed of 
some landed property there.’ 

The life of Aristophanes was so early devoted to the comic 
stage, that we cannot mistake a strong natural tendency on his 
part for this vocation. He. brought out his first: comedies at so 
early an age that he was prevented (if not by law, at all events 
by the conventions of society) from allowing them to appear 
under his own name. It is to be observed that at Athens the 
state gave itself no trouble to inquire who was really the author 
of a drama: this was no subject for an official examination ; 





1 Τὸ is clearly an exaggeration when the Schol. on the Frogs, 504, calls Aris- 
tophanes σχεδὸν μειρακίσκος, i.e, about 18 years old, when he first came forward as 
a dramatist. If such were the case, he would have been at his prime in his 20th 
year, and would have ceased to compose at the aye of 56. In the pieces of Ari- 
stophanes we discern indications of advanced age, and we therefore assume that 
he was at least 25 years old at the time of his first appearance as a comic poet, 
(B.C. 427.) 

2See Aristoph. Acharn. 652; Vita Aristoph. p. 14; Kiister, and Theagenes 
quoted by the Schol. on Plat. Apol. p. 93, 8, (p. 331, Bekk.) The Acharnians 
was no doubt brought out by Callistratus ; but it is clear that the passage quoted 
above referred the public to the poet himself, who was already well known to his 
audience. 

C2 


20 ARISTOPHANES. 


but the magistrate presiding over any Dionysian festival at 
which the people were to be entertained with new dramas,’ gave 
any chorus-teacher who offered to instruct the chorus and actors 
for a new drama the authority for so doing, whenever he had 
the necessary confidence in him. The comic poets, as well as 
the tragic, were professedly chorus-teachers, (χοροδιδάσκαλοι, 
or, as they specially called themselves, κωμῳδοδιδάσκαλοι;) and 
in all official proceedings, such as assigning and bestowing the 
prize, the state only inquired who had taught the chorus, and 
thereby brought the new piece before the public. The comic 
poets likewise retained for a longer period a custom, which 
Sophocles was the first to discontinue on the tragic stage, that 
the poet and chorus-teacher should also appear as the profa- 
gonist or chief actor in his own piece. ‘This will explain what 
Aristophanes says in the paradasis of the Clouds, that his muse 
at first exposed her children, because, as a maiden, she dared 
not acknowledge their birth, and that another damsel had taken 
them up as her own; while the public, which could not be long 
in recognizing the real author, had nobly brought up and edu- 
cated the foundlings.? Aristophanes handed over his earlier 
pieces, and some of the later ones too, either to Philonides or 
to Callistratus, two chorus-teachers, with whom he was intimate, 
and who were at the same time poets and actors; and these 
persons produced them on the stage. The ancient grammarians 
state that he transferred to Callistratus the political dramas, 
and to Philonides those which related to private life.’ It was 
these persons who applied for the chorus from the archon, who 
produced the piece on the stage, and, if it was successful, re- 
ceived the prize, of which we have several examples in the 
didascalize ; in fact, everything was done as if they had been 
the real authors, although the discriminating public could not 
have failed to discover whether the real author of the piece was 





1 At the great Dionysia, the first archon ; (ὁ ἄρχων as he was emphatically called ;) 
at the Lenza, the basileus, or king archon. 

* Compare the Knights, 513, where he says that many considered he had too 
long abstained from χορὸν αἰτεῖν καθ᾽ ἑαυτόν. In the parabasis of the Wasps, 
he compares himself to a ventriloquist who had before spoken through others. 

8 So the anonym. de comedia apud Kiister. The Vita Aristophanis has the 
contrary statement, but merely from an error, as is shown by various examples. 


DRAMAS OF ARISTOPITANES. ya | 


the newly-risen genius of Aristophanes or the well-known and 
hacknied Callistratus. 

§ 2. The ancients themselves did not know whether Philo- 
nides or Callistratus brought out the Detaleis, the first of his 
plays, which was performed in Ol. 88, 1. B.c. 427.’ The 
Feasters, who formed the chorus in this piece, were conceived 
as a company of revellers who had banqueted in a temple of 
Hercules, (in whose worship eating and drinking bore a promi- 
nent part,’?) and were engaged in witnessing a contest between 
the old frugal and modest system of education and the frivolous 
and talkative education of modern times, in the persons of two 
young men, Temperate (σώφρων) and Profligate (καταπύγων). 
Brother Profligate was represented, in a dialogue between him 
and his aged father, as a despiser of Homer, as accurately 
acquainted with legal expressions, (in order, of course, to em- 
ploy them in pettifogging quibbles,) and as a zealous partizan of 
the sophist Thrasymachus, and of Alcibiades the leader of the 
frivolous youth of the day. In his riper years, Aristophanes 
completed in the Clouds what he had attempted in this early 
play. 

The second play of Aristophanes was the Babylonians, and 
was brought out Ol. 88, 2, B.c. 426, under the name of Callis- 
tratus. This was the first piece in which Aristophanes adopted 
the bold step of making the people themselves, in their pubhe 
functions, and with their measures for ensuring the public good, 
the subject of his comedy. He takes credit to himself, in the 
parabasis of the Acharnians, for having detected the tricks 
which the Athenians allowed foreigners, and especially foreign 
ambassadors, to play upon them, by lending too willing an ear to 
their flatteries and misrepresentations. He also maintains that 
he has shown how democratic constitutions fall into the power 
of demagogues; and that he has thereby gained a great name 
with the allies, and, as he says, with humorous rhodomontade, 
at the court of the Great King himself. The name of the piece 





E Schol. on the Clouds, 531. 

2 Miiller’s Dorians, II. 12. ὃ το. 

3. Τὴ the important fragment preserved by Galen Ἱπποκράτους γχῶσσαι Proemium, 
which has been recently freed from some corruptions which disfigured it. See 
Dindorf Aristoph. Fragmenta. Deetal. 1. 


~ 


22 ARISTOPHANES. 


is obviously connected with this. We infer from the statements 
of the old grammarians,' that the Babylonians who formed the 
chorus, were represented as common labourers in the mills, the 
lowest sort of slaves at Athens, who were branded, and were 
forced to work in the mills by way of punishment ; and that they 
passed themselves off as Babylonians, i. e., as ambassadors from 
Babylon. 

By this it was presumed that Babylon had revolted against 
the great king, who was constantly at war with Athens; and 
Aristophanes thought that the credulous Athenians might easily 
be gulled into the belief of something of the kind. The play 
would therefore be nearly related to that scene in the Achar- 
nians, in which the supposed ambassadors of the Persian 
monarch make their appearance, though the one cannot be con- 
sidered as a mere repetition of the other. Of course, these 
fictitious Babylonians were represented as a cheat practised 
on the Athenian Demus by the demagogues, who were then 
(after the death of Pericles) at the head of affairs; and Aristo- 
phanes had made Cleon the chief butt for his witty attacks. 
This comedy was performed at the splendid festival of the great 
Dionysia, in the presence of the allies and a number of stran- 
gers who were then at Athens; and we may see, from Cleon’s 
earnest endeavours to revenge himself on the poet, how severely 
the powerful demagogue smarted under the attack made upon 
him. He dragged Callistratus’? before the council of the Five 





1 See especially Hesychius on the verse: Σαμίων ὁ δῆμος ὡς πολυγράμματος: ‘these 
are the words of one of the characters in Aristophanes,’ says Hesychius, ‘when he 
sees the Babylonians from the mill, being astonished at their appearance, and not 
knowing what to make of it.” The verse was clearly spoken by some one, who 
was looking at the chorus without knowing what they were intended to represent, 
and who mistook them for Samians branded by Pericles, so that πολυγράμματος 
contains a direct allusion to the invention of letters by the Samians. That these 
Babylonians were intended to represent mill-slaves appears to stand in connexion 
with the fact that Hucrates, a demagogue powerful at that very time, possessed 
mills. (Aristoph. Knights, 254.) 'The piece, however, seems to have been directed 
chiefly against Cleon. 

*? We say Cailistratus, because, as χοροδιδάσκαλος and protagonist in the Achar- 
nians, he acted the part of Diczopolis, and because the public could not fail to 
understand the words αὐτός τ᾽ ἐμαυτὸν ὑπὸ Κλέωνος ἃ παθον, ἐπίσταμαι, v. 377 foll., 
as spoken of the performer himself.. In the ποιητὴς of the parabasis in the Achar- 
nians we do not hesitate to recognise Aristophanes, whose talents could not have 
remained unknown to the public for three years. 


‘ 


ANALYSIS OF THE ACHARNIANS. v3 


Hundred, (which, as a supreme tribunal, had also the superin- 
tendence of the festival amusements,) and overwhelmed him with 
reproaches and threats. With regard to Aristophanes himself, 
it is probable that Cleon made an indirect attempt to bring him 
into danger by an indictment against him for assuming the rights 
of a citizen without being entitled to them (γραφὴ ξενίας). 
There is no doubt that the poet successfully repelled the charge, 
and victoriously asserted his civic rights.’ 

§ 3. In the following year, (Ol. 88, 3. B.c. 425,) at the 
Lena, Aristophanes brought out the Acharnians, the earliest 
of his extant dramas. Compared with most of his plays, the 
Acharnians is a harmless piece: its chief object is to depict the 
earnest longing for a peaceful country life on the part of those 
Athenians who took no pleasure in the babbling of the market- 
place, and had been driven into the city against their will by the 
military plans of Pericles. Along with this, a few lashes are 
administered to the demagogues, who, like Cleon, had inflamed 
the martial propensities of the people, and to the generals, who, 
like Lamachus, had shown far too great a love for the war. 
We have also in this play an early specimen of his literary 
criticism, directed against Euripides, whose overwrought at- 
tempts to move the feelings, and the vulgar shrewdness with 
which he had invested the old heroes, were highly offensive to 
our poet. In this play we have at once all the peculiar cha- 
racteristics of the Aristophanic comedy ;—his bold and genial 
originality, the lavish abundance of highly comic scenes with 
which he has filled every part of his piece, the surprising and 
striking delineation of character which expresses a great deal 
with a few master-touches, the vivid and plastic power with 
which the scenes are arranged, the ease with which he has dis- 
posed of all difficulties of space and time. Indeed, the play 
possesses its author’s peculiar characteristics in such perfection 
and completeness, that it may be proper in this place to give such 
an analysis of this, the oldest extant comedy, as may serve to 
illustrate not merely the general ideas, which we have already 





1 Schol. Acharn. 377. It was on this occasion, according to the author of the 
Vita Aristophanis, that Aristophanes quoted that verse of Homer, (Odyss. 1. 216,) 
οὐ γάρ πώ τις ἑὸν γόνον αὐτὸς ἀνέγνω. 


94 ARISTOPHANES. 


given, but also the whole plot and technical arrangement of the 
drama. Ἷ 

The stage in this play represents sometimes town and some- 
times country, and was probably so arranged that both were 
shown upon it at once. When the comedy begins, the stage 
gives us a glimpse of the Pnyz, or place of public assembly ; 
that is to say, the spectator saw the dema for the orator cut 
out of the rock, and around it some seats and other objects 
calculated to recal the recollection of the well-known place. 
Here sits the worthy Diczopolis, a citizen of the old school, 
grumbling about his fellow citizens, who do not come punctually 
to the Pnyx, but lounge idly about the market-place, which is 
seen from thence; for his own part, although he has no love for — 
a town-life, with its bustle and gossip, he attends the assembly 
regularly in order to speak for peace. On a sudden the Prytanes 
come out of the council-house ; the people rush in; a well-born 
Athenian, Amphitheus, who boasts of having been destined by 
the gods to conclude a peace with Sparta, is dismissed with the 
utmost contempt, in spite of the efforts of Diczeopolis on his 
behalf; and then, to the great delight of the war party, ambas- 
sadors are introduced, who have returned from Persia, and have 
brought with them a Persian messenger, ‘ the Great King’s eye,’ 
with his retinue: this forms a fantastic procession, which, as 
Aristophanes hints, is all a trick and imposture, got up by the 
demagogues of the war party. Other ambassadors bring a 
similar messenger from Sitalces, king of Thrace, on whose assist- 
ance the Athenians of the day built a great deal, and drag before 
the assembly a miserable rabble, under the name of picked 
Odomantian troops, which the Athenians are to take into their 
service for very high pay. Meanwhile Diczopolis, seeing that 
he cannot turn affairs into another channel, has sent Amphi- 
theus to Sparta on his own account; the messenger returns in 
a few minutes with various treaties, (some for a longer, others 
for a shorter time,) in the form of wine-jars, like those which 
were used for pouring out libations on the conclusion of a treaty 
of peace ; Diczopolis selects a thirty years’ truce by sea and 
land, which does not smell of pitch and tar, like a short armis- 
tice, in which there is only just time to calk the ships. All 
these delightful scenes are possible only in a comedy like that 


ANALYSIS OF THE ACHARNIANS. 95 


of the Athenians, which has its outward form for the repre- 
sentation of every relation, every function, and every character ; 
which is able to sketch everything in bold colours by means of 
grotesque speaking figures, and does not trouble itself with con- 
fining the activity of these figures to the laws of reality and the 
probabilities of actual life.’ 

The first dramatic complication which Aristophanes intro- 
duces into his plot, arises from the chorus, which consists of 
Acharnians, i.e., the inhabitants of a large village of Attica, 
where the people gained a livelihood chiefly by charcoal-burn- 
ing, the materials of which were supplied by the neighbouring 
mountain-forests: they are represented as rude, robust old 
fellows, hearts of oak, martial by their disposition, and especially 
incensed against the Peloponnesians, who had destroyed all the 
vineyards in their first invasion of Attica. These old Acharnians 
at first appear in pursuit of Amphitheus, who, they hear, has gone 
to Sparta to bring treaties of peace: in his stead, they fall in with 
Diceopolis, who is engaged in celebrating the festival of the 
country Dionysia, here represented as an abstract of every sort 
of rustic merriment and jollity, from which the Athenians at 
that time were debarred. The chorus no sooner learns from 
the phallus-song of Diczopolis, that he is the person who has 
sent for the treaties, than they fall upon him in the greatest 
rage, refuse to hear a word from him, and are going to stone 
him to death without the least compunction, when Diczopolis 
seizes a charcoal-basket, and threatens to punish it as a hostage 
for all that the Acharnians do to himself. The charcoal-basket, 
which the Acharnians needed for their every-day occupations, is 
so dear to their hearts that they are willing, for its sake, to 
listen to Diczopolis; especially as he has promised to speak 
with his head on a block, on condition that he shall be be- 
headed at once if he fails in his defence. All this is amusing 
enough in itself, but becomes additionally ludicrous when we 
remember that the whole of Diczeopolis’s behaviour is an imita- 





’ 1Jn all this, comedy does but follow in its own way the spirit of ancient art in 
general, which went far beyond modern art in finding an outward expression for 
every thought and feeling of the mind, but fell short of that art in keeping up an 
appearance of consistency in the employment of these forms, as the laws of actual 
life would have required. 


26 ARISTOPHANES. 


tion of one of the heroes of Euripides, the rhetorical and plain- 
tive Telephus, who snatched the infant Orestes from his cradle 
and threatened to put him to death, unless Agamemnon would 
listen to him, and was exposed to the same danger when he 
spoke before the Achzeans as Dicopolis is when he argues with 
the Acharnians. Aristophanes pursues this parody still farther, 
as it furnishes him with the means of exaggerating the situation 
of Diczopolis in a very comic manner; Diceopolis applies to 
Euripides himself, (who is shown to the spectators by means of 
an eccyclema, in his garret, surrounded by masks and costumes, 
such as he was fond of employing for his tragic heroes,) and 
begs of him the most piteous of his dresses, upon which he 
obtains the most deplorable of them all, that of Telephus. We 
pass over other mockeries of Euripides, in which Aristophanes 
indulges from pure wantonness, and turn to the following scene, 
one of the chief scenes in the piece, in which Diczopolis, in 
the character of a comic Telephus, and with his head over the 
block, pleads for peace with the Spartans. It is obvious, that 
however seriously Aristophanes embraced the cause of the peace- 
party, he does not on this occasion speak one word in serious 
earnest. He derives the whole Peloponnesian war from a bold 
frolic on the part of some drunken young men, who had carried 
off a harlot from Megara, in reprisal for which the Megarians 
had seized on some of the attendants of Aspasia. As this 
explanation is not satisfactory, and the chorus even summons 
to its assistance the warlike Lamachus, who rushes from his 
house in extravagant military costume,’ Diczeopolis is driven to 
have recourse to argumenta ad hominem, and he impresses on the 
old people who form the chorus, that they are obliged to serve 
as common soldiers, while young braggadocios, like Lamachus, 
made a pretty livelihood by serving as generals or ambassadors, 
and so wasted the fat of the land. This produces its effect, and 
the chorus shows an inclination to do justice to Diczeopolis. 
This catastrophe of the piece is followed by the parabasis, in 





1 Consequently, the house was also represented on the stage; probably the town 
house of Diczopolis was in the middle, on the one side that of Euripides, on the other 
that of Lamachus, On the left was the place which represented the Pnyx; on the 
right some indication of a country house: this, however, occurs only in the scene 
of the country Dionysia, all the rest takes place in the city. 


ANALYSIS OF THE ACHARNIANS. 27 


the first part of which the poet, with particular reference to his 
last play, takes credit to himself for being an estimable friend 
to the people; he says that he does not indeed spare them, 
but that they need not fear, for that he will be just in his satire.’ 
The second part, however, keeps close to the thought which 
Diczeopolis had awakened in the minds of the chorus ; they com- 
plain bitterly of the assumption of their rights by the clever, 
witty, and ready young men, from whom they could not defend 
themselves, especially in the law-courts. 

Thesecond part of the piece,after the catastrophe and parabasis, 
is merely a description, overflowing with wit and humour, of the 
blessings which peace has conferred on the sturdy Diczopolis. 
At first he opens his free market, which is visited in succession 
by a poor starving wretch from Megara, (the neighbouring 
country to Attica, which, poorly gifted by nature, had suffered 
in the most shocking manner from the Athenian blockade and 
the yearly devastations of its territory,) and by a stout Boeotian 
from the fertile land on the shore of the Copaic lake, which 
was well known to the Athenians for its eels. For want of 
other wares, the Megarian has dressed up his little daughters 
like young pigs, and the honest Diczopolis is willing to buy 
them as such, though he is strangely surprised by some of their 
peculiarities ;—a purely ludicrous scene, which was based, per- 
haps, on the popular jokes of the Athenians; a Megarian 
would gladly sell his children as little pigs, if any one would 
take them off his hands :—we could point out many jokes of 
this kind in the popular life, as well of ancient as of modern 
times. During this, the dealers are much troubled by syco- 
phants, a race who lived by indictments, and were especially 
active in hunting for violations of the customs’ laws ;? they 
want to seize on the foreign goods as contraband, but Diczopolis 
makes short work with them: one of the sycophants he drives 
away from his market ; the other, the little Nicarchus, he binds 





ly. 655, ἀλλ᾽ ὑμεῖς μή ποτε δείσηθ᾽ ὡς κωμῳδήσει τὰ δίκαια. When we find such 
open professions as this, we may at least be certain that Aristophanes intended 
to direct the sting of his comedy against that only which appeared to him to be 
really bad. 

2 The sycophants, no doubt, derived their names from a sort of φάσις, 1.6. 
public information against those who injured the state in any of its pecuniary 
interests. 


28 ARISTOPHANES. 


up in a bundle, and packs him on the back of the Beeotian, who 
shows a desire to take him away asa laughable little monkey. 

Now begins, on a sudden, the Athenian feast of the pitchers 
(the Χόες). Lamachus' in vain sends to Diceopolis for some 
of his purchases, in order that he may keep the feast merrily ; 
the good citizen keeps every thing to himself, and the chorus, 
which is now quite converted, admires the prudence of Diczo- 
polis, and the happiness he has gained by it. In the midst of 
his preparations for a sumptuous banquet, others beg for some 
share of his peace; he returns a gruff answer to a countryman 
whose cattle have been harried by the Beeotians ; but he behaves 
a little more civilly to a bride who wants to keep her husband at 
home. Meanwhile, various messages are brought ; to Lamachus, 
that he must march against the Beotians, who are going to 
make an inroad into Attica at the time of the feast of the. 
Choes ; to Diczeopolis, that he must go to the priest of Bacchus, 
in order to assist him in celebrating the feast of the Choes. 
Aristophanes works out this contrast in a very amusing manner, 
by making Diczopolis parody every word which Lamachus utters 
as he is preparing for war, so as to transfer it to his own 
festivities ; and when, after a short time which the chorus fills 
up by a satirical song, Lamachus is brought back from the war 
wounded, and supported by two servants, Diceeopolis meets him 
in a happy state of intoxication, and leaning on two damsels of 
easy virtue, and so celebrates his triumph over the wounded 
warrior in a very conspicuous manner. 

To say nothing of the pithy humonr of the style, and the 
beautiful rhythms and happy turns of the choral songs, it must 
be allowed that this series of scenes has been devised with 
genial merriment from beginning to end, and that they must 
have produced a highly comic effect, especially if the scenéry, 
costumes, dances, and music were worthy of the conceptions 
aud language of the poet. The piece, if correctly understood, 
is nothing but a Bacchic revelry, full of farce and wantonness ; 
for although the conception of it may rest upon a moral founda- 





1 That Lamachus is only a representative of the warlike spirits is clear from his 
name, Aa-yaxos: otherwise, Phormio, Demosthenes, Paches, and other Athenian 
heroes might just as well have been substituted for him. 


ANALYSIS OF THE KNIGHTS. 29 


tion, yet the author is, throughout the piece, utterly devoid of 
seriousness and sobriety, and in every representation, as well of 
the victorious as of the defeated party, follows the impulses of 
an unrestrained love of mirth. At most, Aristophanes expresses 
his own sentiments in the parabasis: in the other parts of the 
play we cannot safely recognize the opinions of the poet in the 
deceitful mirror of his comedy. 

§ 4. The following year (Ol. 88, 4. B.c. 424) is distinguished 
in the history of comedy by the appearance of the Knights of 
Aristophanes. It was the first piece which Aristophanes brought 
out in his own name, and he was induced by peculiar circum- 
stances to appear in it as an actor himself. This piece is en- 
tirely directed against Cleon; not, like the Babylonians, and at 
a later period the Wasps, against certain measures of his policy, 
but against his entire proceedings and influence as a demagogue. 
There is a certain degree of spirit in attacking, even under the 
protection of Bacchic revelry, a popular leader who was mighty 
by the very principle of his policy, viz. of advancing the material 
interests and immediate advantage of the great mass of the people 
at the sacrifice of everything else; and who had become still 
more formidable by the system of terrorism with which he carried 
out his views. This system consisted in throwing all the citizens 
opposed to him under the suspicion of being concealed aris- 
tocrats; in the indictments which he brought against his ene- 
mies, and which his influence with the law courts enabled him 
without difficulty to turn to his own advantage; and in the 
terrible severity with which he urged the Athenians in the public 
assembly and in the courts to put down all movements hostile 
to the rule of the democracy, and of which his proposal to 
massacre the Mitylenzans is the most striking example. 
Besides, at the very time when Aristophanes composed the 
Knighis, Cleon’s reputation had attained its highest pitch, for 
fortune in her sport had realized his inconsiderate boast, that it 
would be an easy matter for him to capture the Spartans in 
Sphacteria; the triumph of having captured these formidable 
warriors, for which the best generals had contended in vain, had 
fallen, like an over-ripe fruit, into the lap of the unmilitary Cleon 
(in the summer of the year 425). That it really was a bold 
measure to attack the powerful demagogue at this time, may 


30 ARISTOPHANES. 


also be inferred from the statement that no one would make a 
mask of Cleon for the poet, and still less appear in the character 
of Cleon, so that Aristophanes was obliged to undertake the 
part himself. 

The Knights is by far the most violent and angry production 
of the Aristophanic Muse ; that which has most of the bitterness 
of Archilochus, and least of the harmless humour and riotous 
merriment of the Dionysia. In this instance comedy almost 
transgresses its proper limits; it is almost converted into an 
arena for political champions fighting for life and death; the 
most violent party animosity is combined with some obvious 
traces of personal irritation, which is justified by the judicial 
persecution of the author of the Babylonians. The piece pre- 
sents a remarkable contrast to the Acharnians ; just as if the 
poet wanted to show that a checkered variety of burlesque 
scenes was not necessary to his comedy, and that he could pro- 
duce the most powerful effect by the simplest means; and 
doubtless, to an audience perfectly familiar with all the hints 
and allusions of the comedian, the Knights must have pos- 
sessed still greater interest than the Acharnians, though modern 
readers, far removed from the times, have not been always able 
to resist the feeling of tediousness produced by the prolix scenes 
of the piece. The number of characters is small and unpre- 
tending; the whole dramatis persone consist of an old master 
with three slaves, (one of whom, a Paphlagonian, completely 
governs his master,) and a sausage-seller. The old master, 
however, is the Demus of Athens, the slaves are the Athenian 
generals Nicias and Demosthenes, and the Paphlagonian is 
Cleon : the sausage-seller alone is a fiction of the poet’s,—a rude, 
uneducated, impudent fellow, from the dregs of the people, 
who is set up against Cleon in order that he may, by his 
audacity, bawl down Cleon’s impudence, and so drive the 
formidable demagogue out of the field in the only way that is 
possible. Even the chorus has nothing imaginary about it, but 
consists of the Knights of the State,’ i.e. of citizens who, ac- 





1 Hardly of actual knights, so that in this case reality and the drama were one 
and the same. That no phyle, but the state paid the expenses of this chorus (it 
we are so to explain δημοσίᾳ in the didascalia of the piece: see the examples in 


ANALYSIS OF THE KNIGHTS. 31 


cording to Solon’s classification, which still subsisted, paid taxes 
according to the rating of a knight’s property, and most of 
whom at the same time still served as cavalry in time of 
war:' being the most numerous portion of the wealthier and 
better educated class, they could not fail to have a decided 
antipathy to Cleon, who had put himself at the head of the 
mechanics and poorer people. We see that in this piece Aris- 
tophanes lays all the stress on the political tendency, and con- 
siders the comic plot rather as a form and dress than as the 
body and primary part of his play. The allegory, which is 
obviously chosen only to cover the sharpness of the attack, is 
cast over it only like a thin veil; according to his own pleasure, 
the poet speaks of the affairs of the Demus sometimes as matters 
of family arrangement, sometimes as public transactions. 

The whole piece has the form of a contest. The sausage- 
seller (in whom an oracle, which has been stolen from the 
Paphlagonian while he was sleeping, recognises his victorious 
opponent) first measures his strength against him in a display 
of impudence and rascality, by which the poet assumes that of 
the qualities requisite to the demagogue these are the most 
essential. The sausage-seller narrates that having, while a 
boy, stolen a piece of meat and boldly denied the theft, a 
statesman had predicted that the city would one day trust itself 
to his guidance. After the parabasis, the contest begins afresh ; 
the rivals, who had in the meantime endeavoured to recommend 
themselves to the council, come before Demus himself, who 
takes his seat on the Pnyx, and sue for the favour of the childish 
old man. Combined with serious reproaches directed against 
Cleon’s whole system of policy, we have a number of joking 
contrivances, as when the sausage-seller places a cushion under 
the Demus, in order that he may not gall that which sat by the 
oar at Salamis.” The contest at last turns upon the oracles, to 
which Cleon used to appeal in his public speeches (and we know 





Boéckh’s Public Economy of Athens, book iii. § 22, at the end,) is no ground for the 
former inference. 

1 That Aristophanes considers the knights as a class is pretty clear from their 
known political tendency ; as part of the Athenian army, he often describes them as 
sturdy young men, fond of horsemanship, and dressed in grand military costume. 

2 ἵνα μὴ τρίβῃς τὴν ἐν Σαλαμῖνι. ν. 785. 


32 ARISTOPHANES. 


from Thucydides’ how much the people were influenced through- 
out the Peloponnesian war by the oracles and predictions attri- 
buted to the ancient prophets); in this. department, too, the 
sausage-seller outbids his rival by producing announcements of 
the greatest comfort to the Demus, and ruin to his opponent. 
As a merry supplement to these long-spun transactions, we have 
a scene which must have been highly entertaining to eye and 
ear alike: the Paphlagonian and the sausage-seller sit down as 
eating-house keepers (κάπηλοι) at two tables, on which a number 
of hampers and eatables are set out, and bring one article after 
the other to the Demus with ludicrous recommendations of their 
excellences ;* in this, too, the sausage-seller of course pays his 
court to the Demus more successfully than his rival. After a 
second parabasis we see the Demus—whom the sausage-seller 
has restored to youth by boiling him in his kettle, as Medea did 
Aison—in youthful beauty, but attired in the old-fashioned 
splendid costume, shining with peace and contentment, and in his 
new state of mind heartily ashamed of his former absurdities. 

§ 5. In the following year we find Aristophanes (after a fresh 
suit® in which Cleon had involved him) bringing out the Clouds, 
and so entering upon an entirely new field of comedy. He had 
himself made up his mind to take a new and peculiar flight 
with this piece. The public, and the judges, however, deter- 
mined otherwise; it was not Aristophanes but the aged Cra- 
tinus who obtained the first prize. The young poet, who had 
believed himself secure against such a slight, uttered some warm 
reproaches against the public in his next play ; he was induced, 
however, by this decision to revise his piece, and it is this 
rifaccimento (which deviates considerably from the original 
form) that has come down to us.’ 





1 Thucyd. ii. 54. viii. 1. 

2 The two eating-houses are represented by an eccyclema, as is clear cam the 
conclusion of the scene. 

ὃ. See the Wasps, v. 1284. According to the Vita Aristoph. the poet had to 
stand three suits from Cleon touching his rights as a citizen. 

4 The first Clouds had, according to a definite tradition, a different parabasis; it 
wanted the contest of the δίκαιος and ἄδικος λόγος, and the burning of the school at 
the end. Itis also probable, from Diog. Laért. ii. 18, (notwithstanding all the 
confusions which he has made,) that in the first Clouds, Socrates was brought into 
connexion with Euripides, and was declared to have had a share in the tragedies of 
the latter. 


ANALYSIS OF THE CLOUDS. oo 


There is hardly any work of antiquity which it is so difficult 
to estimate as the Clouds of Aristophanes. Was Socrates really, 
perhaps only in the earlier part of his career, the fantastic 
dreamer and sceptical sophist which this piece makes him? 
And if it is certain that he was not, is not Aristophanes a 
common slanderer, a buffoon, who, in the vagaries of his 
humour, presumes to attack and revile even what is purest 
and noblest? Where remains his solemn promise never to 
make what was right the object of his comic satire ? 

If there be any way of justifying the character of Aristo- 
phanes, as it appears to us in all his dramas, even in this hostile 
encounter with the noblest of philosophers, we must not attempt, 
as some modern writers have done, to convert Aristophanes into 
a profound philosopher, opposed to Socrates; but we must be 
content to recognise in him, even on this occasion, the vigilant 
patriot, the well-meaning citizen of Athens, whose object it is 
by all the means in his power to promote the interests of his 
native country so far as he is capable of understanding them. 

As the piece in general is directed against the new system 
of education, we must first of all explain its nature and ten- 
dency. Up to the time of the Persian war, the school-education 
of the Greeks was limited to a very few subjects. From his 
seventh year, the boy was sent to schools in which he learned 
reading and writing, to play on the lute and sing, and the usual 
routine of gymnastic exercises. In these schools it was cus- 
tomary to impress upon the youthful mind, in addition to these 
acquirements, the works of the poets, especially Homer, as the 
foundation of all Greek training, the religious and moral songs ~ 
of the lyric poets, and a modest and decent behaviour. This 
instruction ceased when the youth was approaching to manhood ; 
then the only means of gaining instruction was intercourse with 
older men, listening to what was said in the market-place, where 
the Greeks spent a large portion of the day, taking a part in 
public life, the poetic contests, which were connected with the 
religious festivals, and made generally known so many works of 
genius ; and, as far as bodily training was concerned, frequenting 
the gymnasia kept up at the public expense. Such was the 





1 és γραμματιστοῦ, és κιθαριστοῦ, és παιδοτρίβου. 


Vou. IT. D 


34 ARISTOPHANES. 


method of education up to the Persian war; and no effect was 
produced upon it by the more ancient systems of philosophy, 
any more than by the historical writings of the period, for no 
one ever thought of seeking the elements of a regular education 
‘from Heraclitus or Pythagoras, but whoever applied himself to 
them did so for his life. With the Persian war, however, 
according to an important observation of Aristotle,’ an entirely 
new striving after knowledge and education developed itself 
among the Greeks; and subjects of instruction were established, 
which soon exercised an important influence on the whole spirit 
and character of the nation. The art of speaking, which had 
hitherto afforded exercise only to practical life and its avocations, 
now became a subject of school-training, in connexion with 
various branches of knowledge, and with ideas and views of 
various kinds, such as seemed suitable to the design of guiding 
and ruling men by eloquence. All this taken together, con- 
stituted the lessons of the Sophists, which we shall contemplate 
more nearly hereafter; and which produced more important 
effects on the education and morals of the Greeks than any- 
thing else at that time. That the very principles of the Sophists 
must have irritated an Athenian with the views and feelings of 
Aristophanes, and have at once produced a spirit of opposition, 
is sufficiently obvious: the new art of rhetoric, always eager for 
advantages, and especially when transferred to the dangerous 
ground of the Athenian democracy and the popular law-courts, 
could not fail to be regarded by Aristophanes as a perilous in- 
strument in the hands of ambitious and selfish demagogues ; he 
saw with a glance how the very foundations of the old morality 
upon which the weal of Athens appeared to him to rest, must 
be sapped and rooted up by a stream of oratory which had the 
skill to turn everything to its own advantage. Accordingly, he 
makes repeated attacks on the whole race of the artificial orators 
and sceptical reasoners, and it is with them that he is principally 
concerned in the Clouds. 

The real object of this piece is stated by the poet himself in 


the parabasis to the Wasps, which was composed in the following — 


year: he says that he had attacked the fiend which, like a night- _ 





1 Aristot, Polit. viii. 6. 


— Δ. a 


ANALYSIS OF THE CLOUDS. 35 


mare, plagued fathers and grandfathers by night, besetting in- 
experienced and harmless people with all sorts of pleadings and 
pettifogging tricks.’ It is obvious that it is not the teachers of 
rhetoric who are alluded to here, but the young men who abused 
the facility of speaking which they had acquired in the schools 
by turning it to the ruin of their fellow citizens. The whole 
plan of the drama depends upon this: an old Athenian, who is 
sore pressed by debts and duns, first labours to acquire a 
knowledge of the tricks and stratagems of the new rhetoric, and 
finding that he is too stiff and awkward for it, sends to this 
school his youthful son, who has hitherto spent his life in the 
ordinary avocations of a well-born cavalier. The consequence 
is, that his son, being initiated into the new scepticism, turns it 
against his own father, and not only beats him, but proves that 
he has done so justly. The error of Aristophanes in identifying 
the school of Socrates with that of the new-fangled rhetoric must 
have arisen from his putting Socrates on the same footing with 
sophists like Protagoras and Gorgias, and then preferring to 
make his fellow-citizen the butt of his witticisms, rather than 
his foreign colleagues, who paid only short visits to Athens. It 
cannot be denied that Aristophanes was mistaken. It must 
indeed be allowed that Socrates, in the earlier part of his career, 
had not advanced with that security with which we see him in- 
vested in the writings of Xenophon and Plato; that he still took 
more part in the speculations of the Tonian philosophers with 
regard to the universe,? than he did at a later period; that 
certain wild elements were still mixed up in his theory, and not 
yet purged out of it by the Socratic dialectic: still it is quite 
incenceivable that Socrates should ever have kept a school of 
rhetoric (and this is the real question), in which instruction was 
given, as in those of the Sophists, how to make the worse 
appear the better reason.* But even this misrepresentation on 
the part of Aristophanes may have been undesigned: we see 





1 Compare, by way of explanation, also Acharnians, 713. Birds, 1347. Frogs, 
147. 

3 τὰ μετέωρα. 

3 The ἥττων or ἄδικος, and the κρείττων or δίκαιος λόγος. Aristophanes makes the 
former manner of speaking the representative of the assuming and arrogant youth, 
and the latter of the old respectable education, and personifies them both. 

D 2 


36 ARISTOPHANES. 


from passages of his later comedies,’ that he actually regarded 
Socrates as a rhetorician and declaimer. He was probably de- 
ceived by appearances into the belief that the dialectic of 
Socrates, the art of investigating the truth, was the same as 
the sophistry which aped it, and which was but the art of pro- 
ducing a deceitful resemblance of the truth. It is, no doubt, a 
serious reproach to Aristophanes that he did not take the 
trouble to distinguish more accurately between the two: but 
how often it happens that men, with the ~ best intentions, con- 
demn arbitrarily and in the lump those tendencies and exertions 
which they dislike or cannot appreciate. 

The whole play of the Clouds is full of ingenious ideas, such 
as the chorus of Clouds itself, which Socrates invokes, and which 
represents appropriately the light, airy, and fleeting nature οὗ 
the new philosophy.” A number of popular jokes, such as 
generally attach themselves to the learned class, and banter the 
supposed subtilties and refinements of philosophy, are here heaped 
on the school of Socrates, and often delivered in a very comic 
manner. The worthy Strepsiades, whose homebred under- 
standing and mother-wit are quite overwhelmed with astonish- 
ment at the subtle tricks of the school-philosophers, until at last 
his own experience teaches him to form a different judgment, is 
from the beginning to the end of the piece a most amusing cha- 
racter, Notwithstanding all this, however, the piece cannot 
overcome the defect arising from the oblique views on which it 
is based, and the superficial manner in which the philosophy of 
Socrates is treated,—at least not in the eyes of any one who is 
unable to surrender himself to the delusion under which Aris- 
tophanes appears to have laboured. 

§ 6. The following year (Ol. 89, 2. B.c. 422) brought the 





1 See Aristoph. Frogs, 1491. Birds, 1555. Eupolis had given a more correct — 
picture of Socrates, at least in regard to his outward appearance. Bergk de rel. 
com. Attica, p. 353. : 

? That this chorus loses its special character towards the end of the piece, — 
and even preaches reverence of the gods, is a point of resemblance between it and — 
the choruses in the Acharnians and the Wasps, who at least act rather according 
to the general character of the Greek chorus, which was on the whole the same — 
for tragedy and comedy, than according to the particular part which has been 
assigned to them. 





ANALYSIS OF THE WASPS. ad 


Wasps of Aristophanes on the stage. The Wasps is so con- 
nected with the Clouds, that it is impossible to mistake a 
similarity of design in the development of certain thoughts in 
each. The Clouds, especially in its original form, was directed 
against the young Athenians, who, as wrangling tricksters, 
vexed the simple inoffensive citizens of Athens by bringing them 
against their will into the law-courts. The Wasps is aimed at 
the old Athenians, who took their seats day after day in great 
masses as judges, and being compensated for their loss of time 
by the judicial fees established by Pericles, gave themselves up 
entirely to the decision of the causes, which had become in- 
finitely multiplied by the obligation on the allies to try their 
suits at Athens, and by the party spirit in the State itself: 
whereby these old people had acquired far too surly and snarling 
a spirit, to the great damage of the accused. There are two 
persons opposed to one another in this piece; the old Philocleon, 
who has given up the management of his affairs to his son, and 
devoted himself entirely to his office of judge (in consequence 
of which he pays the profoundest respect to Cleon, the patron 
of the popular courts) ; and his son Bdelycleon, who has a horror 
of Cleon and of the severity of the courts in general. It is 
very remarkable how entirely the course of the action between 
these two characters corresponds to that in the Clouds, so that 
we can hardly mistake the intention of Aristophanes to make 
one piece the counterpart of the other. The irony of fate, 
which the aged Strepsiades experiences, when that which had 
been the greatest object of his wishes, namely, to have his son 
thoroughly imbued with the rhetorical fluency of the Sophists, 
soon turns out to be the greatest misfortune to him,—is pre- 
cisely the same with the irony of which the young Bdelycleon is 
the object in the Wasps; for, after having directed all his 
efforts towards curing his father of his mania for the profession 
of judge, and having actually succeeded in doing so, (partly by 
establishing a private dicasterion at home, and partly by recom- 
mending to him the charms of a fashionable luxurious life, such 
as the young Athenians of rank were attached to,) he soon 
bitterly repents of the metamorphosis which he has effected, 
since the old man, by a strange mixture of his old-fashioned 
rude manners with the luxury of the day, allows his dissolute- 


38 ARISTOPHANES. 


ness to carry him much farther than Bdelycleon had either ex- 
pected or desired. 

The Wasps is undoubtedly one of the most perfect of the 
plays of Aristophanes.' We have already remarked upon the 
happy invention of the masks of the chorus.’ The same spirit 
of amusing novelty pervades the whole piece. The most farcical 
scene is the first between two dogs, which Bdelycleon sets on 
foot for the gratification of his father, and in which not only is 
the whole judicial system of the Athenians parodied in a ludi- 
crous manner, but also a particular law-suit between the dema- 
gogue Cleon and the general Laches appears in a comic contrast, 
which must have forced a laugh from the gravest of the 
spectators. 

§ 7. We have still a fifth comedy, the Peace, which is con- 
nected with the hitherto unbroken series ; it is established by a 
didascalia, which has been recently brought to light, that it was 
produced at the great Dionysia in Ol. 89, 3. B.c. 421. Accord- 
ingly, this play made its appearance on the stage shortly 
before the peace of Nicias, which concluded the first part of 
the Peloponnesian war, and, as was then fully believed, was 
destined to put a final stop to this destructive contest among 
the Greek states. 

The subject of the Peace is essentially the same as that of 
the Acharnians, except that, in the latter, peace is represented 
as the wish of an individual only, in the former as wished for 
by all. In the Acharnians, the chorus is opposed to peace; in 
the Peace, it is composed of countrymen of Attica, and all parts 
of Greece, who are full of a longing desire for peace. It must, 
however, be allowed, that in dramatic interest the Acharnians 
far excels the Peace, which is greatly wanting in the unity of 
a strong comic action. It must, no doubt, have been highly 
amusing to see how Trygzus ascends to heaven on the back of 
an entirely new sort of Pegasus—a dung beetle,—and there, 





1 We cannot by any means accept A. W. von Schlegel’s judgment, that this 
play is inferior to the other comedies of Aristophanes, and we entirely approve 
of the warm apology by Mr. Mitchell, in his edition of the Wasps, 1835, the 
object of which has unfortunately prevented the editor from giving the comedy in 
its full proportions, 


2 Chap. XXVII. § 5. 


ANALYSIS OF THE BIRDS. 39 


amidst all kinds of dangers, in spite of the rage of the demon 
of war, carries off the goddess Peace, with her fair com- 
panions, Harvesthome and Mayday:’ but the sacrifice on account 
of the peace, and the preparations for the marriage of Trygzeus 
with Harvesthome, are split up into a number of separate 
scenes, without any direct progress of the action, and without 
any great vigour of comic imagination. It is also too obvious, 
that Aristophanes endeavours to diminish the tediousness of 
these scenes by some of those loose jokes which never failed to 
produce their effect on the common people of Athens; and it 
must be allowed, in general, that the poet often expresses better 
rules in respect to his rivals than he has observed in his own 
pieces.” 

§ 8. There is now a gap of some years in the hitherto un- 
broken chain of Aristophanic comedies; but our loss is fully 
compensated by the Birds, which was brought out in Ol. ΟἹ, 
2. B.C. 414. If the Acharnians is a specimen of the youthful 
vigour of Aristophanes, it appears in the Birds displayed in all 
its splendour, and with a style, in which a proud flight of 
imagination is united with the coarsest jocularity and most 
genial humour. 

The Birds belongs to a period when the power and dominion 
of Athens had attained to an extent and grandeur which can only 
_be compared to the time about Ol. 81, 1. B.c. 456, before the 
military power of Athens was overthrown in Egypt. Athens 
had, by the very favourable peace of Nicias, strengthened her 
authority on the sea and in the coasts of Asia Minor; had 
shaken the policy of the Peloponnese by skilful intrigues; had 
brought her revenues to the highest point they ever attained ; 
and finally had formed the plan of extending her authority by 
sea and on the coasts, over the western part of the Mediterranean, 
by the expedition to Sicily, which had commenced under the most 
favourable auspices. The disposition of the Athenians at this 
period is known to us from Thucydides: they allowed their de- 





1So we venture to translate ’Orwpa and Θεωρία. 

2 Tt should’ be added, that according: to the old grammarians Eratosthenes and 
Crates, there were two plays by Aristophanes with this title, though there is no 
indication that the one which has come down to us is not that which appeared in 
the year 421. 


40 ARISTOPHANES. 


magogues and soothsayers to conjure up before them the most 
brilliant visionary prospects; henceforth nothing appeared un- 
attainable ; people gave themselves up, in general, to the intoxi- 
cation of extravagant hopes. The hero of the day was Alci- 
biades, with his frivolity, his presumption, and that union of 
a calculating understanding with a bold, unfettered imagination, 
for which he was so distinguished ; and even when he was lost 
- to Athens by the unfortunate prosecution of the Hermocopide, 
the disposition which he had excited still survived for a con- 
siderable time. 

It was at this time that Aristophanes composed his Birds. 
In order to comprehend this comedy in its connexion with the 
events of the day, and, on the other hand, not to attribute to 
it more than it really contains, it is especially necessary to take 
a rigorous and exact view of the action of the piece. Two 
Athenians, Peistheterus and Euelpides, (whom we may call 
Agitator and Hopegood,) are sick and tired of the restless life 
at Athens, and the number of law-suits there, and have wan- 
dered out into the wide world in search of Hoopoo, an old 
mythological kinsman of the Athenians.’ They soon find him 
in a rocky desert, where the whole host of birds assemble at 
the call of Hoopoo: for some time they are disposed to treat 
the two strangers of human race as national enemies; but are 
at last induced, on the recommendation of Hoopoo, to give 
them a hearing. Upon this, Agitator lays before them his 
grand ideas about the primeval sovereignty of the birds, the 
important rights and privileges they have lost, and how they 
ought to win them all back again by founding a great city for 
the whole race of birds: and this would remind the spectators 
of the plan of centralization (συνοικισμός), which the Athenian 
statesmen of the day often employed for the establishment of 
democracy, even in the Peloponnese. While Agitator under- 
takes all the solemnities which belonged to the foundation of a 
Greek city, and drives away the crowd, which is soon collected, 
of priests, writers of hymns, prophets, land-surveyors, inspectors- 
general, and legislators—scenes full of satirical reflexion on the 





1 Tt is said to have been, in fact, the Thracian king Tereus, who had married 


Pandion’s daughter Procne, and was ‘turned into a hoopoo, his wife being meta- 
morphosed into a nightingale. 


ANALYSIS OF THE BIRDS. 41 


conduct of the Athenians in their colonies and in allied states,— 
Hopegood superintends the building of this castle-in-the-air, 
the Cloudcuckootown (Νεφελοκοκκυγία), and shortly after a 
messenger makes his appearance with a most amusing descrip- 
tion of the way in which the great fabric was constructed by 
the labours of the different species of birds. Agitator treats 
this description as a lie;’ and the spectators are also sensible 
that Cloudeuckootown exists only in imagination, since Iris, the 
messenger of the gods, flies past without having perceived, on 
her way from heaven to earth, the faintest trace of the great 
blockading fortress.? The affair creates all the more sensation 
among men on this account, and a number of swaggerers come 
to get their share in the promised distribution of wings, without 
Agitator being able to make any use of those new citizens for 
his city. As, however, men leave off sacrificing to the gods, 
and pay honour to the birds only, the gods themselves are 
obliged to enter into the imposture, and bear a part in the 
absurdities which result from it. An agreement is made in 
which Zeus himself gives up his sovereignty to Agitator ; this is 
brought about by a contrivance of Agitator; he has the skill to 
win over Hercules, who has come as an ambassador from the 
gods, with the savoury smell of certain birds, whom he has 
arrested as aristocrats, and is roasting for his dinner. At the 
end of the comedy Agitator appears with Sovereignty, (Βασίλεια,) 
splendidly attired as his bride, brandishing the thunder-bolts of 
Zeus, and in a triumphal hymeneal procession, accompanied by 
the whole tribe of birds. 

In this short sketch we have purposely omitted all the 
subordinate parts, amusing and brilliant as they are, in order 
to make sure of obtaining a correct view of the whole piece. 
People have often overlooked the general scope of the play, and 
have sought for a signification in the details, which the plan of 
the whole would not allow. It is impossible that Athens can 
have been intended under Cloudcuckootown, especially as this 





ly. 1167. ἴσα γὰρ ἀληθῶς φαίνεταί μοι ψεύδεσιν. 

2 Of course we see nothing of the new city on the stage, which throughout the 
piece represents a rocky place with trees about it, and with the house of the Epops 
in the centre, which at the end of the play is converted into the kitchen where the 
birds are roasted. 


42 ARISTOPHANES. 


city of the birds is treated as a mere imagination: moreover, 
the birds are real birds throughout the play, and if Aristophanes 
had intended to. represent his countrymen under these masks, 
the characteristics of the Athenians would have been shown in 
them in a very different way.’ Besides, it is very difficult to 
believe that Agitator and Hopegood were intended to re- 
present any Athenian statesmen in particular; the chief 
rulers of the people at the time could not possibly have shown 
themselves diametrically opposed, as Agitator does, to the 
judicial and legislative system, and to the sycophancy of the 
Athenians. But according to the poet’s express declaration, 
they are Athenians, the genuine offspring of Athens, and it is 
clear, that in these two characters, he intended to give two per- 
fect specimens of the Athenians of the day; the one is an 
intriguing projector, a restless, inventive genius, who knows how 
to give a plausible appearance to the most irrational schemes ; 
the other is an honest credulous fool, who enters into the follies 
of his companion with the utmost simplicity.” Consequently, 
the whole piece is a satire on Athenian frivolity and credulity, 
on that building of castles in the air, and that dreaming ex- 
pectation of a life of luxury and ease, to which the Athenian 
people gave themselves up in the mass: but the satire is so 
general, there is so little of anger and bitterness, so much of 
fantastic humour in it, that no comedy could make a more 
agreeable and harmless impression. We must, in this, dissent 
entirely from the opinion of the Athenian judges, who, though 
they crowned the Knights, awarded only the second prize to the 
Birds ; it seems that they were better able to appreciate the 
force of a violent personal attack than the creative fulness of 
comic originality. 

§ 9. We have two plays of Aristophanes which came out in 
Ol. 92, 1. B.c. 411 (if our chronological data are correct), the 





1 That several points applicable to Athens occur in the Cloudeuckootown (the 
Acropolis, with the worship of Minerva Polias, the Pelasgian wall, &c.) proves 
nothing but this, that the Athenians, who plan the city, made use of names 
common at home, as was always the custom in colonies. 

* We may remark that Euelpides only remains on the stage till the plan of 


Nephelococcygia is formed: after that, the poet has no further employment for 
him, 


ANALYSIS OF THE THESMOPHORIAZUS.%. 43 


Lysistrata and the Thesmophoriazuse. <A didascalia, which has 
come down to us, assigns the Lysistrata to this year, in which, 
after the unfortunate issue of the Sicilian expedition, the occu- 
pation of Deceleia by the Spartans, and their subsidiary treaty 
with the king of Persia, the war began to press heavily upon 
the Athenians. At the same time the constitution of Athens 
had fallen into a fluctuating state, which ended in an oligarchy; 
a board of commissioners (πρύβουλοι), consisting of men of the 
greatest rank and consideration, superintended all the affairs of 
state ; and, a few months after the representation of the Thes- 
mophoriazuse began the rule of the Four Hundred. Aristo- 
phanes, who had all along been attached to the peace-party, 
which consisted of the thriving landed proprietors, now gave 
himself up entirely to his longing for peace, as if all civic rule 
and harmony in the state must necessarily be restored by a 
cessation from war. In the Lysistrata this longing for peace is 
exhibited in a farcical form, which is almost without a parallel 
for extravagant indecency ; the women are represented as com- 
pelling their husbands to come to terms, by refusing them the 
exercise of their marital rights; but the care with which he 
abstains from any direct political satire shows how fluctuating . 
all relations were at that time, and how little Aristophanes could 
tell whither to turn himself with the vigour of a man who has 
chosen his party. 

In the Thesmophoriazuse, nearly contemporary with the 
Lysistrata,’ Aristophanes keeps still further aloof from politics, 





1 The date assigned to the Thesmophoriazuse, Ol. 92, 1. B.C. 411, rests partly 
on its relation to the Andromeda of Euripides, (see chap. XXV. § 17, note,) 
which was a year older, and which, from its relation to the Frogs, (Schol. Aristoph. 
Frogs, 53,) is placed in Ol. ΟἹ, 4. Β.6. 412. No doubt the expression ὀγδόῳ ἔτει 
would also allow us to place the Andromeda in 413; and therefore, the Thesmo- 
phoriazuse in 412; but this is opposed by the clear mention of the defeat of 
Charminus in a sea-fight, (Thesmoph. 804 ;) which falls, according to Thucyd. viii. 
41, in the very beginning of 411. Without setting aside the Schol. Frogs, 53, and 
some other corresponding notices in the Ravenna scholia on the Thesmophoriazuse, 
we cannot bring down this comedy to the year 410: consequently, the passage in v. 
808 about the deposed councillors, cannot refer to the expulsion of the Five Hundred 
by the oligarchy of the Four Hundred (Thucyd. viii. 69,) which did not take place 
till after the Dionysia of the year 411; but to the circumstance that the βουλευταὶ 
of the year 412, Ol. g1, 4, were obliged to give up a considerable part of their 
functions to the board of πρόβουλοι (Thucyd, viii. 1). 


44 ARISTOPHANES. 


and plunges into literary criticism (such as before only served 
him fora collateral ornament), which he helps out with a com- 
plete apparatus of indecent jokes. Euripides passed for a 
woman-hater at Athens: but without any reason ; for, in his 
tragedies, the charming, susceptible mind of woman is as often 
the motive of good as of bad actions. General opinion, how- 
ever, had stamped him as a misogynist. Accordingly, the piece 
turns on the fiction that the women had resolved at the feast of 
the Thesmophoria, when they were quite alone, to take vyen-— 
geance on Euripides, and punish him with death; and that 
Euripides was desirous of getting some one whom he might pass 
off for a woman, and send as such into thisassembly. The first 
person who occurs to his mind, the delicate, effeminate Agathon 
—an excellent opportunity for travestying Agathon’s manner— 
will not undertake the business, and only furnishes the costume, 
in which the aged Mnesilochus, the father-in-law and friend of 
Euripides, is dressed up as a woman. Mnesilochus conducts his 
friend’s cause with great vigour; but he is denounced, his sex 
is discovered, and, on the complaint of the women, he is com- 
mitted to the custody of a Scythian police-slave, until Euripides, 
having in vain endeavoured, in the guise of a tragic Menelaus 
and Perseus, to carry off this new Helen and Andromeda, 
entices the Scythian from his watch over Mnesilochus by an 
artifice of a grosser and more material kind. The chief joke 
in the whole piece is that Aristophanes, though he pretends to 
punish Euripides for his calumnies against women, is much 
more severe upon the fair sex than Euripides had ever been. 

§ 10. The literary criticism, which seems to have been the 
principal employment of Aristophanes during the last gloomy 
years of the Peloponnesian war, came out in its most perfect 
form in the Frogs, which was acted Ol. 93, 3. B.c. 405, and is 
one of the most masterly productions which the muse of comedy 
has ever conceded to her favourites. The idea, on which the 
whole is built, is beautiful and grand. Dionysus, the god of the 
Attic stage, here represented as a young Athenian fop, who 
gives himself out as a connoisseur of tragedies, is much dis- 
tressed at the great deficiency of tragic poets after the deaths of 
Euripides and Sophocles, and is resolved to go and bring up a 


ANALYSIS OF THE FROGS. 45 


tragedian from the other world,—if possible, Euripides.’ He 
gets Charon to ferry him over the pool which forms the 
boundary of the infernal regions (where he is obliged to pull 
himself to the merry croaking of the marsh frogs),’ and arrives, 
after various dangers, at the place where the chorus of the 
happy souls who have been initiated into the mysteries (¢.e. those 
who are capable of enjoying properly the freedom and merriment 
of comedy) perform their songs and dances: he and his servant 
Xanthias have, however, still many amusing adventures to 
undergo at Pluto’s gate, before they are admitted. It so happens 
that a strife has arisen in the subterranean world between 
Z&schylus, who had hitherto occupied the tragic throne, and the 
newly-arrived Euripides, who lays claim to it: and Dionysus 
connects this with his own plan by promising to take with him 
to the upper regions whichever of the two gains the victory in 
this contest. The contest which ensues is a peculiar mixture of 
jest and earnest : it extends over every department of tragic 
art,—the subject-matter and moral effects, the style and execu- 
tion, prologues, choral songs and monodies, and often, though 
in a very comic manner, hits the right point. The comedian, 
however, does not hesitate to support, rather by bold figures 
than by proofs, his opinion that Aischylus had uttered profound 
observations, sterling truths, full of moral significance; while 
Euripides, with his subtle reasonings, rendered insecure the basis 
of religious faith and moral principles on which the weal of the 
state rested. Thus, at the end of the play, the two tragedians 
proceed to weigh their verses; and the powerful sayings of 
Aischylus make the pointed thoughts of Euripides kick the 
beam. In his fundamental opinion about the relative merits of 
these poems, Aristophanes is undoubtedly so far right, that the 
immediate feeling for and natural consciousness of the right 





1 He is chiefly desirous of seeing the Andromeda of Euripides, which was 
exceedingly popular with the people of Abdera also, Lucian. Quom. conser. sit. 
Hist, 1. 

2 The part of the Frogs was indeed performed by the chorus, but they were 
not seen, (i.¢. it was a parachoregema;) probably the choreutz were placed in the 
hyposcenium, (a space under the stage,) and therefore on the same elevation as the 
orchestra. 


46 ARISTOPHANES. 


and the good which breathes in the works of Alschylus, was far 
more conducive to the moral strength of mind and public virtue 
of his fellow-citizens than a mode of reasoning like that in 
Euripides, which brings all things before its tribunal, and, as it 
were, makes everything dependent on the doubtful issue of a 
trial. But Aristophanes is wrong in reproaching Euripides 
personally with a tendency which exercised such an irresistible 
influence on his age in general. If it was the aim of the 
comedian to bring back the Athenian public to that point of 
literary taste when Aischylus was fully sufficient for them, it 
would have been necessary for him to be able to lock the wheels 
of time, and to screw back the machinery which propelled the 
mind in its forward progress. 

We should not omit to mention the political references which 
occasionally appear by the side of the literary contents of this 
comedy. Aristophanes maintains his position of opponent to 
the violent democrats: he attacks the demagogue Cleophon, 
then in the height of his power: in the parabasis he recom- 
mends the people, covertly but significantly enough, to make. 
peace with and be reconciled to the persecuted oligarchs, who 
had ruled over Athens during the time of the Four Hundred ; 
recognising, however, the inability of the people to save them- 
selves from the ruin which threatens them by their own power 
and prudence, he hints that they should submit to the mighty 
genius of Alcibiades, though he was certainly no old Athenian 
according to the ideal of Aristophanes: this suggestion is con- 


tained in two remarkable verses, which he puts into the mouth 
of Aischylus :— 


*T were best to rear no lion in the state, 
But when ’tis done, his will must not be thwarted ;— 


a piece of advice which would have been more in season had it 
been delivered ten years earlier. . 

§ 11. Aristophanes is the only one of the great Athenian 
poets who survived the Peloponnesian war, in the course of 
which Sophocles and Euripides, Cratinus and Eupolis, had all 
died. We find him still writing for the stage for a series of 
years after the close of the war. His Ecclesiazuse was probably 
brought out in Ol. 96, 4. B.c. 392: it is a piece of wild 


ANALYSIS OF THE PLUTUS. 47 


drollery, but based upon the same political creed which Aristo- 
phanes had professed for thirty years. Democracy had been 
restored in its worst features; the public money was again 
expended for private purposes ; the demagogue Agyrrhius was 
catering for the people by furnishing them with pay for their 
attendance in the public assembly ; and the populace were fol- 
lowing to-day one leader, and to-morrow another. In this 
state of affairs, according to the fiction of Aristophanes, the 
women resolve to take upon themselves the whole management 
of the city, and carry their point by appearing in the assembly 
in men’s clothes, principally ‘ because this was the only thing 
that had not yet been attempted at Athens ;’’ and people hoped 
that, according to an old oracle, the wildest resolution which 
they made would turn out to their benefit. The women then 
establish an excellent Utopia, in which property and wives are 
to be in common, and the interests of the ugly of both sexes 
are specially provided for, a conception which is followed out 
into all its absurd consequences with a liberal mixture of 
humour and indecency. 

From this combination of a serious thought, by way of 
foundation, with the boldest creations of a riotous imagination, 
the Ecclesiazuse must be classed with the works which appeared 
during the vigour of Attic comedy: but the technical arrange- 
ment shows, in a manner which cannot be mistaken, the poverty 
and thriftiness of the state at this time. The chorus is obvi- 
ously fitted out very parsimoniously ; its masks were easily 
made, as they represented only Athenian women, who at first 
appear with beards and men’s cloaks; besides, it required but 
little practice, as it had but little to smg. The whole parabasis 
is omitted, and its place is supplied by a short address, in which 
the chorus, before it leaves the stage, calls upon the judges 
to decide fairly and impartially. 

These outward deviations from the original plan of the old 
comedy are in the Plutus combined with great alterations in 
the internal structure; and thus furnish a plain transition to 





1 Eeclesiaz. v. 456. ἐδόκει yap τοῦτο μόνον ἐν τῃ πόλει 
f οὔπω γεγενῆσθαι. 
3 The choregie were not discontinued, but people endeavoured to make them less 
expensive every year. See Boeckh, Public Economy of Athens, book iii. § 22. 


48 ARISTOPHANES. 


the middle comedy, as it is called. The extant Plutus is not 

that which the poet produced in Ol. 92, 4. B.c. 408, but that 

which came out twenty years later in Ol. 97, 4. B.c. 388, and 

was the last piece which the aged poet brought forward himself; 

for two plays which he composed subsequently, the Cocalus and 

Miolosicon, were brought out by his son Araros. [πὰ the extant 

Plutus, Aristophanes tears himself away altogether from the 

great political interests of the state. His satire in this piece is, 

in part, universally applicable to all races and ages of men, for 
it is directed against defects and perversities which attach them- 

selves to our everyday life; and, in part, it is altogether 

personal, as it attacks individuals selected from the mass at the 

caprice of the poet, in order that the jokes may take a deeper _ 
and wider root. The conception on which it is based is of 
- lasting significance: the god of riches has, in his blindness, 
fallen into the hands of the worst of men, and has himself 
suffered greatly thereby: a worthy, respectable citizen, Chre- 
mylus, provides for the recovery of his. sight, and so makes 
many good people prosperous, and reduces many knaves to 
poverty. From the more general nature of the fable it follows 
that the persons also have the general character of their condi- 
tion and employments, in which the piece approximates to the 
manner of the middle comedy, as it also does in the more 
decent, less offensive, but at the same time less genial nature of 
the language. The alteration, however, does not run through 
the play so as to bring the new species of comedy before us in 
its complete form ; here and there we feel the breath of the old 
comedy around us, and we cannot avoid the melancholy convic- 
tion that the genial comedian has survived the best days of his 
art, and has therefore become insecure and unequal in his 
application of it. 


49 


CHAPTER XXIX. 


THE OTHER POETS OF THE OLD COMEDY—THE MIDDLE AND 
NEW COMEDY. 


§ 1. Characteristics of Cratinus. § 2. Eupolis. § 3. Peculiar tendencies of Crates ; 
his connexion with Sicilian comedy. § 4. Sicilian comedy originates in the 
Doric farces of Megara. § 5. Events in the life of Epicharmus; general tendency - 
and nature of his comedy. § 6. The middle Attic comedy; poets of this class 
akin to those of the Sicilian comedy in many of their pieces. § 7. Poets of the 
new comedy the immediate successors of those of the middle comedy. How the 
new comedy becomes naturalized at Rome. § 8. Public morality at Athens 
at the time of the new comedy. § 9. Character of the new comedy in connexion 
therewith. 


§ 1. (A\RATINUS and Evpotis, Puerecrares and Hermrrrvs, 

TELECLEIDES and PxarTo, and several of those who com- 
peted with them for the prize of comedy, are known to us from 
the names of a number of their pieces which have come down 
to our time, and also from the short quotations from their plays 
by subsequent authors; these furnish us with abundant ma- 
terials for an inquiry into the details of Athenian life, public 
and private, but are of little use for a description like the 
present, which is based on the contents of individual works and 
on the characteristics of the different poets. 

Of Cratinvs, in particular, we learn more from the short but 
pregnant notices of him by Aristophanes, than from the very 
mutilated fragments of his works. Itis clear that he was well 
fitted by nature for the wild and merry dances of the Bacchic 
Comus. The spirit of comedy spoke out as clearly and as 
powerfully in him as that of tragedy did in Aischylus. He 
gave himself up with all the might of his genius to the fantastic 
humour of this amusement, and the scattered sparks of his 
wit proceeded from a soul imbued with the magnanimous honesty 
of the older Athenians. His personal attacks were free from 
all fear or regard to the consequences. As opposed to Cratinus, 
Aristophanes appeared as a well educated man, skilled and apt 
in speech, and not untinged with that very sophistic training of 

Vou. 11. E 


50 OTHER POETS OF THE OLD COMEDY. 


Euripides, against which he so systematically inveighed: and 
thus we find it asked in a fragment of Cratinus—‘ Who art 
thou, thou hair-splitting orator; thou hunter after sentences ; 
thou petty Euripidaristophanes Ὁ} 

Even the names of his choruses show, to a certain extent, on 
what various and bold devices the poems of Cratinus were based. 
He not only made up a chorus of mere Archilochuses and Cleo- 
bulines, ὁ. 6. of abusive slanderers and gossiping women ; he also 
brought on a number of Ulysseses and Chirons as a chorus, and - 
even Panopteses, ὁ. e. beings like the Argos-Panoptes of my- 
thology, who had heads turned both ways, with innumerable 
eyes,” by which, according to an ingenious explanation,’ he in- 
tended to represent the scholars of Hippo, a speculative phi- 
losopher of the day, whose followers pretended that nothing in 
heaven or earth remained concealed from them. Even the 
riches (πλοῦτοι) and the laws (νόμοι) of Athens formed choruses 
in the plays of Cratinus, as, in general, Attic comedy took the 
liberty of personifying whatever it pleased. 

The play of Cratinus, with the plot of which we are best 
acquainted, is the Pytine, or ‘ bottle,” which he wrote in the 
_ last year of his life. In his later years Cratinus was un- 

doubtedly much given to drinking, and Aristophanes and the 
other comedians were already sneering at him as a doting old 
man, whose poetry was fuddled with wine. Upon this the old 
comedian suddenly roused himself, and with such vigour and 
success that he won the prize, in Ol. 89, 1. B.c. 423, from all 
his rivals, including Aristophanes, who brought out the Clouds 
on the occasion. The piece which Cratinus thus produced was 
the Pytine. With magnanimous candour the poet made him- 
self the subject of his own comedy. The comic muse was 
represented as the lawful wife of Cratinus, as the faithful 
partner of his younger days, and she complained bitterly of the 
neglect with which she was then treated in consequence of her 
husband having become attached to another lady, the bottle. 





1 Tis δὲ σύ ; (κομψός τις ἔροιτο θεατής) 
Ὑπολεπτολόγος, γνωμιδιώτης, εὐριπιδαριστοφανίζων, 
The answer of Aristophanes is mentioned above, chap. XXV. 8 7. 
3 Κράνια δισσὰ φορεῖν, ὀφθαλμοὶ δ᾽ οὐκ ἀριθματοί" 
3 Bergk de reliquiis Comedie Attice antique, p. 162. 





CRATINUS—EUPOLIS. 51 


She goes to the Archons, and brings a plaint of criminal neg- 
lect (κάκωσις) against him; if her husband will not return to 
her she is to obtain a divorce from him. The consequence is, 
that the poet returns to his senses, and his old love is re- 
awakened in his bosom; and at the end he raises himself up 
in all the power and beauty of his poetical genius, and goes so 
far in the drama that his friends try to stop his mouth, lest he 
should carry away everything with the overflowing of his 
imagery and versification.’ In this piece Cratinus does not 
merit the reproach which has been generally cast upon him, 
that he could not work out his own’ excellent conceptions, but, 
as it were, destroyed them himself. 

So early as the time when Cratinus was im his prime (Ol. 85, 
I. B.c. 440), a law was passed limiting the freedom of comic 
satire. It is very probable that it was under the constraint of 
this law (which, however, was not long in force), that the 
Ulysses (Οδυσσεῖς) of Cratinus was brought out; a piece of 
which it was remarked by the old literary critics,’ that it came 
nearer to the character of the middle comedy: it probably ab- 
stained from all personal, and especially from political satire, 
and kept itself within the circle of the general relations of man- 
kind, in which it was easy for the poet to avail himself of the 
old mythical story,—Ulysses in the cave of Polyphemus. 

§ 2. A Roman poet, who was very careful in his choice of 
words, and who is remarkable for a certain pregnancy of ex- 
pression,’ calls Cratinus ‘the bold, and in the same passage 
opposes Evro.is to him, as ‘ the angry.’ Although Eupolis is 
stated to have been celebrated for his elegance, and for the 
aptness of his witticisms, as well as for his imaginative powers,* 





1 Cratini fragmenta coll. Runkel, p. 50. Meineke, Hist. Crit. Com. Grec., vol. 1. 
p. 54, vol. II. p. 116—132. 

2 Platonius de Comedia, p. viii. That the piece contained a caricature (διασυρμόν 
twa) of Homer's Odyssey is not to be understood as if Cratinus had wished to 
ridicule Homer, 

3 Audaci quicunque adflate Cratino, 
Tratum Eupolidem preegrandi cum sene palles. 
Persius I. 124. The Vita Aristophanis agrees with this. 

4 Φαντασία, εὐφάνταστος. Platonius also speaks highly of the energy (ὑψηλός) 
and grace (ἐπίχαρις) of Eupolis. He perhaps exaggerates the latter quality. See 
Meineke, Hist. Crit. Com. Gr. vol. I. p. 107. 

E 2 


52 OTHER POETS OF THE OLD COMEDY. 


his style was probably marked by a strong hatred of the pre- 
vailing depravity, and by much bitterness of satire. He himself 
claimed a share in the Knights of Aristophanes, in which per- 
sonal satire prevails more than in any other comedy of that 
poet. On the other hand, Aristophanes maintains that Eupolis, 
in his Maricas, had imitated the Knights, and spoiled it by 
injudicious additions.’ Of the Maricas, which was produced 
Ol. 89, 3. B.c. 421, we only know thus much, that under this 
slave’s name he exhibited the demagogue Hyperbolus, who suc- 
ceeded to Cleon’s place in the favour of the people, and who 
was, like Cleon, represented as a low-minded, ill-educated 
fellow; the worthy Nicias was introduced in the piece chiefly 
as the butt of his tricks. The most virulent, however, of the 
plays of Eupolis was probably the Bapte, which is often men- 
tioned by old writers, but in such terms that it is not easy to 
gather a clear notion of this very singular drama. The view 
which appears most probable to the author of these pages is, 
that the comedy of Eupolis was directed against the club 
(cratpia) of Alcibiades, and especially against a sort of mixture 
of profligacy, which despised the conventional morality of the 
day, and frivolity, and which set at nought the old religion of 
Athens, and thus naturally assumed the garb of mystic and 
foreign religions. In this piece Alcibiades and his comrades 
appeared under the name of Bapte (which seems to haye been 
borrowed from a mystic rite of baptism which they practised), 
as worshippers of a barbarian deity Cotys or Cotytto, whose 
wild worship was celebrated with the din of loud music, and 
was made a cloak for all sorts of debauchery ; and the picture 
given of these rites in the piece, if we may judge from what 
Juvenal says,” must have been very powerful and impressive. 
Eupolis composed two plays which obviously had some con- 
nexion with one another, and which represented the political 
condition of Athens at the time, the one in its domestic, the 
other in its external relations. In the former, which was ¢alled 
the Demi, the boroughs of Attica, of which the whole people 
consisted (οἱ δῆμοι), formed the persons of the chorus; and 
Myronides, a distinguished general and statesman of the time 





1 Aristophanes, Clouds, 553. 2 Juvenal, II. gr. 


7 


EUPOLIS—CRATES. 53 


of Pericles, who had survived the great men of his own day, 
and now in extreme old age felt that he stood alone in the 
midst of a degenerate race, was represented as descending to 
the other world to restore to Athens one of her old leaders ; 
and he does in fact bring back Solon, Miltiades, and Pericles. 
The poet contrived, no doubt, to construct a very agreeable plot 
by a portraiture of these men, in which respect for the great- 
ness of their characters was combined with many merry jests, 
and by exhibiting on the other side, in the most energetic 
manner, the existing state of Athens, destitute as she then was 
of good statesmen and generals. From some fragments it 
appears that the old heroes felt very uncomfortable in this upper 
world of ours, and that the chorus had to intreat them most 
earnestly not to give up the state-affairs and the army of 
Athens to a set of effeminate and presumptuous young men : 
at the conclusion of the piece, the chorus offers up to the spirits 
of the heroes, with all proper ceremonies, the wool-bound olive 
boughs (εἰρεσιῶναι), by which, according to the religious rites 
of the Greeks, it had supported its supplications to them, and so 
honours them as gods. In the Poleis, the chorus consisted of 
the allied or rather tributary cities ; the island of Chios, which 
had always remained true to Athens, and was therefore better 
treated than the others, stood advantageously prominent among 
them, and Cyzicus in the Propontis brought up the rear. Be- 
yond this little is known about the connexion of the plot. 

ὃ 3. Among the remaining comic poets of this time, Crarrs 
stands most prominently forward, because he differs most from 
the others. From being an actor in Cratinus’ plays, Crates had 
risen to the rank of a comic poet ; he was, however, anything 
but an imitator of his master. On the contrary, he entirely 
gave up the field which Cratinus and the other comedians had 
chosen as their regular arena, namely, political satire; perhaps 
because in his inferior position he lacked the courage to attack 





1 That Myronides brings up Pericles is clear from a comparison of Plutarch, 
Pericl. 24, with the passages of Aristides, Platonius, and others, (Raspe de Zupolid. 
Δήμοις et ἸΤόλεσιν. Lips. 1832.) Pericles asks Myronides, ‘Why he brings him 
back to life? are there no good people in Athens? if his son by Aspasia is not 
a great statesman? and so forth. From this it is clear that it was Myronides 
who had conveyed him from the other world. 


54 OTHER POETS OF THE OLD COMEDY. 


from the stage the most powerful demagogues, or because he 
thought that department already exhausted of its best materials. 
His skill lay in the more artificial design and development of 
his plots,’ and the interest of his pieces depended on the con- 
nexion of the stories which they involved. Accordingly, Aris- 
tophanes says of him,’ that he had feasted the Athenians at a 
trifling expense, and had with great sobriety given them the 
enjoyment of his most ingenious inventions. Crates is said to 
have been the first who introduced the drunkard on the stage: 
and Puerecrates, who of the later Attic comedians most 
resembled Crates,’ painted the glutton with most colossal 
features. 

§ 4. Aristotle connects Crates with the Sicilian comic poet 
EpicuarMus, and no doubt he stood ina nearer relation to him 
than the other comedians of Athens. This will be the right 
place to speak of this celebrated poet, as it would have disturbed 
the historic development of the Attic drama had we turned our 
attention at an earlier period to the comedy of Sicily. As we 
have already remarked (chap. XXVII. § 3), Sicilian comedy is 
connected with the old farces of Megara, but took a different 
direction, and one quite peculiar to itself. The Megarian farces 
themselves did not exhibit the political character which was so 
early assumed by Attic comedy ; but they cultivated a depart- 


ment of raillery which was unknown to the comedy of Aris- — 


tophanes, that is, a ludicrous imitation of certain classes and 
conditions of common life. A lively and cheerful observation 
of the habits and manners connected with certain offices and 
professions soon enabled the comedian to observe something 
characteristic in them, and often something narrow-minded and 
partial, something quite foreign to the results of a liberal educa- 
tion, something which rendered the person awkward and un- 


fitted for other employments, and so opened a wide field for 


satire and witticisms. In this way Mason, an old Megarian 





1 Aristot. Poet.c.5. Tay δὲ ᾿Αθήνησι Κράτης πρῶτος ἧρξεν, ἀφέμενος τῆς ἰαμβικῆς 
ἰδέας, καθόλου λόγους ἢ μύθους ποιξιν" ἱ.6. ‘ Of the Athenian comedians, Crates was 
the first who gave up personal satire, and began to makenarratives or poems on more 
general subjects.’ 

® Knights, 537. Comp. Meineke, Hist. Crit. Com. Gree. p. 60. 

3 Anonym. de Comedia, p. xxix., 


ΝΥΝ δε ee 


SICILIAN COMEDY. 55 


comic actor and poet,’ constantly employed the mask of a cook 
or a scullion: consequently such persons were called Mzsones 
(μαίσωνες) at Athens, and their jokes Mesonian (μαισωνικα) 
A considerable element in such representations would consist of 
mimicry and absurd gestures, such as the Dorians seem to have 
been generally more fond of than the Athenians ; the amusement 
furnished by the Spartan Deicelicte (δεικήλικται) was made up 
of the imitation of certain characters taken from commom life ; 
for instance, the character of a foreign physician represented in 
a sort of pantomime dance, and with the vulgar language of the 
lower orders.* The more probable supposition is, that this sort 
of comedy passed over to Sicily through the Doric colonies, as 
it is on the western boundaries of the Grecian world that we find 
a general prevalence of comic dramas in which the amusement 
consists in a recurrence of the same character and the same 
species of masks. The Oscan pastime of the Afellane, which 
went from Campania to Rome, was also properly designated by 
these standing characters ; and great as the distance was from 
the Dorians of the Peloponnese to the Oscans of Atella, we may 
nevertheless discern in the character-masks of the latter some 
clear traces of Greek influence.* 

In Sicily, comedy made its first appearance at Selinus, a 
Megarian colony. ARIstoxENUS, who composed comedies in the 
Dorian dialect, lived here before Epicharmus ; how long before 
him cannot be satisfactorily ascertained. In fact we know very 
little about him; still it is remarkable that among the few 
records of him which we possess there is a verse which was the 
commencement of a somewhat long invective against sooth- 





1 There can be no doubt that he lived at a time when there existed by the side of 
the Attic comedy a Megarian drama of the same kind, of which Ecphantides, a 
predecessor of Cratinus, and other poets of the old comedy, spoke as a rough 
farcical entertainment. The Megarian comedian Solynus belongs to the same 
period. 

3 The grammarian Aristophanes of Byzantium, quoted by Atheneus, XIV., p. 
659, and Festus, 5. v. Meson. 

3 See Miiller’s Dorians, b. iv. ch. 6. ὃ 9. 

4 Among the standing masks of the Atellana was the Pappus, whose name is 
obviously the Greek πάππος, and reminds us of the Παπποσείληνος, the old leader 
of the satyrs, in the satyric drama ; the Maccus, whose name is explained by the Greek 
μακκοᾶν ; also the Simus, (at least in later times: Sueton. Galba, 13), which was a 
peculiar epithet of the Satyrs from their flat noses. 


56 OTHER POETS OF THE OLD COMEDY. 


sayers ;' whence it is clear that he, too, occupied himself with 

the follies and absurdities of whole classes and conditions of 
men. ; 

§ 5. The flourishing period of Sicilian comedy was that in which 

Puormis, Ertcuarmvs, and Dernotocuus (the son or scholar 

of the latter), wrote for the stage. Phormis is mentioned as 

.the friend of Gelo and the instructor of his children. Accord- 

ing to credible authorities, Epicharmus was a native of Cos, 

who went to Sicily with Cadmus, the tyrant of Cos, when he 

resigned his power and emigrated to that island, about Ol. 73, 

B.c. 488. Epicharmus at first resided a short time at the 

Sicilian Megara, where he probably first commenced his career 

as a comedian. Megara was conquered by Gelo (Ol. 74, 1 or 2. 

B.C. 484, 483), and its inhabitants were removed to Syracuse, 

and Epicharmus among them. The prime of his life, and the 

most flourishing period of his art, are included in the reign of 
Hiero (Ol. 75, 3. to Ol. 78, 2. B.c. 478—467.) These chrono- 

logical data are sufficient to show that the tendency of Epi- 

charmus’ comedy could not be political. The safety and 
dignity of a ruler like Hiero would have been alike incompa- 

tible with such a licence of the stage. It does not, however, 

follow from this, that the plays of Epicharmus did not touch 

upon or perhaps give a complete picture of the great events of 
the time and the circumstances of the country ; and in fact we 

can clearly point out such references to the events of the day 

in several of the fragments: but the comedies of Epicharmus 

did not, like those of Aristophanes, take a part in the contests 

of political factions and tendencies, nor did they select some 

particular political circumstance of Syracuse to be praised as 

fortunate, while they represented what was opposed to it as 

miserable and ruinous. The comedy of Epicharmus has a 

general relation to the affairs of mankind: it ridicules the 

follies and perversities which certain forms of education had 

introduced into the social life of man; and a considerable 

element in it was a vivid representation of particular classes 

and persons from common life ; a large number of Epicharmus’ 

plays seem to have been comedies of character, such as his 





In Hepheestion, Encheir. p. 45. 


SICILIAN COMEDY. 57 


‘Peasant,’ (’A-ypworivoc,) and ‘the Ambassadors to the Fes- 
tival,” (Θεᾶροι;) we are positively informed that Epicharmus 
was the first to bring on the stage the Parasite and the 
Drunkard,—characters which Crates worked up for Athenian 
comedy. Epicharmus was also the first to use the name of the 
Parasite,’ which afterwards became so common in Greek and 
Roman plays, and it is likely that the rude, merry features 
with which Plautus has drawn this class of persons may, in 
their first outlines, be traceable to Epicharmus.? The Syra- 
cusan poet no doubt showed in the invention of such cha- 
racters much of that shrewdness for which the Dorians were 
distinguished more than the other Greek tribes; careful and 
acute observations of mankind are compressed into a few 
striking traits and nervous expressions, so that we seem to see 
through the whole man though he has spoken only a few 
words. But in Epicharmus this quality was combined in a 
very peculiar manner with a striving after philosophy. Epi- 
charmus was a man of a serious cast of mind, variously and 
profoundly educated. He belonged originally to the school of 
physicians at Cos, who derived their art from A‘sculapius. He 
had been initiated by Arcesas, a scholar of Pythagoras, into the 
peculiar system of the Pythagorean philosophy; and _ his 
comedies abounded in philosophical aphorisms,’ not merely, 
as one might at first expect, on notions and principles of 





ΤῸ the Attic drama of Eupolis the parasites of the rich Callias appeared as 
κόλακες ; but the fact that they constituted the chorus rendered it impossible that 
they could be made a direct object of comic satire. Alexis, of the middle comedy, 
was the first who brought the parasite (under this name) on the stage. 

2 Gelasime, salve.—Non id est nomen mihi.— 
Certo mecastor id fuit nomen tibi.— 
Fuit disertim; verum id usu perdidi ; 
Nune Miccotrogus nomine ex vero vocor,’ 
Plaut. Stich. act I. sc. 3. 

The name Miecotrogus, by which the parasite in the preceding passage calls him- 
self, is not Attic but Doric, and therefore is perhaps derived from Epicharmus. 

8 Epicharmus himself says in some beautiful verses quoted by Diogenes Laertius, 
III. ὃ 17, that one of his successors would one day surpass all other speculators by 
adopting his sayings in another form, without metre. It is perhaps not unlikely 
that the philosophical anthology which was in vogue under the name of Epicharmus, 
and which Ennius in his Zpicharmus imitated in trochaic tetrameters, was an ex- 
cerpt from the comedies of Epicharmus, just as the Gnomology, which we have 
under the name of Theognis, was a set of extracts from his Elegies. 


58 OTHER POETS OF THE OLD COMEDY. 


morality, but also on metaphysical points—-God and the world, 
body and soul, &c.; where it is certainly difficult to conceive 
how Epicharmus interwove these speculative discourses into the 
texture of his comedies. Suffice it to say, we see that Epi- 
charmus found means to connect a representation of the follies 
and absurdities of the world in which he lived, with profound 
speculations on the nature of things; whence we may infer how 
entirely different his manner was from that of the Athenian 
comedy, 

With this general ethical and philosophical tendency we may 
easily reconcile the mythical form, which we find in most of the 
comedies of Epicharmus,' Mythical personages have general 
and formal features, free from all accidental peculiarities, and 
may therefore be made the best possible basis of the principles 
and results, the symptoms and criteria of good and bad cha- 
racters. Did we but possess the comedy of the Dorians, and 
those portions of the old and middle comedy (especially the 
latter) which are so closely connected with it, we should be 
able to discern clearly what we can now only guess from titles 
and short fragments, that mythology thus treated was just as 
fruitful a source of materials for comedy as for the ideal world 
of the tragic drama. No doubt, the whole system of gods and 
heroes must have been reduced to a lower sphere of action in 
order to suit them to the purposes of comedy: the anthropo- 
morphic treatment of the gods must necessarily have arrived at 
its last stage ; the deities must have been reduced to the level © 
of common life with all its civic and domestic relations, and 
must have exhibited the lowest and most vulgar inclinations 
and passions. Thus the insatiable gluttony of Hercules was a 
subject which Epicharmus painted in vivid colours ;? in another 
place,’ a marriage feast among the gods was represented as 
extravagantly luxurious; a third, ‘ Hephestus, or the Revel- 
lers,’* exhibited the quarrel of the fire-god with his mother Hera 
as a mere family brawl, which is terminated very merrily by 
Bacchus, who, when the incensed son has left Olympus, invites 





1 Of 35 titles of his comedies, which haye come down to us, 17 are borrowed 
from mythological personages. Grysar, de Doriensium Comedia, p. 274. 


2 In his Busiris, 4In the Marriage of Hebe, 
3 Ἥφαιστος ἤ Kwpacral, 


SICILIAN COMEDY. 59 


him to a banquet, makes him sufficiently drunk, and then con- 
ducts him back in triumph to Olympus, in the midst of a 
tumultuous band of revellers. The most lively view which we 
still have of this mythological comedy is furnished by the scenes 
in Aristophanes, which seem to have the same tone and feeling : 
such as that in which Prometheus appears as the malcontent 
and intriguer in Olympus, and points out the proper method of 
depriving the gods of their sovereignty ; and then the embassy 
of the three gods, when Hercules, on smelling the roasted 
birds, forgets the interest of his own party, and the voice of 
the worst of the three ambassadors constitutes the majority ; 
this shows us what striking pictures for situations of common 
life and common relations might be borrowed from the sup- 
posed condition of the gods. At any rate, we may also see 
from this how the comic treatment of mythology differed from 
that in the satyric drama. In the latter, the gods and heroes 
were introduced among a class of beings in whom a rude, un- 
cultivated mode of life predominated: in the former they 
descended to social life, and were subject to all the deficiencies 
and infirmities of human society. 

§ 6. The Sicilian comedy in its artistic development pre- 
ceded the Attic by about a generation; yet the transition to 
the middle Attic comedy, as it is called, is easier from Epi- 
charmus than from Aristophanes, who appears very unlike him- 
self in the play which tends towards the form of the middle 
comedy. This branch of comedy belongs to a time when the 
democracy was still moving in unrestrained freedom, though 
the people had no longer such pride and confidence in them- 
selves as to ridicule from the stage their rulers and the reco- 
gnised principles of state policy, and at the same time to prevent 
themselves from being led astray by such ridicule. The unfor- 
tunate termination of the Peloponnesian war had damped the 
first fresh vigour of the Athenian state; freedom and democracy 
had been restored to the Athenians, and even a sort of maritime 
supremacy ; but their former energy of public life had not been 
restored along with these things; there were too many weak- 
nesses and defects in all parts of their political condition,—in 
their finances, in the war-department, in the law-courts. The 
Athenians, perhaps, were well aware of this, but they were too 


60 THE MIDDLE COMEDY. 


indolent and fond of pleasure to set about in earnest to free 
themselves from these inconveniences. Under such circum- 
stances, satire and ridicule, such as Aristophanes indulged 
in, would have been quite intolerable, for it would no longer 
have pointed out certain shadows in a bright and glorious pic- 
ture, but would have exhibited one dark picture without a 
single redeeming ray of light, and so would have lacked all the 
cheerfulness of comedy. Accordingly, the comedians of this 
time took that general moral tendency which we have pointed 
out in the Megarian comedy and in all that is connected with it ; 
they represented the ludicrous absurdities of certain classes and 
conditions in society,’ and in their diction kept close to the 
language of common life, which prevails much more uniformly 
in their plays than in those of Aristophanes, with the exception 
of some few passages, where it is interrupted by parodies of 
epic and tragic poetry.2 These comedians were not alto- 
gether without a basis of personal satire; but this was no 
longer directed against influential men, the rulers of the 
people ;* or, if it touched them at all, it was not on account of 
their political character, or of any principles approved by the 
bulk of the people. On the contrary, the middle comedy cul- 
tivated a narrower field of its own,—the department of literary 
rivalship. The poems of the middle comedy were rich in ridi- 
cule of the Platonic Academy, of the newly-revived sect of 
the Pythagoreans, of the orators and rhetoricians of the day, 
and of the tragic and epic poets: they sometimes even took a 
retrospective view, and subjected to their criticism anything 
which they thought weak or imperfect in the poems of Homer. 





1A bragging cook, a leading personage in middle comedy, was the chief cha- 
racter in the 4olosicon of Aristophanes. We may infer what influence the Mega- 
rian and Sicilian comedy had in the formation of regular standing characters, from 
the fact that Pollux (Onom. IV. § 146, 148, 150) names the Sicilian parasite and 
the scullion Mason among the masks of the new comedy, (according to the restora- 
tion by Meineke, Hist. Crit. Com. Gree., p. 664, comp. above, § 4.) 

5 Hence we see why the Scholiast, in the Plutus, 515, recognises the character 
of the middle comedy in the epic tone of the passage. 

3 On the contrary, these comedians considered ludicrous representations ot 
foreign rulers as quite allowable; thus the Dionysius of Eubulus was directed 
against the Sicilian tyrants, and the Dionysalecandrus of the younger Cratinus 
against Alexander of Phere. Similarly, in later times, Menander satirized Dio- 
nysius, tyrant of Heraclea, and Philemon king Magas of Cyrene. 


‘POETS OF THE MIDDLE COMEDY. 61 


This criticism was totally different from that directed by Aris- 
tophanes against Socrates, which was founded exclusively upon 
moral and practical views ; the judgments of the middle comedy 
considered everything in a literary point of view, and, if we may 
reason from individual instances, were directed solely against the 
character of the writings of the persons criticised. In the tran- 
sition from the old to the middle comedy we may discern at once 
the great revolution which had taken place in the domestic his- 
tory of Athens, when the Athenians, from a people of politicians, 
became a nation of literary men; when, instead of pronouncing 
judgment upon the general politics of Greece, and the law-suits 
of their allies, they judged only of the genuineness of the Attic 
style and of good taste in oratory; when it was no longer the 
opposition of the political ideas of Themistocles and Cimon, but 
the contest of opposing schools of philosophers and rhetoricians, 
which set all heads in motion. This great change was not fully 
accomplished till the time of Alexander’s successors; but the 
middle comedy stands as a guide-post, clearly pointing out the 
way to this consummation. The frequency of mythical subjects 
in the comedies of this class’ has the same grounds as in the 
Sicilian comedy ; for the object in both was to clothe general 
delineations of character in a mythicalform. Further than this, 
we must admit that our conceptions of the middle comedy are 
somewhat vacillating and uncertain; this arises from the con- 
stitution of the middle comedy itself, which is rather a transition 
state than a distinct species. Consequently, we find, along 
with many features resembling the old comedy, also some pecu- 
liarities of the new. Aristotle, indeed, speaks only of an old 
and a new comedy, and does not mention the middle comedy as 
distinct from the new. 

The poets of the middle comedy are also very numerous ; 
they occupy the interval between Ol. I00. B.c. 380, and 
the reign of Alexander. Among the earliest of them we find 
the sons of Aristophanes, Araros and Purippvs, and the prolific 
Evsutvs, who flourished about Ol. 107. B.c. 376: then follows 
ANAXANDRIDES, who is said to have been the first to introduce 





1 Meineke (Hist. Crit. Com. Grec., p. 283, foll.) gives a long list of such 
mythical comedies. 


62 THE NEW COMEDY. 


into comedy the stories of love and seduction, which afterwards 
formed so large an ingredient in it'—so that we have here 
another reference to the new comedy, and the first step in its 
subsequent development. Then we have Ampuis and ANnaxi- 
LAus, both of whom made Plato the butt of their wit; the 
younger Cratinus; Timocxies, who ridiculed the orators De- 
mosthenes and Hyperides; still later, ALexts, one of the most 
productive, and at the same time one of the most eminent of 
these poets: his fragments, however, show a decided affinity to 
the new comedy, and he was a contemporary of Menander and 
Philemon.? AnrtreHanes began to exhibit as early as 383 B.c. ; 
his comedies, however, were of much the same kind with those 
of Alexis: he was by far the most prolific of the poets of the 
middle comedy, and was distinguished by his redundant wit 
and inexhaustible invention. The number of his pieces, which 
amounted to 300, and according to some authorities exceeded 
that number, proves that the comedians of this time no longer 
contended, like Aristophanes, with single pieces, and only at the 
Lenza and great Dionysia, but either composed for the other 
festivals, or, what seems to us the preferable opinion, produced 
several pieces at the same festival.’ 

§ 7. These last poets of the middle comedy were contem- 
poraries of the writers of the new comedy, who rose up as their 
rivals, and were only distinguished from them by following their 
new tendency more decidedly and more exclusively. Mrnan- 
DER was one of the first of these poets (he flourished at the 
time immediately succeeding the death of Alexander ἢ), and he 
was also the most perfect of them, which will not surprise us if 
we consider the middle comedy as a sort of preparation for the 





1The Cocalus of Aristophanes (Araros) contains, according to Platonius, a 
scene of seduction and recognition of the same kind with those in the comedies of 
Menander. 

2It appears by the fragment of the Hypobolimeus, (Athen. XI. p. 502. B. 
Meineke Hist. Crit. Com. Grec. p. 315.) 

3 Concerning Antiphanes, see Clinton, Philol. Mus. I. p. 558 foll., and Meineke, 
Hist. Crit. Com. Gr. p. 304—40. It appears from the remarks of Clinton, p. 607, 
and Meineke, p. 305, that the passage attributed by Atheneus IV. p. 156. ©., to 
Antiphanes, in which king Seleucus is mentioned, is probably by another comic poet. 


4 Menander brought out his first piece when he was still a young man (ἔφηβος) in 


Ol. 114, 3. B.C. 322, and died as early as Ol. 122, 1. B.C. 291. 








POETS OF THE NEW COMEDY. 63 


new.’ PxHrILtEeMon came forward rather earlier than Menander, 
and survived him many years; he was a great favourite with 
the Athenians, but was always placed after Menander by those 
who knew them both.? These are followed by Purtirripss, a 
contemporary of Philemon ;* by Direuiivus of Sinope,* who was 
somewhat later; by Arottoporvus of Gela, a contemporary of 
Menander, Arottoporvs of Carystus, who was in the following 
generation,’ and by a considerable number of poets, more or 
less worthy to be classed with these. 

Passing here from the middle comedy to the new, we come 
at once to a clearer region; here the Roman imitations, com- 
bined with the numerous and sometimes considerable fragments, 
are sufficient to give us a clear conception of a comedy of Me- 
nander in its general plan and in its details: a person who 
possessed the peculiar talents requisite for such a task, and had 
acquired by study the acquaintance with the Greek language 
and the Attic subtlety of expression necessary for the execution 
of it, might without much difficulty restore a piece of Menander’s, 
so as to replace the lost original. The comedy of the Romans 
must not be conceived as merely a learned and literary imitation 
of the Greek ; it formed a living union with the Greek comedy, 
by a transfer to Rome of the whole Greek stage, not by a mere 
transmission through books; and in point of time too there is 
an immediate and unbroken connexion between them. For 
although the period at which the Greek new comedy flourished 
followed immediately upon the death of Alexander, yet the first 
generation was followed by a second, as Philemon the son fol- 
lowed Philemon the father, and comic writing of less merit and 
reputation most probably continued till a late period to provide 
by new productions for the amusement of the people; so that 





1 According to Anon. de comedia, Menander was specially instructed in his art 
by Alexis. 

2 Menander said to him, when he had won the prize from him in a dramatic 
contest, ‘Philemon, do you not blush to conquer me? Aul. Gel. V.A. XVIL. 4. 

3 According to Suidas he came forward Ol. 111., still earlier than Philemon. 

4 Sinope was at that time the native city of three comedians, Diphilus, Diony- 
sius, and Diodorus, and also of the cynic philosopher Diogenes. It must have 
been the fashion at Sinope to derive proper names from Zeus, the Zeus Chthonius 
or Serapis of Sinope. 

5 According to the inferences in Meineke’s Hist. Crit. Com. Grec., p. 459, 462. 


64 THE NEW COMEDY. 


when Livius Andronicus first appeared before the Roman pub- 
lic with plays in imitation of the Greek (A.U.c. 514. B.C. 240), 
the only feat which he performed was, to attempt in the lan- 
guage of Rome what many of his contemporaries were in the 
habit of doing in the Greek language; at any rate, the plays of 
Menander and Philemon were the most usual gratification which 
an educated audience sought for in the theatres of Greek 
states, as well in Asia as in Italy. By viewing the case in this 
way, we assume at once the proper position for surveying the 
Latin comedians in all their relations to the Greek, which are so 
peculiar that they can only be developed under these limited 
historical conditions. For to take the two cases, which seem 
at first sight the most obvious and natural; namely, first, that 
translations of the plays of Menander, Philemon, &c., were sub- 
mitted to the educated classes at Rome; or secondly, that people 
attempted by free imitations to transplant these pieces into a 
Roman soil, and then to suit them to the tastes and under- 
standings of the Roman people by Romanizing them, not merely 
in all the allusions to national customs and regulations, but also 
in their spirit and character: neither of these two alternatives 
was adopted, but the Roman comedians took a middle course, in 
consequence of which these plays became Roman and yet re- 
mained perfectly Greek. In other words, in the Greek comedy 
(or comedia palliata, as it was called) of the Romans, the train- 
ing of Greece in general, and of Athens in particular, ex- 
tended itself to Rome, and compelled the Romans, so far as 
they wished to participate in that, in which all the educated 
world at that time participated, to acquiesce-in the outward 
forms and conditions of this drama ;—in its Greek costume and 
Athenian locality ; to adopt Attic life as a model of social ease 
and familiarity; and (to speak plainly) to consider themselves 
for an hour or two as mere barbarians,—and, in fact, the 
Roman comedians occasionally speak of themselves and their 
countrymen as barbari.’ 

It is necessary that we should premise these observations 
(however much they may seem chronologically misplaced), in 





1See Plautus, Bacchid. I. 2.15. Captivi. III, 1. 32. IV. 1. 104. Trinwmm. 
Prol. 19. Festus v. barbari and vapula. 


PUBLIC MORALITY AT ATHENS. 65. 


order to justify the use which we purpose to make of Plautus 
and Terence. ‘The Roman comedians prepared the Greek dish 
for the Roman palate in a different manner according to their 
own peculiar tastes ; for example, Plautus seasoned it with coarse 
and powerful condiments, Terence, on the other hand, with 
moderate and delicate seasoning ;’ but it still remained the 
Attic dish: the scene brought before the Roman public was 
Athens in the time of those Macedonian rulers who are called 
the Diadochi and Epigoni.’ 

§ 8. Consequently, the scene was Athens after the downfall 
of its political freedom and power, effected by the battle of 
Cheronea, and still more by the Lamian war: but it was 
Athens, still the city of cities, overflowing with population, 
flourishing with commerce, and strong in its navy, prosperous 
both as a state and in the wealth of many of its individual 
citizens.* This Athens, however, differed from that of Cimon 
and Pericles much in the same way as an old man weak in body, 
but full of a love of life, good-humoured and self-indulgent, 
differs from the vigorous middle-aged man at the summit of his 
bodily strength and mental energy. The qualities which were 
before singularly united in the Athenian character, namely, 
resolute bravery and subtlety of intellect, were now entirely dis- 
joined and separated. The former had taken up its abode with 
the homeless bands of mercenaries who practised war as a handi- 
craft, and it was only on impulses of rare occurrence that the 
people of Athens gave way to a warlike enthusiasm which was 
speedily kindled and as speedily quenched. But the excellent 
understanding and mother-wit of the Athenians, so far as they 
did not ramble in the schools of the philosophers and rheto- 





1 Yet Plautus is more frequently an imitator and a translator of the Attic come- 
dians than many persons have supposed. Not to speak of Terence, Ceecilius Statius 
has also followed very closely in the steps of Menander. 

2 So much so, that the most peculiar features of Attic law (as in all that related 
to ἐπίκληροι, or heiresses) and of the political relations of Athens (as the κληρουχία 
in Lemnos) play an important part in the Roman comedies. 

8 The finances of Athens were to all appearance as flourishing under Lycurgus 
(i.e. B.C. 338—326) as under Pericles. The well-known census under Demetrius 
the Phalerian (8.0. 317) gives a proof of the number of citizens and slaves at Athens. 
Even in the days of Demetrius Poliorcetes, Athens had still a great fleet. In a 
word, Athens did not want means at this time to enable her to command the 
respect even of kings; she only lacked the necessary spirit. 


Vot. II. F 


66 THE NEW COMEDY. 


ricians, found an object (now that there was so little in polities 
which could interest or employ the mind) in the occurrences of 
social life, and in the charm of dissolute enjoyments. 

Dramatic poetry now for the first time centred in Jove,’ as it 
has since done among all nations to whom Greek cultivation has 
descended ; but certainly it was not love in those nobler forms 
to which it has since elevated itself. The seclusion and want 
of all society in which unmarried women lived at Athens (such 
as we have before described it, in speaking of the poetry of 
Sappho)’ continued to prevail unaltered in the families of the 
citizens of Athens; according to these customs then, an amour 
of any continuance with the daughter of a citizen of Athens was 
out of the question, and never occurs in the fragments and imi- 
tations of the comedy of Menander; if the plot of the piece 
depends on the seduction of an Athenian damsel, this has taken 
place suddenly and without premeditation, in a fit of drunken- 
ness and youthful lust, generally at one of the pervigilia, which 
the religion of Athens had sanctioned from the earliest times: 
or some supposed slave or hefera, with whom the hero is des- 
perately in love, turns out to be a well-born Athenian maiden, 
and marriage at last crowns a connexion entered upon with very 
different intentions.’ 

The intercourse of the young men with the hetere, or 
courtesans, an intercourse which had always been a reproach to 
them since the days of Aristophanes,‘ had at length become a 
regular custom with the young people of the better class, whose 
fathers did not treat them too. parsimoniously. These courte- 
sans, who were generally foreigners or freed-women,’ possessed 
more or less education and charms of manner, and in proportion 
to these attractions, bound the young people to them with more 
or less of constancy and exclusiveness; their lovers found an 





1 Fabula jucundi nulla est sine amore Menandri. Ovid. 7rist,, II. 369. 

2 Chap, XIII, § 6, 

® This is the φθορὰ and the ἀναγνώρισις, which formed the basis of so many of 
Menander’s comedies, 

4 See 6, 9. Clouds, 996. 

5 This constitutes the essential distinction between the ἑταίρα and the πόρνη, the 
latter being a slave of the πορνοβοσκός (ὁ, ἡ, the leno or lena), although the πόρναι 


are often ransomed (torres) by their lovers, and so rise into the other more honour- 
able condition, 


PUBLIC MORALITY AT ATHENS. 67 


entertainment in their society which naturally rendered them 
little anxious to form a regular matrimonial alliance, especially 
as the legitimate daughters of Athenian citizens were still brought 
up in a narrow and limited manner, and with few accomplish- 
ments. The fathers either allowed their sons a reasonable 
degree of liberty to follow their own inclinations and sow their 
wild oats, or through parsimony or morose strictness endeavoured 
to withhold from them these indulgences, in the midst of all 
which it often happened that the old man fell into the very 
same follies which he so harshly reproved in his son. In these 
domestic intrigues the slaves exercised an extraordinary influence: 
even in Xenophon’s time, favoured by the spirit of democracy, 
and as it seems almost standing on the same footing with the 
meaner citizens, they were still more raised up by the growing 
degeneracy of manners, and the licence which universally pre- 
vailed. In these comedies, therefore, it often happens that a 
slave forms the whole plan of operations in an intrigue; it is” 
his sagacity alone which relieves his young master from some 
disagreeable embarrassment, and helps to put him in possession 
of the object of his love; at the same time we are often intro- 
duced to rational slaves, who try to induce their young masters 
to follow the suggestions of some sudden better resolution, and 
free themselves at once from the exactions of an unreasonable 
hetera.' No less important are the parasites, who, not to speak 
of the comic situations in which they are placed by their reso- 
lution to eat without labouring for it, are of great use to the 
comedian in their capacity as a sort of dependent on the family : 





1 As in Menander’s Zwnuch, in the scene of which Persius gives a miniature 
copy (Sat. V. 161), In this passage Persius has Menander immediately in his eye, 
and not the imitation in Terence’s Zunuch, act 1, sc. 1, although Terence’s Phedria, 
Parmeno, and Thais, correspond to the Cherestratus, Daos, and Chrysis of Me- 
nander. In Menander, however, the young man takes counsel with his slave at a 
time when the hetewra had shut him out, and on the supposition that she would 
invite him to come to her again; in Terence the lover is already invited to a 
reconciliation after a quarrel. This results from the adoption by Terence of a prae- 
tice common with the Latin comedians, and called contaminatio; he has here com- 
bined in one piece two of Menander’s comedies, the Zunuch and the Kolax. Ac- 
cordingly he is obliged to take up the thread of the Zunuch somewhat later, in order 
to gain more room for the developement of his double plot. In the same manner 
the Adelphi of Terence is made up from the Γεωργὸς of Menander and the 
Συναποθνήσκοντες of Diphilus. 

F 2 


Γ 


68 THE NEW COMEDY. 


they are brought into social relations of every kind, and are 
ready to perform any service for the sake of a feast. Of the 
characters who make their appearance less frequently, we will 
only speak here of the Bramarbas or miles gloriosus. He is no 
Athenian warrior, no citizen-soldier, like the heroes of the olden 
time, but a nameless leader of mercenaries, who enlists men-at- 
arms, now for king Seleucus, now for some other crowned 
general ; who makes much booty with little trouble in the rich 
provinces of Asia, and is willing to squander it away in lavish 
extravagance on the amiable courtesans of Athens ; who is always 
talking of his services, and has thereby habituated himself to 
continual boasting and bragging: consequently he is a demi- 
barbarian, over-reached by his parasite, and cheated at pleasure 


by some clever slave, and with many other traits of this kind. 


which may easily be derived from the Roman comedies, but can 
only be viewed in their right light by placing the character about 
one hundred years earlier.’ 

§ 9. This was the world in which Menander lived, and which, 
according to universal testimony, he painted so truly. Mani- 
festly, the motives here rested upon no mighty impulses, no 
grand ideas. The strength of the old Athenian principles and 
the warmth of national feelings had gradually grown fainter and 
weaker till they had melted down into a sort of philosophy of 
life, the main ingredients of which were a natural good temper 
and forbearance, and a sound mother-wit nurtured by acute ob- 
servation ; and its highest principle was that rule of ‘live and 
let live,’ which had its root in the old spirit of Attic democracy, 
and had been developed to the uttermost by the lax morality of 
subsequent times.” 

It is highly worthy of observation, as a hint towards appre- 
ciating the private life of this period, that Menander and Epi- 





1The ἀλάζων of Theophrastus (Charact. 23) has some affinity with the Thraso — 


of comedy (as Theophrastus’s characters in general are related to those of Menan- 


der), but he is an Athenian citizen who is proud of his connexion with Macedon, — 


and not a mercenary soldier. 


2 The aristocratic constitutions at that time in Greece were connected with a 


stricter superintendence of morals (censura morum) ; the leading principle of the 
Athenian democracy, on the other hand, was to impose no further restraint on the 


private life of the citizen than the immediate interests of the state required. How- — 
ever, the writings of the new comedy were not altogether without personal invee- 





ITS CHARACTER. 69 


curus were born in the same year at Athens, and spent their 
youth together as sharers in the same exercises (συνέφηβοι) :' 
and an intimate friendship united these two men, whose charac- 
ters had much in common. Though we should wrong them 
both if we considered them as slaves to any vulgar sensuality, 
yet it cannot be doubted that they were both of them deficient 
in the inspiration of high moral ideas. The intention with 
which each of them acted was the same: to make the most of 
life as it is, and to make themselves as agreeable as they could. 
They were both too refined and sensible to take any pleasure 
in vulgar enjoyments ; Menander knew so well by experience 
the deceitfulness of these gratifications, and felt so great a 
weariness and disgust of their charms, that he had arrived at a 
sort of passionless rest and moderation ;? though it is possible 
that in actual life Menander placed his happiness less in the 
painless tranquillity which Epicurus sought, than in various 
kinds of moderate gratification. It is known how much he 
gave himself up to intercourse with the hefere, not merely with 
the accomplished Glycera, but also with the wanton Thais; and 
his effeminate costume, according to a well-known βίου," 
offended even Demetrius of Phalerus, the regent of Athens 
under Cassander, who however led a sufficiently luxurious life 
himself. 

Such a philosophy of life as this, which places the summum 
bonum in a well-based love of self, could very well dispense 
with the gods, whom Epicurus transferred to the intermundane 
regions, because, according to his natural philosophy, he could 
not absolutely annihilate them. Agreeing entirely with his 
friend on this pot, Menander thought that the gods would 
have a life of trouble if they had to distribute good and evil 
for every day. It was on this account that the philosopher 





tives, and there were still questions with regard to the freedom of the comie stage 
(Plutarch Demetr. 12. Meineke Hist. Crit. Com. Gree. p. 436). The Latin come- 
dians also occasiunally introduced personal attacks, which were most bitter in the 
comedies of Nevius. 

1 Strabo XIV. p. 526. Meineke, Menandri et Philemonis fragm., p. χχν. 

2 The reader will find characteristic expressions of this luxurious philosophy in 
Meineke, Menandri fragm. p. 166. 3 Phedrus, fub., v. 1. 

* In a fragment which has recently come to light from the commentary of David 
on Aristotle’s Categories. See Meineke, Hist. Crit. Com. Grec., p. 454- 


70 THE NEW COMEDY. 


attributed so much to the influence of chance in the creation of 
the world and the destinies of mankind. Menander also exalts 
Τύχη (Fortune) as the sovereign of the world;' but this no 
longer implies the saviour daughter of almighty Zeus, but 
merely the causeless, incalculable, accidental combinations of 
things in nature and in the life of man. 

It was, however, precisely at such a time as this, when all 


relations were dislocated or merged in licentiousness, that 


comedy possessed a power, which, though widely different from 
the angry flashes of the genius of Aristophanes, perhaps pro- 
duced in its way more durable effects: this power was the 
power of ridicule, which taught people to dread as folly that 
which they no longer avoided as vice. This power was the 
more effective as it confined its operations to the sphere of the 
actual, and did not exhibit the follies which it represented under 
the same gigantic and superhuman forms as the old comedy. 
The old comedy, in its necessity for invention, created forms in 
which it could portray with most prominent features the cha- 
racteristics of whole classes and species of men; the new 
comedy took its forms, in all their individual peculiarities, from 
real life, and did not attempt to signify by them more than 
individuals of the particular class.2, On this account more im- 
portance was attached by the writers of the new comedy to the 
invention of plots, and to their dramatic complication and solu- 
tion, which Menander made the leading object in his composi- 
tions: for, while the old comedy set its forms in motion in a 
very free and unconstrained manner, according as the develop- 
ment of the fundamental thought required, the new comedy 
was subject to the laws of probability as established by the 
progress of ordinary life, and had to invent a story in which all 
the views of the persons and all the circumstances of their 
actions resulted from the characters, manners, and relations of 
the age. The stretch of attention on the part of the spectator 
which Aristophanes produced by the continued progression in 
the development of the comic ideas of his play was effected in 
the new comedy by the confusion and solution of outward dif- 





1 Meineke, Menandri fragm., p. 168. 
? Hence the exclamation: ὦ Mévavdpe καὶ Ble. 


iti Χο . ... 


ITS CHARACTER. 71 


ficulties in the circumstances represented, and by the personal 
interest felt for the particular characters by the spectators,—an 
interest closely connected with the illusion of reality. 

In this the attentive reader of these observations will readily 
have perceived how comedy, thus conducted by Menander and 
Philemon, only completed what Euripides had begun on the 
tragic stage a hundred years before their time. Euripides, too, 
deprived his characters of that ideal grandeur which had been 
most conspicuous in the creations of Aischylus, and gave them 
more of human weakness, and therefore of apparent indi- 
viduality. He also abandoned the foundation of national 
principles in ethics and religion on which the old popular 
morality of the Greeks had been built up, and subjected all 
relations to a dialectical, and sometimes sophistical mode of 
reasoning, which very soon led to the lax morality and common 
sense doctrines which prevailed in the new comedy. Euripides 
and Menander consequently agree so well in their reasonings 
and sentences, that in their fragments it would be easy to con- 
fuse one with the other; and thus tragedy and comedy, these 
two forms of the drama which started from such different be- 
ginnings, here meet as it were in one point.’ The form of the 
diction also contributed a great deal to this: for as Euripides 
lowered the poetic tone of tragedy to the ordinary language of 
polished society, in the same way comedy, even the middle,* 
but still more the new, relinquished, on the one hand, 
the high poetic tone which Aristophanes had aimed at, espe- 
cially in Kis choral songs, and, on the other hand, the spirit of 
caricature and burlesque which is essentially connected with 
the portraiture of his characters: the tone of polished conver- 
sation® predominates in all the pieces of the new comedy ; and 
in this Menander gave a greater freedom and liveliness to the 
recitations of his actors by the looser structure of his sentences 
and the weaker connexion of his periods; whereas Philemon’s 





1 Philemon was so warm an admirer of Euripides, that he declared he would at 
once destroy himself, in order to see Euripides in the other world, provided he 
could convince himself that departed spirits preserved their life and understanding. 
See Meineke, Men. et Philem. Rel., p. 410. 

3 According to Anonymus de Comedia, p. xxviii. 

3 This is particularly mentioned by Plutarch (Aristoph. et Menandri compar, c. 2.) 


72 THE NEW COMEDY. 


pieces, by their more connected and periodic style, were better 
suited for the closet than for the stage.’ The Latin comedians, 
Plautus, for instance, gave a great deal more of burlesque than 
they found in their models, availing themselves perhaps of the 
Sicilian comedy of Epicharmus, as well as of the comedy of their 
own country. The elevated poetic tone must have been lost 
with the choruses, of which we have no sure traces even in the 
middle comedy ;? the connexion of lyric and dramatic poetry 
was limited to the employment by the actors of lyric measures 
of different kinds, and they expressed their feelings at the 
moment by singing these lyrical pieces, and accompanying them 
with lively gesticulations: in this the model was rather the 
monodies of Euripides than the lyrical passages in Aristo- 
phanes. ‘ 

We have now brought down the history of the Attic drama 
from Aischylus to Menander, and in naming these two extreme 
points of the series through which dramatic poetry developed 
itself, we cannot refrain from reminding our readers what a 
treasure of thought and life is here unfolded to us; what re- 
markable changes were here effected, not only in the forms of. 
poetry, but in the inmost recesses of the constitution of the 
Greek mind; and what a great and significant portion of the 
history of our race is here laid before us in the most vivid 
delineations. 





1 According to a remark of the so named Demetrius Phaler. de Hlocut., § 193. 

2 According to Platonius, the middle comedy had no parabases, because there 
was no chorus. The olosicon was quite without choral songs. The new come- 
dians, in imitation of the older writers, wrote ΧΟΡΟΣ at the end of the acts; pro- 
bably the pause was filled up by the performance of a flute-player. At any rate, 
such was the custom at Rome. Evanthius (de Comed., p. lv. in Westerton’s 
Terence) seems to mean the same. 


73 


CHAPTER XXX. 


LYRIC AND EPIC POETRY DURING THIS PERIOD. 


§ 1. The Dithyramb becomes the chief form of Athenian lyric poetry. Lasus of 
Hermione. ὃ 2. New style ofthe dithyramb introduced by Melanippides. Phi- 
loxenus. Cinesias. Phrynis. Timotheus. Polyeidus. § 3. Mode of pro- 
ducing the new dithyramb: its contents and character. § 4. Reflective lyric 
poetry. ὃ 5. Social and political elegies. The Zyde of Antimachus essentially 
different. ὃ 6, Epic poetry. Panyasis, Cheerilus, Antimachus. 


§ 1. HE Drama was so well adapted to reflect the thoughts 

and feelings of the people of Attica in the mirror of 
poetry, that other sorts of metrical composition fell completely 
into the background, and for the public in general assumed 
the character rather of isolated and momentary gratifications 
than that of a poetic expression of prevailing sentiments and 
principles, 

However, Lyric poetry was improved in a very remarkable 
manner, and struck out tones which seized with new power upon 
the spirit of the age. This was principally effected by the new 
Dithyramb, the cradle and home of which was Athens, before all 
the cities of Greece, even though some of the poets who adopted 
this form were not born there. 

As we have remarked above,' Lasus of Hermione, the rival of 
Simonides, and the teacher of Pindar, in those early days ex- 
hibited his dithyrambs chiefly at Athens, and even in his poems 
the dithyrambic rhythm had gained the greater freedom by 
which it was from thenceforth characterized. Still the dithy- 
rambs of Lasus were not generically different from those of 
Pindar, of which we still possess a beautiful fragment. This 
dithyramb was designed for the vernal Dionysia at Athens, and 
it really seems to breathe the perfumes and smile with the bright- 
ness of spring. The rhythmical structure of the fragment is 
bold and rich, and a lively and almost violent motion prevails 





1 Chap. XIV. § 14. 2 See above, chap. XIV. § 7. 


74 LYRIC AND EPIC POETRY DURING THIS PERIOD. 


in it;' but this motion is subjected to the constraint of fixed 
laws, and all the separate parts are carefully incorporated in 
the artfully constructed whole. We also see from this frag- 
ment that the strophes of the dithyrambic ode were already 
made very long; from principles, however, which will be stated 
in the sequel, we must conclude that there were antistrophes 
corresponding to these strophes. 

§ 2. The dithyramb assumed a new character in the hands of 
Metanteripes of Melos. He was maternal grandson of the 
older Melanippides, who was born about Ol. 65. B.c. 520, and 
was contemporary with Pindar ;? the younger and more cele- 
brated Melanippides lived for a long period with Perdiccas, king 
of Macedon, who reigned from about Ol. 81, 2. B.c. 454, to Ol. 
ΟἹ, 2. B.C. 4143 consequently, before and during the greater part 
of the Peloponnesian war. The comic poet Pherecrates (who, 
like Aristophanes, was in favour of maintaining the old simple 
music as an essential part of the old-fashioned morality) con- 
siders the corruption of the ancient musical modes as having 
commenced with him. Closely connected with this change is 
the increasing importance of instrumental music; in conse- 
quence of which the fiute-players, after the time of Mela- 
nippides, no longer received their hire as mere secondary persons 
and assistants, from the poets themselves, but were paid imme- 
diately by the managers of the festival.’ 

Melanippides was followed by Puttoxenvus of Cythera, first his 
slave and afterwards his pupil, who is ridiculed by Aristophanes in 
his later plays, and especially in the Plutus. He lived, at a later 
period, at the court of Dionysius the elder, and is said to have 
taken all sorts of liberties with the tyrant, who sometimes in- 
dulged in poetry as an amateur; but he had to pay for this dis- 





1 The peeonic species of rhythms, to which the ancients especially assign ‘the 
splendid,’ (τὸ μεγαλοπρεπές), is the prevailing one in this fragment. 

? That the younger Melanippides is the person with whom, according to the cele- 
brated verses of Pherecrates, (Plutarch de Musica, 30. Meineke, Fr. Com. Gr., 
vol. ΤΙ, p. 326), the corruption of music begins, is clear, partly from the direct 
statement of Suidas, partly from his chronological relation to Cinesias and Phi- 
loxenus. The celebrated Melanippides was also the contemporary of Thucydides 
(Marcellin. V. Thucyd. § 29), and of Socrates, (Xenoph. Mem., I. 4, ὃ 3.) 

3 Plutarch, de Mus. § 30. 

4 Aristoph. Plut. 290; and see Schol. 





THE DITHYRAMB. 75 


tinction by confinement to the stone-quarries at Syracuse, when 
the tyrant was in a bad humour. He died Ol. 100, 1. B.c. 
380.' His Dithyrambs enjoyed the greatest reputation all over 
Greece, and it is remarkable that while Aristophanes speaks of 
him as a bold innovator, Antiphanes, the poet of the middle 
comedy, praises his music as already the genuine style of music, 
and calls Philoxenus himself, ‘a god among men; whereas he 
calls the music and lyric poetry of his own time a flowery style 
of composition, which adorns itself with foreign melodies.’ 

In the series of the corrupters of music, Pherecrates, in the 
passage already quoted, mentions, next to Melanippides, ΟἸΝΈΒΙΑΒ, 
whom Aristophanes also ridicules about the middle of the Pelo- 
ponnesian war,* on account of his pompous, and at the same 
time empty diction, and also for his rhythmical imnovations. 
‘ Our art,’ he there says, ‘ has its origin in the clouds: for the 
splendid passages of the dithyrambs must be aerial, and obscure ; 
azure-radiant, and wing-wafted.’? Plato‘ designedly brings for- 
ward Cinesias as a poet who obviously attached no importance 
to making his hearers better, but only sought to please the 
greater number: just as his father Meles, who sang to the harp, 
had wished only to please the common people, but, as Plato 
sarcastically adds, had done just the reverse, and had only 
shocked the ears of his audience. 

Next to Cynesias, Purynis is arraigned by the personification 
of Music, who comes forward as the accuser in the lines of Phe- 
recrates, of being one of her worst tormentors, ‘ who had quite 
annihilated her with his twistings and turnings, since he had 
twelve modes on five strings.’ This Phrynis was a later off- 
shoot of the Lesbian school; he was a singer to the harp, who 
was born at Mitylene, and won his first victory at the musical 
contests which Pericles had introduced at the -Panathenza ;° 
he flourished before and during the Peloponnesian war. The 





1 Fifty-five years old, Marm. Par. ep. 69. 

3 Athen. XIV. p. 643, Ὁ. 

8 Birds, 1382. Com. Clouds, 332. Peace, 832. 

4 Gorgias, p. 501, D. 

δ᾽ Ἐπὶ Καλλίου ἄρχοντος. Schol. Clouds, 976. But no Callias answers to the time 
when Pericles was agonothetes, and built the Odeium, (about Ol. 84, Plutarch, 
Pericl. 13), and it is probable that we should substitute the archon Callimachus 
Ol. 83, 3.) for Callias. 


76 LYRIC AND EPIC POETRY DURING THIS PERIOD. 


alteration in the old nomes of Terpander, which originally 
formed the conventional basis of harp-music, is ‘attributed 
to him.’ 

Timornevs of Miletus? formed himself after the model of 
Phrynis; at a later period he gained the victory over his master 
in the musical contests, and raised himself to the highest rank 
among dithyrambic poets. He is the last of the musical artists 
censured by Pherecrates, and died in extreme old age in OL 
105, 4. B.c. 357.2. Although the Ephors at Sparta are said to 
have taken from his harp four of its eleven strings, Greece in 
general received his innovations in music with the most cordial 
approbation ; he was one of the most popular musicians of his 
time. The branches of poetry, which he worked out in the 
spirit of his own age, were in general the same which Terpander 


cultivated 400 years before, namely, Nomes,* Proems, and Hymns. . 


There were still some antique forms which he too was obliged 
to observe; for instance, the hexameter verse was not quite 
given up by Timotheus in his nomes; but he recited them in 
the same manner as the Dithyramb, and mixed up this metre 
with others.’ The branch of poetry which he chiefly cultivated, 
and which gave its colour to all the others, was undoubtedly 
the Dithyramb. 

Timotheus, too, was worsted, if not before the tribunal of 
impartial judges, at least in the favour of the public, by 
Potyerpus, whose scholar Philotas also won the prize from 
Timotheus in a musical contest.’ Polyeidus was also regarded 
as one of those whose artificial innovations were injurious to 
music, but he also gained a great reputation among the Greeks, 





1 Plutarch, de Mus. 6. 

2 See, besides the better known passages, Aristot. Metaphys. A. ἔλαττον, c. 1. 

3 Marm. Par. 76. Suidas perhaps places his death most correctly at the age 
of 97. 

4 Steph. Byz. v. Μίλητος, attributes to him 18 books of νόμοι κιθαρῳδικοὶ, in 8000 
verses ; where the expression ἔπη is not to be taken strictly to signify the hexa- 
meter, although this metre was mixed up in them. 

5 Plut. de Mus. 4. Timotheus’s Nome, ‘the Persians,’ began ; K)\ewdv ἐλευθερίας 
τεύχων μέγαν Ἑλλάδι κόσμον, Pausan. VIII., 50, ὃ 3. 

6 Atheneus, VIII. p. 352, B. Comp. Plutarch, de Mus. 21. It is clear that he 
is not the same as the tragedian and sophist Polyeidus, mentioned in Aristotle’s 
Poetic. Aristotle would hardly have given the name ὁ σοφιστὴς to a dithyrambie 
poet whose pursuit was chiefly the study of music. 





a 


EXHIBITION OF THE DITHYRAMB. vd 


There was nothing which so much delighted the crowded audi- 
ences which flocked to the theatres throughout Greece as the 
Dithyrambs of Timotheus and Polyeidus.’ 

Besides these poets and musicians there was still a long 
series of others, among whom we may name Ion of Chios, who 
was also a favourite dithyrambic poet ;? Diacoras of Melos, 
the notorious sceptic;* the highly-gifted Licymnivs of Chios, 
(whose age is not accurately known) ; Crexus, also accused of 
innovations ; and Tetestes of Selinus, a poetic opponent of 
Melanippides,* who gained a victory at Athens in Ol. 94, 3. B.c. 
401. : 

§ 3. It is far more important, however, to obtain a clear 
conception of the more recent Dithyramb in all its peculiarities. 
This we shall be better able to do by first establishing some of 
the main points of the question. 

With regard to the mode of exhibition, the Dithyrambs at 
Athens, during the Peloponnesian war, were still represented by 
choruses furnished by the ten tribes for the Dionysian festivals ; 
consequently, the dithyrambic poets were also called Cyclic 
chorus-teachers :° but the more liberty they gave to the metre, 
the more various their rhythmical alterations, so much the more 
difficult was the exhibition by means of a complete chorus; and 
so much the more common it became to get the Dithyramb 
performed by private amateurs.’ The Dithyramb also entirely 
gave up the antistrophic repetition of the same metres, and 
moved on in rhythms which depended entirely on the humour 
and caprice of the poet ;’ it was particularly characterized by 
certain runs by way of prelude, which were called ἀναβολαί, and 





1 Tn a Cretan decree, (Corp. Inscr. Gr. N. 305,) one Menecles of Teos is praised 
for having often played on the harp at Cnossus after the style of Timotheus, Poly- 
eidus, and the old Cretan poets (chap. XII. § 9). 

2 Comp. chap. VI. § 2. 

3 The most important fragments of his lyric poems are given by the Epicurean, 
Pheedrus, in the papyri brought from Herculaneum (Herculanensia, ed. Drummond 
et Walpole, p. 164). 

4 Athen. XIV. p. 616, E, relates, in very pretty verses, a contest between the 
two poets, on the question whether Minerva had rejected the tlute-accompani- 
ment. 

5 Aristoph. Birds, 1403. 

6 Aristotle speaks of this alteration, Problem. 19, 15. Comp. Rhetor, 111. 9. 

7 ἀπολελυμένα, 


78 LYRIC AND EPIC POETRY DURING THIS PERIOD. 


which are much censured by strict judges,’ but doubtless were 
listened to with avidity hy the public in general. In this the 
poet had nothing to hinder him from passing from one musical 
note to another, or from combining various rhythms in the same 
poem ; so that at last all the constraints of mere metre seemed 
to vanish, and poetry in its very highest flight seemed to meet 
the opposite extreme of prose, as the old critics remark. 

At the same time the Dithyramb assumed a descriptive, or, 
as Aristotle says, a mimetic character? The natural phe- 
nomena which it described were imitated by means of tunes 
and rhythms, and the pantomimic gesticulations of the actors, 
‘(as in the antiquated Hyporcheme) ; and this was very much 
aided by a powerful instrumental accompaniment, which sought 
to represent with its loud full tones the raging elements, the 
voices of wild beasts, and other sounds,* 

With regard to the contents or subject of this dithyrambic 
poetry, in this it was based upon the compositions of Xenocritus, 
Simonides, and other old poets, who had taken subjects for the 
Dithyramb from the ancient heroic mythology. The Dithy- 
rambs of Melanippides announce this even by their titles, such 
as Marsyas, (in which, by a modification of the legend, Athena 
invents the flute, and on her throwing it away it is taken up by 
Marsyas,) Persephone, and the Danaides. The Cyclops of 
Philoxenus was in great repute; in this the poet, who was well 
known in Sicily, introduced the beautiful Sicilian story of the 
love of the Cyclops Polyphemus for the sea-nymph Galatea, 
who on account of the beautiful Acis rejects his suit, till at last 
he takes deadly vengeance on his successful rival. From the 
verses in Aristophanes in which Philoxenus is parodied,’ we 





1 ἡ μακρὰ ἀναβολὴ τῷ ποιήσαντι κακίστη : an hexameter with a peculiar synizesis. 

2 This is called μεταβολή. The fragments of the dithyrambic poets consequently 
contain also many pieces in simple Doric rhythms. 

% Plato (Resp. p. 396) alludes to this imitation of storms, roaring torrents, 
lowing herds, &c., in the Dithyrambs. A parasite wittily observed of one of 
these storm-dithyrambs of Timotheus, that ‘he had seen greater storms, than 
those which Timotheus made, in many a kettle of boiling water.’ Athen. VIII. 
p- 338, A. 

4 Chap. XIV. ὃ τι. comp. XXT. § 4. 

5 Plutus, 290. The songs of the sheep and goats, which the chorus was there 
to bleat forth to please Carion, refer to the imitations of these animals in the Dithy- 
ramb, 


CONTENTS OF THE DITHYRAMB. 79 


may pretty well see in what spirit this subject was treated. 
The Cyclops was represented as a harmless monster, a good- 
natured Caliban, who roams about the mountains followed by 
his bleating sheep and goats as if they were his children, and 
collects wild herbs in his wallet, and then half-drunk lays him- 
self down to sleep in the midst of his flocks. In his love he 
becomes even poetical, and comforts himself for his rejection 
with songs which he thinks quite beautiful; even his lambs 
sympathize with his sorrows and bleat longingly for the fair 
Galatea.’ In this whole poem (the subject of which Theocritus 
took up at a later period and with better taste formed it into 
an Idyll*) the ancients discerned» covert allusions to the con- 
nexion of the poet with Dionysius, the poetizing tyrant of Sicily, 
who is said to have deprived Philoxenus of the object of his 
love. If we add to this the statement that Timotheus’ Dithy- 
ramb, ‘the travails of Semele,’* passed with the ancients for 
an indecent and unimaginative representation of such a scene,’ 
we shall have the means of forming a satisfactory judgment of 
the general nature of this new Dithyramb. There was no unity 
of thought; no one tone pervading the whole poem, so as to 
preserve in the minds of the hearers a consistent train of feelings; 
no subordination of the story to certain ethical ideas ; no arti- 
ficially constructed system of verses regulated by fixed laws ; 
but a loose and wauton play of lyrical sentiments, which were 
set in motion by the accidental impulses of some mythical story, 
and took now one direction, now another ; preferring, however, 
to seize on such points as gave room for an immediate imitation 
in tones, and admitting a mode of description which luxuriated 
in sensual charms. Many monodies in the later tragedies of 
Euripides, such as Aristophanes ridicules in the Frogs, have 
this sensual colouring, and in this want of a firm basis to rest 
upon have quite the character of the contemporary Dithyramb, 
of which they perhaps furnish a most vivid picture. 





1 Hermesianax, FPragm. v. 74. 

3 Theocrit. Jd. xi., where the reader should consult the scholia. 

8 Σεμέλης ὠδίς. 

4 Of this the witty Stratonicus said, ‘could she have cried out more piteously, 
if she had been bringing forth not a God, but a common mechanic?’ Athen. VIII. 
p. 352, A. Ina similar spirit Polyeidus made Atlas a shepherd in Libya. Tzetz. 
on Lycophr. 879. 


80 LYRIC AND EPIC POETRY DURING THIS PERIOD. 


§ 4. From these productions of Euripides which intrude on 
the domain of lyric poetry, we may also observe that, in addition 
to this pictorial delineation of sensible impressions, a species of 
reflexion which set about analysing and dissecting everything, 
and a sort of transcendental reasoning, had established them- 
selves also in the lyric poetry of the time. The Dithyramb 
furnished less room for this than the other more tranquil forms 
of poetry. We call attention especially to the abstract subjects 
introduced into the encomiastic poetry, which was exhibited 
under the form of Peans, such as Health, and others of the same 
kind, which were in fashion at the time. We have several 
verses of a similar poem by Licymnius,' most of which are 
contained in a short pean on health, by AripHron, which has 
been preserved, and in which we are told with perfect truth, 
but at the same time in the most insipid manner, that neither 
wealth, nor power, nor any other human bliss, can be properly 
enjoyed without health.2. The Peean or scolinm on ‘ Virtue’ 
by the great Arisrorie is no doubt lyric in form, but quite as 
abstract as these in its composition. Virtue, at the beginning 
of the ode, is ostentatiously represented with all the warmth of 
inspiration as a young beauty, to die for whom is considered in 
Hellas as an enviable lot: and the series of mighty heroes who 
had suffered and died for her is closed by a transition, which, 
though abrupt, no doubt proceeded from the deepest feelings of 
Aristotle, to the praise of his noble-minded friend Hermeias, the 
ruler of Atarneus. . 

§ 5. The Elegy still continued a favourite poetical amusement 
while Attic literature flourished ; it remained true to its original 
destination, to enliven the banquet and to shed the gentle light 
of a higher poetic feeling over the convivialities of the feast. 
Consequently, the fragments of elegies of this time by Ion of 
Chios, Dionysius of Athens, Evenus the sophist of Paros, and 
Caitias of Athens, all speak much of wine, of the proper mede 
of drinking, of dancing and singing at banquets, of the cottabus- 
game, which young people were then so fond of, and of other 
things of the same kind, and they took as their subject the joys 





1 Sextus Empiricus adv. Mathematicos, p. 447 ¢. 
2 Athen. XV. p. 702, A. Boeckh. Corp: Inscript. I. p. 477, seqg. Schneidewin 
Delectus poes. Gr. eleg. iamb. melice, p. 450. 


SOCIAL AND POLITICAL ELEGIES. 81 


of the banquet and the right measure to be observed at it. 
This elegiac poetry proceeds on the principle that we should 
enjoy ourselves in society, combining the pleasures of the senses 
with intellectual gratifications, and not forgetting our higher 
calling in the midst of such enjoyments. ‘ To drink and sport 
and be right-minded ’—is the expression of Ion.’ As however 
the thoughts easily passed from the festal board to the general 
social and political interests of the time, the elegy had political 
features also, and statesmen often expressed in this form their 
Opinions on the course to be adopted for Greece in general and 
for the different republics in particular. This must have been 
the case with the elegies of Dionysius, who was a considerable 
statesman of the time of Pericles, and led the Athenians who 
settled at Thurii, in the great Hellenic migration to that place. 
The Athenians by way of joke called him ‘ the man of copper,’ 
because he had proposed the introduction of a copper coinage 
in addition to the silver money which had been exclusively used 
before that time. It is to be wished that we had the continu- 
ation of that elegy of Dionysius which ran thus: ‘ Come here, 
and listen to good intelligence: adjust your cup-battles, give all 
your attention to me, and listen.?? The political tendency 
appeared still more clearly in the elegies of Crirras, the son of 
Callzeschrus, in which he said bluntly that he had recommended 
in the public assembly that Alcibiades should be recalled and 
had drawn up the decree. The predilection for Lacedemon, 
which Critias had imbibed as one of the Eupatride and as a 
friend of Socrates, declares itself in his commendations of the 
old customs which the Spartans kept up at their banquets: ἡ 
nevertheless we have no right to suppose in this an early mani- 
festation of the ill-affected and treasonable opinions with regard 
to the democracy of Athens, which only gradually and through 
the force of circumstances developed themselves in the character 
of Critias with the fearful consequences which often convert a 
single false step of the politician into a disastrous and criminal 
progress for the rest of his life. 





1 πίνειν καὶ παίζειν καὶ τὰ δίκαια φρονεῖν. 2 Athen. XV. p. 669, Β. 
3 Plutarch, Alcib. 33. 4. Athen. Χ, p. 432, Ὁ. 
Vou. 11. G 


82 LYRIC AND EPIC POETRY DURING THIS PERIOD. 


_ From this elegiac poetry, which was cultivated in the circle 
of Attic training, we must carefully distinguish the elegies of 
Antimacuvs of Colophon, which we may term a revival of the 
love-sorrows of Mimnermus. Antimachus, who flourished after 
Ol. 94, B.c. 404, was in general a reviver of ancient poetry, one 
who, keeping aloof from the stream of the new-fashioned literature, 
applied himself exclusively to his own studies, and on that very 
account found little sympathy among the people of his own time, 
as indeed appears from the well-known story that, when he was 
reciting his Thebais, all his audience left the room with the 
single exception of Plato. His elegiac poem was called Lyde, 
and was dedicated to the remembrance of a Lydian maiden whom 
Antimachus had loved and early lost.’ The whole work, therefore, 
was a lamentation for her loss, which doubtless gained life and 
warmth from the longing and eyer-recurring recollections of the 
poet. Itis true that Antimachus, as we are told, availed himself 
largely of mythical materials in the execution of his poem, but if 
he had only adorned the general thought, that his love had caused 
him sorrow, with examples of the similar destiny of others, his 
poem could not possibly have gained the reputation which it en- 
joyed in ancient times. 

§ 6. Here we must resume the thread of our history of Epic 
poetry, which we dropped with Pisander (chapter IX.). Epic 
poetry, however, did not slumber in the meantime, but found an 
utterance in Panyasis of Halicarnassus, the uncle of Herodotus 
(fl. Ol. 78, B.c. 468°) in Cua@ritus of Samos, a contemporary of 
Lysander (about Ol. 94, B.c. 404), and in Antimacuus of Co- 
lophon, just mentioned, whose younger days coincide with the 
old age of Cheerilus ;* these poets, however, were received by the 
public with an indifference fully equal to the general attention 
and admiration which the Homeric poems had excited. The 





1 According to the passage in Hermesianax. 

? This date is given by Suidas ; somewhat later, (about ΟἹ. 82,) Panyasis was 
put to death by Lygdamis, the tyrant of Halicarnassus, whom Herodotus afterwards 
expelled. 

3 When Lysander was in Samos as the conqueror of Athens, Cheerilus was then 
with him, and in the musical contests which Lysander established there, Antima- 
chus, son of Niceratus, from Heraclea, then a young man, was one of the defeated 
poets. Plutarch, Lysander, 18. 


EN Ee eS χόω νων 


EPIC POETRY. 83 


Alexandrian school was the first to bring them into notice, and 
the critics of this school placed Panyasis and Antimachus, 
together with Pisander, in the first rank of epic poets. On this 
account also we have proportionally few fragments of these poets; 
most of the citations from them are made only for the sake of 
learned illustrations; but little has come down to us, which 
could give us a conception of their general style and art. 

Panyasis comprised in his Hercules a great mass of mythical 
legends, and was chiefly occupied with painting in romantic 
colours the adventures of this hero in the most distant regions 
of the world. ‘The description of the mighty feats of this hero, 
of his athletic strength and invincible courage, was no doubt 
relieved or softened down by pictures of a very different kind ; 
such as those in which Panyasis gave life to a feast where 
Hercules was present, by recounting the pleasant speeches of 
the valiant banqueters, or painted in warm colours the thraldom 
of Hercules to Omphale which brought him to Lydia. 

In a great epic poem called Jonica, Panyasis took for his 
subject the early history of the Ionians in Asia Minor, and 
their wanderings and settlements under the guidance of Neleus 
and others of the descendants of Codrus. 

Cueritus of Samos formed the grand plan of exalting in 
epic poetry the greatest, or at least the most joyful event of 
Greek history, the expedition of Xerxes, king of Persia, against 
Greece. We could not blame this choice, even though we con- 
sidered the historical epos, properly so called, an unnatural 
production. But the Persian war was in its leading features 
an event of such simplicity and grandeur,—the despot of the 
East leading against the free republics of Greece countless 
hosts of people who had no will of their own,—and besides 
this, the subordinate details had been cast into such darkness 
and obscurity by the infinite multiplication of stories among 
the Greeks, that it gave room for an absolutely poetic treat- 
ment. If Aristotle is right in asserting that poetry 15 more 
philosophical than history, because it contains more general 
truth, it must be admitted that events like the Persian war 
place themselves on the same footing with poetry, or with a 
history naturally poetical. Whether Cheerilus, however, con- 
ceived this subject in all its grandeur, and considered it with 

G 2 


84 LYRIC AND EPIC POETRY DURING THIS PERIOD. 


equal liveliness and vigour in its higher and lower relations, 
cannot now be determined, as the few fragments refer to par- 
ticulars only, and generally to subordinate details.’ It is a bad 
symptom that Cherilus should complain, in the first verses of 
his poem, that the subjects of epic poetry were already ex- 
hausted : this could not have been his motive if he had under- 
taken to paint the greatest deeds of the Greeks. But, in general, 
a striving after novelty seems to have produced marked effects 
upon his works, both in general and in the details. Aristotle 
finds fault with his comparisons as far-fetched and obscure ;* 
and even the fragments have been sometimes justly censured 
for their forced and artificial tone.*. 

The Thebais of ANtIMAcHUs was formed on a wide and com- 
prehensive plan; there was mythological lore in the execution 
of the details, and careful study in the choice of expressions ; 
but the whole poem was deficient, according to the judgment of 
the ancient critics, in that natural connexion which arrests and 
detains the attention, and in that charm of poetic feeling which 
no laborious industry or elaborate refinement can produce.’ 
Hadrian, therefore, remained true to his predilection for every- 
thing showy, affected, and unnatural, when he placed Anti- 
machus before Homer, and attempted an epic imitation of the 
style of the former.° 





1 Tt is clear that the Athenians did not pay Cheerilus a golden stater for every 
verse, as has been inferred from Suidas: it is obvious that this is a confusion with 
the later Cheerilus, whom Alexander rewarded in so princely a manner. Horat, 
Ep. IL. 1, 233. 

2°A μάκαρ ὅστις ἔην κεῖνον χρόνον ἴδρις ἀοιδῶν 
Μουσάων θεράπων, ὅτ᾽ ἀκήρατος ἣν ἔτι λειμών. 
νῦν δ᾽ ὅτε πάντα δέδασται, ἔχουσι δὲ πείρατα τέχναι, 
ὕστατοι αὖτε δρόμου καταλειπόμεθ᾽" οὐδέ πῃ ἔστιν 
πάντῃ παπταίνοντα νεοζυγὲς ἅρμα πελάσσαι. 
These verses are preserved in the Scholiast to Aristot. Rhet. III. 14, § 4, in Gais- 
ford’s Animadversiones (Oxon. 1820). Compare Naeke’s Cherilus, p. 104. 
3 Aristot. Topic. VIII. 1. 
4A. F. Naeke, Cherili Samii que supersunt. Lips. 1817. 
5 Antimachi Colophonii reliquie, ed. Schellenberg, p. 38, seq. 
5 Spartianus in the Life of Hadrian, c. 15. The title of Hadrian’s work is now 
known to have been Catachane ; the poem probably had some resemblance to the 
Catonis Dire of Valerius, 








85 


CHAPTER XXXI. 


POLITICAL ORATORY AT ATHENS PREVIOUSLY TO THE 
INFLUENCE OF RHETORIC. 


§ 1. Importance of prose at this period. § 2. Oratory at Athens rendered neces 
sary by the democratical form of government. § 3. Themistocles; Pericles: 
power of their oratory. § 4. Characteristics of their oratory in relation to their 
opinions and modes of thought. § 5. Form and style of their speeches. 


δι 1. E have seen both tragedy and comedy im their latter 
days gradually sinking into prose; and this has 
shown us that prose was the most powerful instrument in the 
literature of the time, and has made us the more curious to in- 
vestigate its tendency, its progress, and its development. 

The cultivation of prose belongs almost entirely to the period 
which intervened between the Persian war and the time of 
Alexander the Great. Before this time every attempt at prose 
composition was either so little removed from the colloquial 
style of the day, as to forfeit all claim to be considered as a 
written language, properly so called: or else owed all its charms 
and splendour to an imitation of the diction and the forms of 
words found in poetry, which attained to completeness and 
maturity many hundred years before the rise of a prose 
literature. 

In considering the history of Attic prose, we propose to give 
a view of the general character of the works of the prose writers, 
and their relation to the circumstances of the Athenian people, 
to their intellectual energy and elasticity, and to the mixture of 
reason and passion which was so conspicuous among them. But 
it is obvious that it will not be possible to do this without care- 
fully examining the contents, the subjects, and the practical and 
theoretical objects of these works. 

We may distinguish three epochs in the general history of 
Attic prose, from Pericles to Alexander the Great: the first that 
of Pericies himself, AntrpHon, and Tuucypipss; the second, 
that of Lystas, Isocrarzs, and Piato; the third, that of De. 


86 POLITICAL ORATORY AT ATHENS. 


MOSTHENES, AscuinEs, and DemaprEs. The sequel will show 
why we have selected these names. 

Two widely different causes co-operated in introducing the 
first epoch :—Athenian politics and Sicilian sophistry. We 
must first take a view of these two causes. 

§ 2. Since the time of Solon, the most distinguished states- 
men of Athens had formed some general views with regard to 
the destination of their native city, based upon a profound con- 
sideration of the external relations and internal resources of 
Attica, and the peculiar capabilities of the inhabitants. An 
extension of the democracy, industry, and trade, and, above all, 
the sovereignty of the sea, were the primary objects which those 
statesmen proposed to themselves. Some peculiar views were 
transmitted through a series of statesmen,’ from Solon to 
Themistocles and Pericles, and were from time to time further 
developed and extended; and though an opposite party in 
politics. (that of Aristides and Cimon) endeavoured to set 
bounds to this development, the point for which they contended 
did not affect any one of the leading principles which guided the 
other party; they only wished to moderate the suddenness and 
violence of the movement. 

This deep reflection on: and clear perception of what was 
needful for Athens, imparted to the speeches of men like 
Themistocles and Pericles a power and solidity which made a 
far deeper impression on the people of Athens than any par- 
ticular proposal or counsel could have done. Public speaking 
had been common in Greece from the earliest times; long 
before popular assemblies had gained the sovereign power by 
the establishment of democracy, the ancient kings had been in 
the habit of addressing their people, sometimes with that natural 
eloquence which Homer ascribes to Ulysses, at other times, like 





1See Plutarch, Themist.2. Themistocles studied as a young man under Mne- 
siphilus, who makes such a distinguished appearance in Herod. VIII. 57, and 
who had devoted himself to the so called σοφία, which, according to Plutarch, 
consisted in political capacity and practical understanding, and which had descended 
from Solon. ’ 

2 Τοῦ δέοντος, an expression which was very common at Athens in the time of 
Pericles, and denoted whatever was expedient under the existing circumstances 
of the state, 


THEMISTOCLES. 87 


Menelaus, with concise but persuasive diction: Hesiod assigns 
to kings a muse of their own,—Calliope—by whose aid they 
were enabled to speak convincingly and persuasively in the 
popular assembly and from the seat of judgment. With the 
further development of republican constitutions after the age 
of Homer and Hesiod, public officers and demagogues without 
number had spoken in the public meetings, or in the deliberative 
councils and legislative committees of the numerous independent 
states, and no doubt they often spoke eloquently and wisely ; 
but these speeches did not survive the particular occasion which 
called them forth: they were wasted on the air without leaving 
behind them a more lasting effect than would have been pro- 
duced by a discourse of common life; and in this whole period 
it seems never to have been imagined that oratory could pro- 
duce effects more lasting than the particular occurrence which 
gave occasion for a display of it, or that it was capable of 
exerting a ruling influence over all the actions and inclinations 
of a people. Even the lively and ingenious Ionians were dis- 
tinguished at the flourishing epoch of their literature for an 
amusing style, adapted to such narratives as might be com- 
municated in private society, rather than for the more powerful 
eloquence of the public assembly: at least Herodotus, whose 
history may be considered as belonging to Ionian literature, 
though he is fond of introducing dialogues and short speeches, 
never incorporates with his history the popular harangues which 
are so remarkable in Thucydides. It is unanimously agreed 
among the ancients that Athens was the native soil of oratory,’ 
and as the works of Athenian orators alone have come down to 
us, so also we may safely conclude that the ruder oratory, not 
designed for literary preservation, but from which oratory, as a 
branch of literature, arose, was cultivated in a much higher 
degree among the Athenians than in all the rest of Greece. 

§ 3. Tuemistocies, who with equal courage and genius had 
laid the foundations of the greatness of Athens at the most 
dangerous and difficult crisis of her history, was not dis- 
tinguished for eloquence, so much as for the wisdom of his plans, 
and the energy with which he carried them out; nevertheless, 





1 Studium eloquentie propriuwm Athenarum, Cicero, Brutus, XIII. 


88 POLITICAL ORATORY AT ATHENS. 


it is universally agreed that he was in the highest degree 
eapable of unfolding his views, and of recommending them by 
argument.’ The oratory of Prricies occupies a much more 
prominent position. The power and dominion of Athens, though 
continually assailed by new enemies, seemed at last to have 
acquired some stability; it was time to survey the advantages 
which had been gained, and to become acquainted with the prin- 
ciples which had led to their acquisition and might contribute 
to their increase: the question too arose, what use should be 
made of this dominion over the Greeks of the islands and the 
coasts, which it had cost so much trouble to obtain, and of the 
revenues which flowed into Athens in such abundant streams. 
It is manifest, from the whole political career of Pericles, that 
on the one hand he presupposed in his people a power of 
governing themselves, and on the other hand that he wished to 
prevent the state from becoming a mere stake to be played for 
by ambitious demagogues: for he favoured every institution 
which gave the poorer citizens a share in the government; he 
encouraged everything which might contribute to extend edu- 
cation and knowledge; and by his astonishing expenditure on 
works of architecture and sculpture, he gave the people a decided 
fondness for the grand and beautiful. And thus the appearance 
of Pericles on the bema (which he purposely reserved for great 
occasions’) was not intended merely to aid the passing of some 
law, but was at the same time calculated to infuse a noble 
spirit into the general politics of Athens, to guide the views of 
the Athenians in regard to their external relations and all the 
difficulties of their position; and it was the wish of this true 
friend of the people that all this might long survive himself. 
This is obviously the opinion of Thucydides, whom we may con- 
sider as in many respects a worthy disciple of the school of 
Pericles ; and this is the representation which he has given us 
of the oratory of that statesman in the three speeches (all of 
them delivered on important occasions) which he has put into 
his mouth. This wonderful triad of speeches forms a beautiful 





1 Not to mention other authorities, Lysias (Epitaph. XLII.) says that he was 
Ἱκανώτατος εἰπεῖν καὶ γνῶναι καὶ πρᾶξαι. 


2 Plutarch, Pericles VII. 


PERICLES. 89 


whole, which is perfect and complete in itself. The first speech’ 
proves the necessity of a war with the Peloponnesians, and the 
probability that it will be successful: the second,’ delivered im- 
mediately after the first successes obtained in the war, under 
the form of a funeral oration, confirms the Athenians in their 
mode of living and acting; it is half an apology for, half a 
panegyric upon Athens: it is full of a sense of truth and of 
noble self-reliance, tempered with moderation; the third,’ de- 
livered after the calamities which had befallen Athens, rather 
through the plague than through the war, and which had 
nevertheless made the people vacillate in their resolutions, 
offers the consolation most worthy of a noble heart, namely, 
that up to that time fortune, on which no man can count, had 
deceived them, but they had not been misled by their own cal- 
culations and convictions; and that these would never deceive 
them if they did not allow themselves to be led astray by some 
unforeseen accidents.‘ 

§ 4. No speech of Pericles has been preserved in writing. 
It may seem surprising that no attempt was made to write 
down and preserve, for the benefit of the present and future 
generations, works which every one considered admirable, and 
which were regarded as, in some respects, the most perfect 
specimens of oratory.’ The only explanation of this that can 
be offered is, that in those days a speech was not considered as 
possessing any value or interest, save in reference to the par- 
ticular practical object for which it was designed: it had never 
occurred to people that speeches and poems might be placed in 
one class, and both preserved, without reference to their sub- 
jects, on account of the skill with which the subjects were treated, 
and the general beauties of the form and composition.’ Only 





1 Thucyd. I., 140—144. 3 Thucyd. 11. 35—46. 3 Thucyd. II. 60.—64. 

4 A speech of Pericles, in which he took a general survey of the military power 
and resources of Athens, is given by Thucydides (II. 13,) indirectly and in outline 
because this was not an opportunity for unfolding a train of leading ideas, 

5 Plato, though not very partial to Pericles, nevertheless considers him as 
τελεώτατος els Thy ῥητορικήν, and refers for the cause to his acquaintance with the 
speculations of Anaxagoras, Phedr. 270. Cicero, in his Brutus XII., calls him 
‘oratorem prope perfectum,’ only to leave something to be said for the other 
orators. 

® [All the speeches which have been preserved to us from antiquity have been 


90 POLITICAL ORATORY AT ATHENS. 


a few emphatic and nervous expressions of Pericles were kept 
in remembrance; but a general impression of the grandeur and 
copiousness of his oratory long prevailed among the Greeks. 
We are enabled, partly by this long prevalent impression, which 
is mentioned even by later writers, and partly by the connexion 
between Pericles and the other old Attic orators, as also with 
Thucydides, to form a clear conception of his style of speaking, 
without drawing much upon our imagination. 

The primary characteristic of the oratory of Pericles, and 
those who most resembled him is, that their speeches are full of 
thoughts concisely expressed. Unaccustomed to continued ab- 
straction, and unwilling to indulge in trivial reasonings, their 
powers of reflection seized on all the circumstances of the world 
around them with fresh and unimpaired vigour, and, assisted by 
abundant experience and acute observations, brought the light 
of their clear general conceptions to bear upon every subject 
which they took up. Cicero characterizes Pericles, Alcibiades, 
and Thucydides, (for he rightly reckons the two latter among 
the orators) by the epithets ‘ subtle, acute, and concise,’’ and 
distinguishes between them and the somewhat younger genera- 
tion of Critias, Theramenes, and Lysias, who had also, he says, 
retained some of the sap and life-blood of Pericles,’ but had 
spun the thread of their discourse rather more liberally.’ 

With regard to the opinions of Pericles, we know that they 
were remarkable for the comprehensive views of public affairs 
on which they were based. The majesty for which Pericles 





preserved by the orators themselves. Pericles appears to have made no record of 
his speeches ; and probably he would have considered it degrading, in his eminent 
position, to place himself on the footing of a A\oyoypddos.—Lditor.} 

1 He says subtiles, acuti, breves, sententiis magis quam verbis abundantes, by which 
he means, ‘skilful in the choice of words, and in the distinct expression of every 
thought’ (subtiles), ‘refined in their ideas’ (acuti), ‘concise’ (breves), ‘and with 
more thoughts than words.’ 

3 Retinebant illum Periclis succum. 

8 De Orator. ΤΙ, 22. In the Brutus, c. VII., he gives a rather different classifi- 
cation of the old orators. In the latter work he classes Alcibiades along with 
Critias and Theramenes, and says the style of their oratory may be gathered from 
Thucydides ; he calls them grandes verbis, crebri sententiis, compressione rerum breves, 
et ob eam causam subobscuri. Critias is described by Philostratus, Sophist. I. τό, and 
still better by Hermogenes, περὶ ἰδεῶν, (in Walz, Rhet. Greci. L. IIL., p. 388): and 
we may infer that he stood, in regard to style, between Antiphon and Lysias. 





SPEECHES OF PERICLES. 91 


was so distinguished, and which gained for him the appellation 
of ‘ the Olympian,’ consisted mostly in the skill and ability with 
which he referred all common occurrences to the general prin- 
ciples and bold ideas, which he had derived from his noble and 
exalted view of the destiny of Athens. Accordingly, Plato says 
of Pericles, that in addition to his natural abilities, he had 
acquired an elevation of mind, and a habit of striving after 
definite objects.’ It was on this account, too, that his opinions 
took such a firm hold of his hearers ; according to the metaphor 
of Eupolis—they remained fixed in the mind, like the sting of 
the bee. 

§ 5. It was because the thoughts of Pericles were so striking, 
so entirely to the purpose, and at the same time so grand, and 
we may add it was on this account alone, that his speeches pro- 
duced so deep and lasting an impression. The sole object of 
the oratory of Pericles was to produce conviction, to give a per- 
manent bias to the mind of the people. It was alien from his 
intentions to excite any sudden and transient burst of passion 
by working onthe emotions of the heart. The whole history 
of Attic oratory teaches us that there could not be in the 
speeches of Pericles the slightest employment of those means 
by which the orators of a later age used to set in motion the 
violent and unruly impulses of the multitude. To judge from 
the descriptions which have been given of the manner of Pericles 
when he ascended the bema, it was tranquil, with hardly any 
change of feature, with calm and dignified gestures; his gar- 
ments were undisturbed by oratorical gesticulations of any kind, 
and the tone and loudness of his voice were equable and sus- 
tained... We may conceive that the frame of mind which this 
delivery expressed, and which it excited in the hearers, was in 
harmony and unison with it. Pericles had no wish to gratify 
the people otherwise than by ministering to their improvement 
and benefit. He never condescended to flatter them. Great as 
was his idea of the resources and high destinies of Athens, he never 
feared in particular cases to tell them even the harshest truths. 





1 Plato, Phadrus, p. 270: τὸ ὑψηλόνουν τοῦτο καὶ πάντῃ τελεσιουργὸν. .. ὃ 
Περικλῆς πρὸς τὸ εὐφυὴς εἶναι ἐκτήσατο. The τελεσιουργὸν denotes, according to 
the context, the striving after a great fixed object. 

1 Plutarch, Pericl. V. 


92 POLITICAL ORATORY AT ATHENS. 


When Pericles declaimed against the people, this was thought, 
according to Cicero, a proof of his affection towards them, and 
produced a pleasing impression ;‘ even when his own safety was 
threatened, he was content to wait till they had an opportunity 
of becoming convinced of his innocence, and he never sought to 
produce this conviction otherwise than by a clear and energetic 
representation of the truth, studiously avoiding any appeal to 
transient emotions and feelings. He was just as little anxious 


to amuse or entertain the populace. Pericles never indulged in. 


a smile while speaking from the bema.? His dignity never 
stooped to merriment.* All his public appearances were 
marked by a sustained earnestness of manner. 

Some traditional particulars and the character of the time 
enable us also to form an opinion of the diction of the speeches 
of Pericles. He employed the language of common life, the 
vernacular idiom of Attica, even more than Thucydides : but his 
accurate discrimination of meanings gave his words a subtlety 
and pregnancy which was a main ingredient in the nervous 
energy of his style. Although there was more of reasoning 
than of imagination in his speeches, he had no difficulty in 
giving a vivid and impressive colouring to his language by the 
use of striking metaphors and comparisons, and as the prose of 
the day was altogether unformed, by so doing, he could not help 
expressing himself poetically. A good many of these figurative 
expressions and apophthegms in the speeches of Pericles have 
been preserved, and especially by Aristotle: as when he said of 
the Samians, that ‘they were like little children who cried when 
they took their food ;’ or when at the funeral of a number of 
young persons who had fallen in battle, he used the beautiful 
figure, that ‘the year had lost its spring.’ ® 





1 Cicero, de Orat. III. 34. 

2 Plutarch, Pericl. 5: προσώπου σύστασις ἄθρυπτος els γέλωτα. 

3 Summa auctoritas sine omni hilaritate, Cic. de Offic. 1. 30. 

4 This appears from the fact mentioned near the end of chap. XX VII. 
5 Aristotle, Rhetor. I. 7; III. 4, το. 


" 
a τ 


93 


CHAPTER XXXII. 


THE RHETORIC OF THE SOPHISTS. 


8 τ. Profession of the Sophists: essential elements of their doctrines. The 
principles of Protagoras. ὃ 2. Opinions of Gorgias. Pernicious effects of his 
doctrines, especially as they were carried out by his disciples. ὃ 3. Important 
services of the Sophists in forming a prose style: different tendencies of the 
Sicilian and other Sophists in this respect. ὃ 4. The rhetoric of Gorgias. ὃ 5. 
His forms of expression. 


δι. ΠῊΕ impulse to a further improvement of the prose 

style proceeded immediately from the Sophists, who, 
in general, exercised a greater influence on the culture of the 
Greek mind than any other class of men, the ancient poets 
alone excepted. . 

The Sophists were, as their name indicates, persons who 
made knowledge their profession, and who undertook to impart 
it to every one who was willing to place himself under their 
guidance. The philosophers of the Socratic school reproached 
them with being the first to sell knowledge for money; and 
such was the case; for they not only demanded admittance- 
money from those who came to hear their public lectures (em- 
δείξεις),; but also undertook for a considerable sum fixed before- 
hand, to give young men a complete sophistical education, and 
not to dismiss them till they were thoroughly instructed in their 
art. At that time a thirst for knowledge was so great in Greece,” 
that not only in Athens, but also in the oligarchies of Thessaly, 
hearers and pupils flocked to them in crowds; the arrival in 
any city of one of the greater sophists, Gorgias, Protagoras, or 
Hippias, was celebrated as a festival; and these men acquired 
riches such as art and science had never before earned among 
the Greeks. 


Not only the outward profession, but also the peculiar doc- 





1 There were wide differences in the amounts paid on these occasions. The 
admission-fee for some lectures was a drachma, for others fifty drachme. 
* Comp. the remark in chap. XX VIL, ὃ 5. 


94 THE RHETORIC OF THE SOPHISTS. 


trines of the Sophists were, on the whole, one and the same, 
though they admitted of certain modifications of greater or less 
importance. If we consider these doctrines philosophically, 
they amounted to a denial or renunciation of all true science. 
Philosophy had then just completed the first stage of her 
career: she had boldly undertaken to solve the abstrusest 
questions of speculation, and the widely different answers which 
had been returned to some of those questions, had all produced 
conviction, and obtained many staunch supporters. The dif- 
ference between the results thus obtained, although the grounds 
of this difference had not been investigated, must of itself have 
awakened a doubt as to the possibility of any real knowledge 
regarding the hidden nature of things. Accordingly, nothing 
was more likely than that every flight of speculation should be 
succeeded by an epoch of scepticism, in which the universality 
of all science would be doubted or denied. That all knowledge 
is suljective, that it is true only for the individual, was the 
meaning of the celebrated saying’ of Proracoras of Abdera, 
who made his appearance at Athens in the time of Pericles,’ 
and for a long time enjoyed a great reputation there, till at last a 
reaction was caused by the bold scepticism of his opinions, and 
he was banished from Athens and his books were publicly 
burnt.2 Agreeing with Heraclitus in regard to the doctrine 
of a perpetual motion and of a continual change in the im- 
pressions and perceptions of men, he deduced from this that the 
individual could know nothing beyond these ever varying per- 
ceptions ; consequently, that whatever appeared to be, was so 
for the individual. According to this doctrine, opposite opinions 
on the same subject might be equally true; and if an opinion 
were only supported by a momentary appearance of truth, this 
was sufficient to make it true for the moment. Hence, it was 
one of the great feats which Protagoras and the other Sophists 
professed to perform, to be able to speak with equal plausibility 





1 Πάντων μέτρον ἄνθρωπος. 

5 About Ol. 84. B.0. 444, according to the chronology of Apollodorus. 

8 Protagoras was prosecuted for atheism and expelled from Athens, on the 
accusation of Pythodorus, one of the council of the Four-hundred: this would be 
in Ol. 92, 1. or 2. B.C. 411, if the event happened during the time of the Four- 
hundred, but this is by no means established. 


GORGIAS. 95 


for and against the same position; not in order to discover the 
truth, but in order to show the nothingness of truth. It was 
not, however, the intention of Protagoras to deprive virtue, as 
well as truth, of its reality: but he reduced virtue to a mere 
state or condition of the subject,—a set of impressions and 
feelings which rendered the subject more capable of active use- 
fulness. Of the gods, he said at the very beginning of the book 
which caused his banishment from Athens: ‘ With regard to the 
gods, I cannot determine whether they are or are not; for there 
are many obstacles in the way of this inquiry—the uncertainty 
of the matter, and the shortness of human life.’ 

§ 2. Goreras, of Leontini, in Sicily, who visited Athens for 
the first time in Ol. 88, 2. B.c. 427, as an ambassador from his 
native town, belonged to an entirely different part of the Hel- 
lenic world, had different teachers, and proceeded from an older 
philosophical school than Protagoras, but yet there was a great 
correspondence between the pursuits of these two men; and 
from this we may clearly see how strongly the spirit of the age 
must have inclined to the form and mode of speculation which 
was common to them both. Gorgias employed the dialectical 
method of the Eleatic school, but arrived at an opposite result 
by means of it: while the Eleatic philosophers directed all their 
efforts towards establishing the perpetuity and unity of existence, 
Gorgias availed himself of the methods and even of some of the 
conclusions, which Zeno and Melissus had applied to such a 
widely different object, in order to prove that nothing exists: 
that even if anything did exist, it would not be cognizable, and 
even if it both existed and were cognizable, it could not be 
conveyed and communicated by words. The result was, that 
absolute knowledge was unattainable ; and that the proper end 
of instruction was to awaken in the pupil’s mind such concep- 
tions as are suitable to his own purposes and interests. The 
chief distinction between Gorgias and the other Sophists con- 
sisted in the frankness with which he admitted, that he promised 
and professed nothing else than to make his scholars apt rheto- 
ricians; and the ridicule with which he treated those of his 
colleagues who professed to teach virtue, a peculiarity which 
Gorgias shared with all the other Sophists of Sicily. The 
Sophists in the mother country, on the other hand, endeavoured 


96 THE RHETORIC OF THE SOPHISTS. 


to awaken useful thoughts, and to teach the principles of prac- 
tical philosophy: thus Hrerias of Elis endeavoured to season 
his lessons with a display of multifarious knowledge, and may 
be regarded as the first Polyhistor among the Greeks:’ and 
Propicus of Ceos, perhaps the most respectable among the 
Sophists, used to present lessons of morality under an agreeable 
form: such a moral lesson was the well-known allegory of the 
choice of Hercules. 

In general, however, the labours of the Sophists were preju- 
dicial alike to the moral condition of Greece, and to the serious 
pursuit of knowledge. The national morality which drew the 
line between right and wrong, though not perhaps according to 
the highest standard, yet at any rate with honest views, and 
what was of most importance, with a sort of instinctive cer- 
tainty, had received a shock from the boldness with which 
philosophy had handled it: and could not but be altogether 
undermined by a doctrine which destroyed the distinction he- 
tween truth and falsehood. And though Protagoras and Gorgias 
shrank from declaring that virtue and religion were nothing but 
empty illusions, their disciples and followers did so most openly, 
when the liberty of speculation was completely emancipated 
from all the restraints of traditionary opinions. In the course 
of the Peloponnesian war, a class of society was formed at 
Athens, which was not without influence on the course of affairs, 
and whose creed was, that justice and belief in the gods were 
but the inventions of ancient rulers and legislators, who gave 
them currency in order to strengthen their hold on the common 
herd, and assist them in the business of government: they some- 
times gave this opinion with this far more pernicious variation, 
that laws were made by the majority of weaker men for their 
protection, whereas nature had sanctioned the right of the 
strongest, so that the stronger party did but use his right when 
he compelled the weaker to minister to his pleasure as far as 
he could. These are the doctrines which Plato in his Gorgias 





1 Plato often speaks of his acquaintance with physics and astronomy: he also 
inquired after genealogies, colonies, and ‘antiquities in general.’ Hippias. Maj. 
p. 285. Some fragments of his treatises on political antiquities have been pre- 
served: probably derived from his συναγωγή. Bickh. Pref. ad Pindari Scholia, 
p- xxi. His list of the Olympic victors was also a remarkable work. 


STYLE OF THE SOPHISTS. 97 


and in his Republic, attributes to Catuicxzs, a disciple of Gorgias, 
and to Turasymacuus of Chalcedon, who flourished as a teacher 
of rhetoric during the Peloponnesian war, and which were 
frequently uttered by Plato’s own uncle, the able and politic 
Critias who has been mentioned more than once in oe course 
of this history.’ 

δ 3. If, however, we turn from this influence of the Sophists 
on the spirit of their age, and set ourselves to inquire what they 
did for the improvement of written compositions, we are con- 
strained to set a very high value on their services. The for- 
mation of an artificial prose style is due entirely to the Sophists, 
and although they did not at first proceed according to a right 
method, they may be considered as having laid a foundation for 
the polished diction of Plato and Demosthenes. The Sophists 
of Greece proper, as well as those of Sicily, made language the 
object of their study, but with this distinction, that the former 
aimed at correctness, the latter at beauty of style? Protagoras 
investigated the principles of accurate composition (ὑρθοέπεια), 
though practically he was distinguished for a copious fluency, 
which Plato’s Socrates vainly attempts to bridle with his dialec- 
tic ; and Prodicus busied himself with inquiries into the signi- 
fication and correct use of words, and the discrimination of 
synonyms: his own discourses were full of such distinctions, as 
_ appears from the humorous imitation of his style in Plato’s 
Protagoras. 

‘The principal object which Gorgias proposed to himself was 
a beautiful, ornamented, pleasing, and captivating style; he was 
by profession a rhetorician, and had been prepared for his trade 
by a suitable education. The Sicilian Greeks, and especially 
the Syracusans, whose lively disposition and natural quickness 
raised them, more than any other Dorian people, toa level with 
the Athenians,* had commenced, even earlier than the people of 
Attica, the study of an artificial rhetoric useful for the discus- 





1 As a tragedian, but only with a view to the promulgation of these doctrines, 
he is mentioned in Chap. XX VI. 8 4; as an Elegiac poet in Chap. XXX. § 5; 
and as an orator, Chap. XXXI. § 4. 

’ 2This distinction is pointed out by Leonhard Spengel in his useful work, 
Συναγωγὴ τεχνῶν, sive artiwm scriptores, 1828, p. 63. 

3 Cicero, Brutus XI1., 46 : Siculi acuta gens et controversa natura. Verrin. IV., 

43, 95: nunquam tam male est Siculis, quin aliquid facile et commode dicant. 
Vou. 11. H 


98 THE RHETORIC OF ΤῊΝ SOPHISTS. 


sions of the law-courts. The situation of Syracuse at the time 
of the Persian war had contributed a good deal to awaken their 
natural inclination and capacity for such a study ; especially by 
the impulse which the abolition of arbitrary government had 
given to democratic sentiments (Ol. 78, 3. B.c.. 466), and by the 
complicated transactions which sprung up from the renewal of 
private claims long suppressed by the tyrants.’ At this time 
Corax, who had been highly esteemed by the tyrant Hiero, 
came forward in a conspicuous manner, both as a public orator 
and as a pleader in the law-courts;* his great practice led him 
to consider more accurately the principles of his art; and at 
last it occurred to him to write a book on the subject:* this 
book, like the innumerable treatises which succeeded it, was 
called τέχνη ῥητορικὴ, “the art of rhetoric,’ or simply τέχνη; 
“the art.” Although this work might have been very circum- 
scribed in its plan, and not very comprehensive in its treatment 
of the subject, it is nevertheless worthy of notice as the first of 
its kind, not only among the Greeks, but perhaps also in the 
whole world. For this τέχνη of Corax was not merely the first 
attempt at a theory of rhetoric, but also the first theoretical 
book on any branch of art:* and it is highly remarkable that 
while ancient poetry was transmitted through so many gene- 
rations by nothing but practice and oral instruction, its younger 
sister began at once with establishing itself in the form of a 
theory, and as such communicating itself to all who were de- 
sirous of learning its principles. All that we know of this τέχνη 





1 Cic. Brut. XII., 46 (after Aristotle): cum sublatis in Sicilia tyrannis res pri- 
vate longo intervallo judictis repeterentur, Aristotle is also the authority for the 
statement in the scholia on Hermogenes, in Reiske’s Oratores Aitici. T. VIII. p. 
196. Comp. Montfaucon, Biblioth. Coislin., p. 592. 

2 Or as a composer of speeches for others, for it is doubtful whether there was 
an establishment of patroni and causidici at Syracuse, as at Rome ; or whether every 
one was compelled to plead his own cause, as at Athens, in which case he was 
always able to get his speech made for him by some professed rhetorician. 

3 This is also mentioned by Aristotle, who wrote a history of rhetoric down to 
his own time, which is now lost: besides the passages referred to above, he men- 
tions the τέχνη of Corax in his Rhetor. II., 24. 

4 The old architectural treatises on particular buildings, such as that of Theo- 
dorus of Samos on the temple of Juno in that island, and those of Chersiphron and 


Metagenes on the temple of Diana at Ephesus, were probably only tables of calcu- 
lations and measurements. 


THE RHETORIC OF THE SOPHISTS. 99 


is that it laid down a regular form and regular divisions for the 
oration ; above all, it was to begin with a distant procemium, 
calculated to put the hearers in a favourable train, and to con- 
ciliate their good will at the very opening of the speech.’ 

§ 4. Tistas was first a pupil and afterwards a rival of 
Corax ; he was also known not only as an orator, but also as 
the author of a τέχνη: Gorgias, again, was the pupil of Tisias, 
and followed closely in his steps: according to one account,? 
Tisias was a colleague of Gorgias in the embassy from Leontini 
mentioned above, though the pupil was at that time infinitely 
more celebrated than his master. -With Gorgias this artificial 
rhetoric obtained more fame and glory than fell to the share of 
any other branch of literature. The Athenians, to whom this 
Sicilian rhetoric was still a novelty, though they were fully 
qualified and predisposed to appreciate and enjoy its beauties,* 
were quite enchanted with it, and it soon became fashionable 
to speak like Gorgias. The impression produced by the oratory 
of Gorgias was greatly increased by his stately appearance, his 
well-chosen and splendid costume, and the: self-possession and 
confidence of his demeanour. Besides, his rhetoric rested on a 
basis of philosophy,‘ though, as has just been mentioned, rather 
of a negative kind; and there is no trace of this in the systems 
of Corax and Tisias. This philosophy taught, that the sole aim 
of the orator is to turn the minds of his hearers into such a 
train as may best consist with his own interests; that, conse- 
quently, rhetoric is the agent of persuasion,’ the art of all arts, 
because the rhetorician is able to speak well and convincingly 
on every subject, even though he has no accurate knowledge 
respecting it. 

In accordance with this view of rhetoric, Gorgias took little 
pains with the subject-matter of his speeches; he only con- 
cerned himself about this so far as to exercise himself in treat- 





1 These introductious were called κολακευτικὰ καὶ θεραπευτικὰ προοίμια. 

3 See Pausan. VI., 17, 18. Diodorus, the principal authority, makes no men- 
tion of Tisias, XTI., 53. ν 

8 ὄντες εὐφυεῖς καὶ φιλολόγοι, says Diodorus. 

4 This philosophy is contained in a treatise by Gorgias, περὶ φύσεως ἢ τοῦ μὴ ὄντος, 
of which the best account is given by Aristotle in his essay on Melissus, Xeno- 
phanes, and Gorgias. 

ὅ Πειθοῦς δημιουργός. 


100 THE RHETORIC OF THE SOPHISTS: 


ing of general topics, which were called /oci communes, and the 
proper management and application of which have always helped 
the rhetorician to conceal his ignorance. The panegyrics and 
invectives which Gorgias wrote on every possible subject, and 
which served him for practice, were also calculated to assist 
him in combating or defending received opinions and convic- 
tions, by palliating the bad, and misrepresenting the good. The 
same purpose was served by his delusive and captious conclu- 
sions, which he had borrowed from the Eleatic school, in order 
to pass with the common herd as a profound thinker, and to 
confuse their notions of truth and falsehood. All this belonged 
to the instrument, by virtue of which Gorgias promised, in the 
language of the day, to make the weaker argument, i.e. the 
worse cause, victorious over the stronger argument, i.e. the 
better cause.’ 

§ 5. But the chief study of Gorgias was directed to the form 
of expression ; and it is true that he was able, by the use of 
high-sounding words and artfully constructed sentences, to de- 
ceive not only the ears but also the mind of the Greeks—alive 
as they were to the perception of such beauties—to so great an 
extent that they overlooked for a long time the emptiness and 
coldness of his declamations. Prose was at this time com- 
mencing its career, and had not yet manifested its resources, 

. and shown the beauty of which it was capable: it was natural, 
therefore, that it should take for its pattern the poetry which 
had preceded it by so long an interval: the ears of the Greeks, 
accustomed to poetry, required of prose, if it professed to be 
more than a mere necessary communication of thoughts, if it 
aimed at beauty, a great resemblance to poetry. Gorgias com- 
plied with this requisition in two ways: in the first place, he 
employed poetical words, especially rare words, and new com- 
pounds, such as were favourites with the lyric and dithyrambic 
poets.” As this poetical colouring did not demand any high 
flight of ideas, or any great exertion of the imaginative powers, 





1 ἥττων καὶ κρείττων λόγος. ‘ 
_ 3 See Aristotle, Rhetor. III., 1, 3, and 3, 1. Here the διπλᾶ ὀνόματα are parti- 
eularly assigned to Gorgias and Lycophron. In the Poetic. 22, Aristotle says, that 
the διπλᾶ ὀνόματα, i.e. extraordinary words and novel compounds, occurred most: 
frequently in the Dithyramb. 


FORMS OF EXPRESSION OF GORGIAS. 101 


and as it remained only an outward ornament, the style of 
Gorgias became turgid and bombastic, and compositions cha- 
racterized by this fault were said, in the technical language of 
Greek rhetoric, to gorgiaze.' In the second place, the prevail- 
ing taste for prose at that time seemed to require some sub- 
stitute for the rhythmical proportions of poetry. Gorgias effected 
this by giving a sort of symmetry to the structure of the sen- 
tences, so that the impression conveyed was, that the different 
members of the period were parallel and corresponding to one 
another, and this stamped the whole with an appearance of 
artificial regularity. To this belonged the art of making the 
sentences of equal length, of making them correspond to one 
another in form, and of making them end in the same way :” 
also the use of words of similar formation and of similar sound, 
i.e. almost rhyming with one another :* also, the antithesis, in 
which, besides the opposition of thought, there was a corre- 
spondence of all the different parts and individual points ; an arti- 
fice which easily led the orator to introduce forced and unnatural 
combinations,’ and which, in the case of the Sicilian rhetoricians, 
had already incurred the ridicule of Epicharmus.’ If we add 
to this the witty turns, the playful style, the various methods 
of winning the attention, which Gorgias skilfully interwove 
with his expressions, we shall have no difficulty in understand- 
ing how this artificial prose, which was neither poetry nor yet 
the language of common life, was so successful on its first ap- 
pearance at Athens. That such a style was highly suitable to 





1 γοργιάζειν. 3 ἰσόκωλα, πάρισα, ὁμοιοτέλευτα. 
8 Παρονομασίαι, παρηχήσεις. 
* As in the forced but ingenious definition of tragic illusion, namely, that it is 
an ἀπάτη, or deceit :— 
ἣν ὅ τι ἀπατήσας δικαιότερος τοῦ μὴ ἀπατήσαντος 
καὶ ὁ ἀπατηθεὶς σοφώτερος τοῦ μὴ ἀπατηθέντος, 
ὁ.6. in which the deceiver does his duty better than the undeceiving, and where the 
person deceived shows more feeling for art than the person who will not yield to 
the deception, All these figures occur in abundance in the very important and no 
doubt genuine fragments of Gorgias’ funeral oration, which are preserved in the 
scholia on Hermogenes : see Foss, de Gorgia Leontino, p.69. Spengel, Συναγωγή, 
p. 78. Clinton, κ΄. H., Vol. II., p. 464, ed. 3. 
ὅ In the verse: τόκα μὲν ἐν τήνοις ἐγὼν ἣν, τόκα δὲ παρὰ Tivos ἐγών, which is an 
opposition of words rather than of sense, such as naturally resulted from a forced 
antithetical style; see especially Demetrius, de Elocutione, § 24. 


102 THE RHETORIC OF THE SOPHISTS. 


the taste of the age as it gradually unfolded itself, is also shown 
by its rapid extension and further development, especially in 
the school of Gorgias. We have already spoken of Agathon’s 
parallelisms and antitheses;' but Potus of <Agrigentum, the 
favourite scholar and devoted partizan of Gorgias, went far 
beyond all others in his attention to those ornaments of 
language, and carried this even into the slightest minutie of 
language :? similarly, Atcrpamas, another scholar of Gorgias, 
who is often mentioned by Aristotle, exceeded his master in his 
showy, poetic diction, and in the affectation of his elegant 
antithesis.’ 





1 Chap. XXVL,, § 3. 

2 In the address: ὦ λῶστε Πῶλε, Plato ridicules his fondness for the juxtaposition 
of words of a similar sound. 

3 The declamations which remain under the name of Gorgias, Alcidamas, and 
Antisthenes (another scholar of Gorgias), have been justly regarded as imitations 
of their style by later rhetoricians. 


103 


CHAPTER XXXIII. 


THE BEGINNINGS OF REGULAR POLITICAL AND FORENSIC 
ORATORY AMONG THE ATHENIANS. 


§ 1. Antiphon’s career and employments. § 2. His school-exercises, the Tetra- 
logies. ὃ 3. His speeches before the courts ; Character of his oratory. ὃ 4, 5 
More particular examination of his style. § 6, Andocides ; his life and character. 


δ 1. (PXHE cultivation of the art of oratory among the Athe- 

nians is due to a combination of the natural eloquence, 
displayed by the Athenian statesmen, and especially by Pericles, 
with the rhetorical studies of the Sophists. The first person 
in whom the effects of this combination were fully shown was 
AntipHon, the son of Sophilus of Rhamnus. Antiphon was 
both a practical statesman and man of business, and also a 
rhetorician of the schools. With regard to the former part of 
his character, we are told by Thucydides that, though the 
tyranny of the Four-hundred was ostensibly established by 
Pisander, it was Antiphon who drew up the plan for it, and 
who had the greatest share in carrying it into effect ; ‘he was 
a man, says the historian,’ ‘inferior to none of his contem- 
poraries in yirtue, and distinguished above all others in forming 
plans and recommending his views by oratory. He made no 
public speeches, indeed, nor did he ever of his own accord 
engage in the litigations of the court ; but being suspected by 
the people from his reputation for powerful speaking,’ there was 
yet no one man in Athens who was better able to assist, by his 
counsels, those who had any contest to undergo either in the 
law-courts or in the popular assemblies. And in his own case, 
when, after the downfal of the Four-hundred, he was tried for 
his life as having been a party to the establishment of the oli- 
garchy, it is acknowledged that the speech which he made in 
his own defence was the best that had ever been made up to 





1 VIII, 68. 
5 δεινότης, here used in its wider sense, as implying any power of persuasion. 


104 POLITICAL AND FORENSIC ORATORY. 


that time.’ But his admirable oratory was of no avail at this 
crisis, when the effect of his speech was more than counter- 
balanced by the feelings of the people: the devices of Thera- 
menes completed his ruin; he was executed in Ol. 92, 2. B.c. 
411, when nearly seventy years old;’ his property was con- 
fiscated, and even his descendants were deprived of the rights 
of citizenship.® 

We clearly see, from the testimony of Thucydides, what use 
Antiphon made of his oratory. He did not come forward, like 
other speakers, to express his sentiments in the Ecclesia, nor was 
he ever a public accuser in the law-courts: he never spoke in 
public save on his own affairs and when attacked : in other cases 
he laboured for others. With him the business of speech-writing 
first rose into importance, a business which for a long time was 
not considered so honourable as that of the public speaker ; 
but although many Athenians spoke and thought contemptu- 
ously of his profession, it was practised even by the great 
public orators along with their other employments ; and accord- 
ing to the Athenian institutions was almost indispensable. 
For in private suits the parties themselves pleaded their cause 
in open court ; and in public indictments, though any Athenian 
might wenihet the prosecution, the accused person was not 
allowed an advocate, though his defence might be supported by 
some friends who spoke after him, and endeavoured to complete 
the arguments in his favour. It is obvious from this, that 
when the need of an advocate in the law-courts began to be 
more and more felt, most Athenians would be obliged to apply 
for professional assistance, and would, with this view, either get 
assisted in the composition of their own speeches, or commit to 
memory and deliver, word for word, a speech composed for 
them by some practised orator. Thus the speech-writers, or 





1 It is a great pity that this speech has not been preserved. Harpocration often 
quotes it under the title ἐν τῷ περὶ τῆς μεταστάσεως. The allusions to the time of 
the Four-hundred are obvious enough. 

2 2.6. if the account is true which places his birth in Ol. 75, 1. B.c. 480. His 
great age and winning eloquence seem to have gained him the name of Nestor, by 
which he was known among the Athenian people. 

3 The decree according to which he was executed, and the decision of the court, 
are preserved in the Vite decem oratorwm (in Plutarch’s works), Cap. I. 


ANTIPHON. 105 


logographi, as they were called,’ (Antiphon, Lysias, Iszeus, and 
Demosthenes,) rendered services partly analogous to those per- 
formed by the Roman patroni and causidici, or to the legal 
advocates and counsellors of modern states, although they did 
not stand nearly so high in public estimation, unless at the same 
time they took an active part in public affairs.2 The practice 
of writing speeches for others probably led to a general habit 
of committing speeches to writing, and thus placing them within 
the reach of others besides those to whom they were delivered : 
at all events, it is certain that Antiphon was the first to do 
this.’ 

Antiphon also established a school of rhetoric, in which the 
art of oratory was systematically taught, and, according to a 
custom which had been prevalent since the time of Corax, wrote 
a Techne, containing a formal exposition of his principles. As 
a teacher of rhetoric Antiphon followed closely in the steps of the 
Sophists, with whose works he was very well acquainted, 
although he was not actually a scholar of any one among 
them :* like Protagoras and Gorgias, he discussed general 
themes, which were designed only for exercises, and had no 
practical object in view. These may have been partly the most 
general subjects about which an argument could be held,—the 
loci communes, as they are called ;° partly, particular cases so 
ingeniously contrived that the contrary assertions respecting 
them might be maintained with equal facility, and thus exercise 
would be afforded to the sophistic art of speaking plausibly on 
both sides of the question. 

§ 2. Of the fifteen remaining speeches of Antiphon, twelve 
belong to the class of school exercises. They form three 





1 They were called λογογράφοι by the common people at Athens. 

? Thus Antiphon was attacked by Plato the comedian for writing speeches for 
hire: Photius, Codex, 259. 

3 Orationem primus omnium scripsit, says Quintilian. 

4 This is shown by the γένος ᾿Αντιφῶντος : the chronology renders it almost im- 
possible that Antiphon’s father could have been a Sophist (Vite X. Orat., ο. 1. 
Phot., Codex 259).—[This is probably a confusion occasioned by the name of Anti- 
phon’s father Sophilus.—Ep.] 

ὅ That Antiphon had practised himself in such commonplaces is shown by their 
occurrence in different orations, in which he inserts them wherever he can. Comp. 
de cede Herod., ὃ 14, 87. Chor., § 2, 3. 


106 POLITICAL AND FORENSIC ORATORY. 


Tetralogies, so that every four of the orations are occupied with 
the discussion of the same case, and contain a speech and reply 
by both plaintiff and defendant.! The following is the subject 
of the first Tetralogy :—A citizen, returning with his slave from 
an evening banquet, is attacked by assassins, and killed on the 
spot: the slave is mortally wounded, but survives till he has 
told the relations of the murdered man that he recognized 
among the assassins a particular person who was at enmity with 
his master, and who was about to lose his cause in an important 
law-suit between him and the deceased. Accordingly, this 
person is indicted by the family of the murdered man, and the 
speeches all turn upon an attempt to exaggerate or diminish the 
probabilities for and against the guilt of the person arraigned. 
For instance, while the complainant lays the greatest stress on 
the animosity existing between the accused and the deceased, 
the defendant maintains that he could certainly have had no 
hand in the murder, when it was obvious that the first sus- 
picion would fall on himself. While the former sets great 
value on the evidence of the slave as the only one available for 
his purpose, the latter maintains that slaves would not be tor- 
tured as they were, according to the Greek custom, unless their 
simple testimony had been considered insufficient. In answer 
to this the complainant urges, in his second speech, that slaves 
were tortured on account of theft, for the purpose of bringing to 
light some transgression which they concealed to please their 
master ; but that, in cases like the one in question, they were 
emancipated in order that they might be qualified to give evi- 
dence ;? and, in regard to the argument that the accused must 
have foreseen that he would be suspected, the fear of this sus- 
picion would not have been sufficient to counterbalance the 
danger resulting from the loss of his cause. The accused, 
however, gives a turn to the argument from probability, by 
remarking, among other things, that a freeman would be re- 
strained from giving a false testimony by a fear of endangering 
his reputation and substance; but that there was nothing to 





1 λόγοι πρότεροι καὶ ὕστεροι.. 
2 Personal freedom was indispensable for evidence (μαρτυρεῖν) properly so called : 
slaves were compelled to give evidence by the torture. 


TETRALOGIES. 107 


hinder the slave at the point of death from gratifying the family 
of his master, by impeaching his master’s old enemy. And 
after having compared all the arguments from probability, and 
drawn a balance in his own favour, he concludes aptly enough, 
by saying that he can prove his innocence, not merely by pro- 
babilities' but by facts, and accordingly offers all his slaves, 
male and female, to be tortured according to the custom of 
Athens, in order to prove that he never left his house on the 
night of the murder. 

We have selected these few points from many other argu- 
ments equally acute on both sides of the question, in order to 
give those readers who are not yet acquainted with Antiphon’s 
speeches, some notion, however faintyof the shrewdness and 
ingenuity with which the rhetoricians of that time could twist 
and turn to their own purposes the facts and circumstances 
which they were called upon to discuss. The sophistic art of 
strengthening the weaker cause was in Antiphon’s school con- 
nected with forensic oratory,? the professor of which must 
necessarily be prepared to argue in favour of either of the 
parties in a law-suit. 

§ 3. Besides these rhetorical exercises, we have three of 
Antiphon’s speeches which were actually delivered in court— 
the accusation of a step-mother charged with poisoning, the de- 
fence of the person charged with the murder of Herodes, and 
another defence of a choregus, one of whose choreute had been 
poisoned while under training. All these speeches refer to 
charges of murder,* and for this reason have been classed with 
the Tetralogies, the assumed subjects of which are of the same 
kind : a distribution of the works of Greek orators according to the 
nature of the different suits was very common among the learned 
grammarians,’ and many ancient citations refer to this division ; 
for instance, when speeches referring to the duties of guardians, 
to money-transactions, or to debts, are quoted as belonging to 
different classes. In this manner Antiphon’s speeches on 





1 In § 10, he says with great acuteness: ‘While they maintain on grounds of 
probability that Iam guilty, they nevertheless maintain that I am not probably but 
actually the murderer.’ 

2 τὸ δικανικὸν γένος. 3 φονικαὶ δίκαι. 

* This occurs frequently in Dionysius of Halicarnassus. 


108 POLITICAL AND FORENSIC ORATORY. 


charges of murder have alone been preserved, and the only 
orations of Iseeus which have come down to us, are those on the 
law of inheritance and wills. In these speeches of Antiphon we 
see the same ingenuity and shrewdness, and the same legal 
acumen, as in the Tetralogies, combined with far greater polish 
and elaboration of style, since the Tetralogies were only designed 
to display skill in the discovery and complication of arguments. 

These more complete speeches may be reckoned among the 
most important materials that we possess for a history of 
oratory. In respect to their style, they stand im close con- 
nexion with the history of Thucydides and the speeches with 
which it is interspersed, and confirm the statement of many 
grammarians,’ that Thucydides was instructed in the school of 
Antiphon,—a statement which harmonizes very well with the 
circumstances of their lives. The ancients often couple Thucy- 
dides with Antiphon,’ and mention these two as the chief masters 
of the old austere oratory,’ the nature of which we must here 
endeavour rightly to comprehend. It does not consist (as might 
be conjectured from the expressions used in speaking of it,* which 
are justified only by a comparison with the smooth and polished 
oratory of later days) in any intentional rudeness or harshness, 
but in the orator’s confining himself to a clear and definite 
expression of what he had clearly and definitely conceived. 
Although it is not to be denied that the orators of that time 
were deficient in the fluency which results from practice, they 
had on that account all the more power and freshness of 
thought; many reflections, which afterwards became trivial 
from frequent repetition, and in this way came to be used in a 
flippant and superficial manner, were then delivered with all the 





1 The most important authority is Cecilius of Calacte, a distinguished rheto- 
rician of Cicero’s time, many of whose striking judgments and important re- 
marks are still extant. See the Vitw X. Orator., c. 1. Photius, Biblioth. Codex, 
259. 
~ 2 When rhetorical studies were still a novelty, Thucydides at the age of 
twenty might easily have been the scholar of Antiphon, who was eight years his 
senior. 

3 Dionys. Hal., de verb. comp., p. 150, Reiske. Tryphon, in Walz, Rhet., ὃ. 
VIIL., p. 750. 

4 αὐστηρὸς χαρακτήρ, αὐστηρὰ ἁρμονία, austerum dicendi genus ; see Dionys. Hal., 
de compos. verborum, p. 147, seqq. 


STYLE OF ANTIPHON. 109 


energetic carnestness of real feeling; and, without taking into 
consideration the value and importance of their works as pro- 
ducts of human genius, we find in writers like Antiphon and 
Thucydides, a continual liveliness, an inexhaustible vigour of 
mind, which, not to go farther, places them above even Plato 
and Demosthenes, notwithstanding their better training and 
wider experience. 

§ 4. We shall arrive at a clearer conception of the train of 
thought in these writers by considering, first the words, and 
then the syntactical combinations by which their style was dis- 
tinguished. Great accuracy in the use of expressions’ is a 
characteristic as well of Antiphon as of Thucydides. This is 
manifested, among other things, by an attempt to make a 
marked distinction between synonyms and words of similar 
sound: this originated with Prodicus, and both in this Sophist 
and in the authors of whom we are speaking occasionally gave 
an air of extravagance and affectation to their style Not to 
speak of individual words, the luxuriance of grammatical forms 
in the Greek language and the readiness with which it ad- 
mitted new compounds, enabled these authors to create whole 
classes of expressions indicating the most delicate shades of 
meaning, such as the neuter participles.’ In regard to the gram- 
matical forms and the connecting particles, the old writers did 
not strive after that regular continuity which gives an equable 
flow to the discourse, and enables one to see the whole con- 
nexion from any part of it: they considered it of more im- 
portance to express the finer modifications of meaning by changes 
in the form of words, even though this might produce abrupt- 
ness and difficulty in the expressions.‘ With respect to the 





1 ἀκριβολογία ἐπὶ τοῖς ὀνόμασιν, Marcellin., vita Thucyd., § 36. 

2 As when Antiphon says (de ced. Herod., § 94, according to the probable read- 
ing): ‘You are now scrutineers (γνωρισταὶ) of the evidence; then you will be 
judges (δικασταί) of the suit: you are now only guessers (Sofacrai), you will then 
be deciders (κριταί) of the truth.’ See the similar examples in §§ ΟἹ, 92. 

3 As when Antiphon says (TZetral. I., y. ὃ 3): ‘The danger and the disgrace 
which had greater influence than the quarrel, were sufficient to subdue the passion 
that was boiling in his mind’ (σωφρονίσαι τὸ θυμούμενον τῆς γνώμης). Thucydides, 
who is as partial as Antiphon to this mode of expression, also uses the phrase, 7d 
θυμούμενον THs γνώμης, VIII. 68. 

4 As an example, we may mention Antiphon’s common practice of passing from. 


110 POLITICAL AND FORENSIC ORATORY. 


connexion of the sentences with one another, the language of 
Antiphon and Thucydides stands half-way between the con- 
secutive but unconnected diction of Herodotus' and the periodic 
style of the school of Isocrates. We shall consider in one of 
the following chapters how the period, which conveys an idea 
of a style finished and rounded off, was first cultivated in that 
later school: here it will be sufficient to mention the total 
want of such a finished periodic completeness in the writings of 
Antiphon and Thucydides. There are, indeed, plenty of long 
sentences in these authors, in which they show a power of 
bringing thoughts and observations into the right connexion with 
each other. But these long sentences appear as a heaping 
together of thoughts without any necessary rule or limit, such 
that if the author had known any further circumstances likely 
to support his argument, he might have added or incorporated 
those circumstances,’ and not as a whole of which all the 
subordinate particulars were necessary integral parts. The only 
structure of sentences which was cultivated to any great extent 
at this period was that in which the different members are not 
related to one another as principal or subordinate, but merely 
as consecutive sentences, ὁ. 6. the copulative, adversative, and 
disjunctive sentences ;* and these were consistently and artfully 
carried out in all their parts. It is indeed very worthy of 
remark, how skilfully an orator like Antiphon arranged his 
thoughts so that they always produced those binary combina- 
tions of corresponding or opposed members ; and how labori- 
ously he strove to exhibit on every side this symmetrical relation, 
and, like an architect, carried the symmetry through all the 
details of his work. To take an example, the orator has 
scarcely opened his mouth to speak on the murder of Herodes 
when he falls into a system of parallelisms such as we haye 





the copulative to the adversative. He often begins with καὶ, but substitutes a δὲ 
for the corresponding καὶ which should follow. This represents the two members 
as at first corresponding parts of a whole, and thus the opposition of the second to 
the first is rendered more prominent and striking. 

1 λέξις εἰρομένη. 

5 This structure of sentences, which occurs principally in narrative, will be dis- 
cussed more at length when we come to Thucydides. 

3 The sentences with καὶ (re) —xal, with μὲν —6é, with 4 (wérepov)—#. In 
general, this constitutes the ἀντικειμένη λέξις, 


STYLE OF ANTIPHON. 111 


just described: ‘ Would that my oratorical skill and knowledge 
of affairs, O judges, were equal to my unhappy condition and 
the misfortunes which I have suffered. As it is, however, I 
have more of the latter than I ought to have; whereas the 
former fails me more than is expedient for me. For where I 
was in bodily peril on account of an unjust accusation, there 
my knowledge of affairs was of no avail; and now that I have 
to save my life by a true statement of the case, I am injured 
by my inability to speak ;’ and so forth. It is clear that this 
symmetrical structure of sentences’ must have had its origin in 
a very peculiar bias of mind; namely, in the habitual proneness 
to compare and discriminate, to place the different points of a 
subject in such connexion that their likeness or dissimilitude 
might appear in the most marked manner; in a word, this 
mode of writing presumes that peculiar combination of ingenuity 
and shrewdness for which the old Athenians were so pre- 
eminently distinguished. At the same time it cannot be de- 
nied that the habit of speaking in this way had something 
misleading in it, and that this parallelism of the members of a 
sentence was often carried much farther than the natural con- 
ditions of thought would have prescribed ; especially as a mere 
formal play with sounds united itself with this striving after an 
opposition of ideas and a counterpoise of thoughts, the object 
being to make this relation of the thoughts significant to the 
ear also; but this was pursued so eagerly that the real object 
was often overlooked. 

The figures of speech, which were mentioned while we were 
speaking of Gorgias,—the Isocola, Homeoteleuta, Parisa, Paro- 
nomasie, and Parecheseis,—were admirably suited to this sym- 
metrical architecture of the periods. The ornaments of diction 
are all found in Antiphon, but not in such numbers as in 
Gorgias, and they are treated with Attic taste and discern- 
ment. But Antiphon also makes his antitheses of equal num- 
bers of like-sounding words balanced against one another. 





1 This is the ἐναρμόνιος σύνθεσις of Cxcilius of Calacte (Photius, Cod. 259), the 
concinnitas of Cicero. 

2 Ase.g., inde ced. Herod., § 73: ‘There must be more in your power to save 
me justly, than in my enemies’ wish to destroy me unjustly’—7d ὑμέτερον δυνάμενον 
ἐμὲ δικαίως σώζειν ἢ τὸ τῶν ἐχθρῶν βουλόμενον ἀδίκως ἐμὲ ἀπολλύναι, 


112 POLITICAL AND FORENSIC ORATORY. 


Antiphon, too, is fond of opposing words of similar sound in 
order to call attention to their contrasted significations,’ and his 
diction has something of that precision and constrained regu- 
larity which reminds us of the stiff symmetry and parallelism of 
attitudes in the older works of Greek sculpture. 

§ 5. Though Antiphon by the use of these artifices, which 
the old rhetoricians called ‘ figures of diction,’® was enabled to 
trick out his style with a sort of antique ornaments, he did not, 
according to the judicious remark of one of the best rhetori- 
cians,* make any use of the ‘ figures of thought.’* These turns 
of thought, which interrupt its equable expression, proceed for 
the most part from passion and feeling, and give langnage its 
pathos; they consist of the sudden burst of indignation, the 
ironical and sarcastic question, the emphatic and vehement 
repetition of the same idea under different forms,’ the gradation 
of weight and energy,’ and the sudden breaking off in the midst 
of a sentence, as if that which was still to be said transcended 
all power of expression.’ But there is often as much of artful 
design as of violent emotion in these figures of thought: thus 
the orator will sometimes seek about for an expression as if he 
could not find the right one, in order that he may give the 
proper phrase with greater force after he has discovered it :° 
sometimes he will correct what he has said, in order to convey 
an idea of his great scrupulousness and accuracy ;° he will 
suggest an answer in the mind of his adversary, as if it was 
obvious and inevitable; or he will pervert the other party’s 
words, so as to give them an entirely different signification ; 
and so forth. All these forms of speech are foreign to the old 
Attic oratory, for reasons which lie deeper than in the history 





1 We have an example of this Paronomasia in de ced. Herod., ὃ 91: ‘If some 
error must be committed, it is more consonant, to piety to acquit unjustly, than to 
eondemn contrary to justice. — ἀδίκως ἀπολῦσαι ὁσιώτερον ἂν εἴη τοῦ μὴ δικαίως 
ἀπολέσαι. 

2 σχήματα τῆς λέξεως. : 

3 Cecilius of Calacte (apud Phot., Cod. 250, p. 485 Bekker), who adds with great 
judgment, ‘ that he will not assert that the figures of thought never occur in Anti- 
phon, but that when they occur, they are not designed (κατ᾽ ἐπιτήδευσω), and that 
they are of rare occurrence.’ 

4 σχήματα THs διανοίας. 5 Polyptoton. 
6 Climax. 7 Aposiopesis, 8 Aporia. 
9 Epidiorthosis, also called Metanewa, 10 Anaclasis. 


ANDOCIDES. 113 


of the rhetorical schools, viz. in the developement and pro- 
gressive change of the Athenian character. These figures rest, 
as has just been shown, partly on a violence of passion which 
lays aside all claim to tranquillity and self-control; partly in a 
sort of crafty dissimulation which employs every artifice in order 
to make the appearances all on its own side.’ These two 
qualities—vehemence of passion and tricky artifice—did not 
become the prominent features of the Athenian character till a 
later period, and though they grew stronger and stronger after 
the shock given to the morality of Greece by the speculations of 
the Sophists, and at the same time by the party-spirit which 
the Peloponnesian war engendered, and which, according to 
Thueydides,? nurtured the prevailing tendency to intrigue, yet 
it was some time before the art of speaking arrived at that 
stage of developement which necessitated or admitted these 
peculiar figures of speech. In Antiphon, as well as in Thucy- 
dides, the old equable and tranquil style is still prevalent: all 
the efforts of the orator are directed to the invention and oppo- 
sition of the ideas which his argument requires him to bring 
forward: all that is unreal or delusive consists in the thoughts 
themselves, not in any obscurity produced by the excitements 
of passion. On the few occasions when Antiphon spoke, he 
must have spoken, like Pericles, with unmoved countenance, 
and in a tone of the most tranquil self-command, although his 
contemporary Cleon, whose style of speaking was very far 
removed from the artificial oratory of the day, used to run 
backwards and forwards on the bema, throwing his mantle 
aside and smiting his thigh with violent and excited gesti- 
culations.* 

§ 6. Anpocipes, who stands next to Antiphon in point of 
time, and some of whose speeches have come down to us, is a 
more interesting person in reference to the history of Athens at 
this period than in regard to the cultivation of rhetoric. Sprung 
from a noble family which furnished the heralds for the 





1 Tavovpyia. On this account the σχήματα τῆς διανοίας are called by Cexcilius 
τροπὴν ἐκ τοῦ πανούργου καὶ ἐνάλλαξιν. 
3 Thucyd. III., 82. 
3 This is mentioned by Plutarch (Nic. VIII., Tib. Gracch. II.) as the first offence 
ever committed against the decency (κόσμος) of public speaking. 
Vou. 11. I 


114 POLITICAL AND FORENSIC ORATORY. 


Eleusinian mysteries,’ we find him employed at an early age as 
general and ambassador, until he was involved in the legal 
proceedings about the mutilation of the Herme and the profana- 
tion of the mysteries; he escaped by denouncing the guilty, 
whether truly or falsely, but was obliged to leave Athens. 
From this time he occupied himself with commercial transac- 
tions, which he carried on chiefly in Cyprus, and with endeavours 
to get recalled from banishment; until,-on the downfall of the 
thirty tyrants, he returned to his native city under the protec- 
tion of the general amnesty which the opposing parties had 
sworn to observe. Though he was not without molestation on 
account of the old charge, we find him still engaged in public 
affairs, till at last, beimg sent as ambassador to Sparta in the 
course of the Corinthian war, in order to negotiate a peace, he 
was again banished by the Athenians because the result of his 
negotiations was unsatisfactory. 

We have three remaining speeches by Andocides: the first 
relating to his return from exile, and delivered after the restora- 
tion of the democracy by the overthrow of the Four Hundred 
Counsellors ; the second relating to the mysteries, and delivered 
in Ol. 95, 1. B.c. 400, in which Andocides endeavours to confute - 
the continually reviving charge with respect to the profanation 
of the mysteries, by going back to the origin of the whole 
matter ; the third on the peace with Lacedzemon, delivered in 
Ol. 97, 1. B.c. 392, ἴῃ which the orator urges the Athenian 
assembly to conclude peace with the Spartans. The genuine- 
ness of the last speech is doubted even by the old grammarians: 
but the speech against Alcibiades, the object of which is to get 
Alcibiades ostracized instead of the orator, is undoubtedly 
spurious. If the speech were genuine it could not have been 
written by Andocides consistently with the well-known circum- 
stances relating to the ostracism of Alcibiades: in that case it 
must be assigned to Phzeax, who shared with Alcibiades in the 
danger of ostracism; and this is the opinion of a modern 
critic °° but the contents and form of the speech prove beyond 





1 τὸ τῶν κηρύκων τῆς μυστηριωτίδος γένος. 
2 Taylor (Lectiones Lysiace, c. VI.), who has not been refuted by Ruhnken and 
Valckenaer.—[See Thirlwall, Hist. of Greece, ITI., p. 463.—Ep.] 


ANDOCIDES. 115 


all power of confutation that it is an imitation by some later 
rhetorician.’ 

Although Andocides has been included in the list of the ten 
celebrated orators, he is very inferior to the others in talent and 
art. He exhibits neither any particular acuteness in treating 
the great events which are referred to in his speeches, nor that 
precision in the connexion of his thoughts which marks all the 
other writers of this time: yet we must give him credit for his 
freedom from the mannerism into which the more distinguished 
men of the age so easily fell, and also for a sort of natural 
liveliness, which may together be considered as reliques of the 
austere style, as it appears in Antiphon and Thucydides.® 





1 According to Meier, de Andocidis que vulgo fertur oratione in Alcibiadem, a 
series of programmes of the University of Halle. 

2 It is surprising that Critias was not rather enrolled among the Ten, but 
perhaps his having been one of the Thirty stood in his way. Comp. Chap, XXXT, 
§ 4. 

3 The ἀντικειμένη λέξις prevails in Andocides also, but without any striving after 
symmetry of expression. 


116 


CHAPTER XXXIV. 
THE POLITICAL HISTORIOGRAPHY OF THUCYDIDES. 


$ 1, The life of Thucydides: his training that of the age of Pericles. § 2. His 
new method of treating history. § 3. The consequent distribution and arrange- 
ment of his materials, as well in his whole work as, § 4, in the introduction. 
§ 5. His mode of treating these materials ; his research and criticism. ὃ 6. Ac- 
curacy and, § 7, intellectual character of his history. §§ 8, 9. The speeches 
considered as the soul of his history. 88 10, 11. His mode of expression and 
the structure of his sentences. 


§ 1. HUCYDIDES, an Athenian of the demus of Alimus, 
was born in Ol. 77, 2. B.c. 471, nine years after the 
battle of Salamis.' His father Olorus, or Orolus, has a 
Thracian name, although Thucydides himself was an Athenian 
born: his mother Hegesipyle bears the same name as the 
Thracian wife of the Great Miltiades, the conqueror at Ma- 
rathon ; and through her Thucydides was connected with the 
renowned family of the Philaide. This family from the time 
of the older Miltiades, who left Athens during the tyranny of 
the Pisistratidee and founded a principality of his own in the 
Thracian Chersonese, had formed alliances with the people and 
princes of that district ; the younger Miltiades, the Marathonian 
victor, had married the daughter of a Thracian king named 
Orolus ; the children of this marriage were Cimon and the 
younger Hegesipyle, the latter of whom married the younger 
Orolus, probably a grandson of the first, who had obtained the 
rights of citizenship at Athens through his connexions ; the son 
of this marriage was Thucydides.’ 





1 According to the well known statement of Pamphila (a learned woman of 
Nero’s time), cited by Gellius, NV. A. XV., 23. This statement is not impugned 
by what Thucydides says himself (V., 26), that he was of the right age to observe 
the progress of the Peloponnesian war. He might well say this of the period 
between the 40th and 67th years of his life; for though the ἡλικία in reference to 
military service was different, it seems that the ancients placed the age suitable to 
literary labours at a more advanced point than we do. 

% This is the best way of reconciling the statements ofMarcellinus (vita Thucy- 








THUCYDIDES. 117 


_ In this way Thucydides belonged to a distinguished and 
powerful family, possessed of great riches, especially in Thrace. 
Thucydides himself owned some gold-mines in that country, 
namely, at Scapte-Hyle (or Wald-rode, as it would have been 
called in the Harz), in the same district from which Philip of 
Macedon afterwards derived those resources by which he esta- 
blished his power in Greece. This property had great influence 
_ on the destiny of Thucydides, especially in regard to his banish- 
ment from Athens, the chief particulars of which we learn from 
himself." In the eighth year of the Peloponnesian war (Ol. 89, 
I. B.c. 423) the Spartan general, Brasidas, was desirous of 
taking Amphipolis on the Strymon. Thucydides, the son of 
Olorus, lay off Thasos with a small fleet of seven ships, probably 
on his first command, which he had merited by his services in 
some subordinate military capacity. Brasidas feared eyen this 
small fleet, because he knew that the admiral possessed gold- 
mines in the district and had great influence with the most 
powerful inhabitants of the country, so that he would have no 
difficulty in getting together a body of native troops to reinforce 
the garrison of Amphipolis. Accordingly, Brasidas granted 
the Amphipolitans a better capitulation than they expected, in 
order to gain possession of the place speedily, and Thucydides 
haying come too late to raise the siege, was obliged to content 
himself with the defence of Eion, a fortified city near the coast. 
The Athenians, who were in the habit of judging their generals 
and statesmen according to the success of their plans, con- 
demned him for neglect of duty ;? and he was compelled to go 
into exile, in which state he continued for twenty years, living 
principally at Scapte-Hyle. He was not permitted to return 





didis) and Suidas with the well-known historical data. The following is the 
whole genealogy :— 
Cimon Stesagore f. Olorus, Thracum regulus. 





Attica uxor — Miltiades Marathon. Hegesipyle I. Filius. 


ee 
Elpinice. Cimon Hegesipyle IT. ~ Olorus IT. 
Thucydides. 


1 Thucyd. IV., 104, seqq. 
3 The charge against him was probably a γραφὴ mpodoctas. 


118 THE POLITICAL HISTORIOGRAPHY OF THUCYDIDES. 


after the peace between Sparta and Athens, but was only re- 
called by a special decree when Thrasybulus had. restored the 
democracy. After this he must have lived some years at 
Athens, as his history clearly evinces; but not so long as 
nature would have permitted: and there is much probability in 
the statement that he lost his life by the hand of an assassin." 

From this account of the career of Thucydides it appears 
that he spent only the first part of his life, up to his forty- 
eighth year, in intercourse with his countrymen of Athens. 
After this period he was indeed in communication with all 
parts of Greece, and he tells us that his exile had enabled him 
to mix with Peloponnesians, and to gain accurate information 
from them :? but he was out of the way of the intellectual 
revolution which took place at Athens between the middle and 
end of the Peloponnesian war: and when he returned home he 
found himself in the midst of a new generation, with novel 
ideas and an essentially altered taste, with which he could 
hardly have amalgamated so thoroughly in his old age as to 
change his own notions in accordance with them. Thucydides, 
therefore, is altogether an old Athenian of the school of Pericles ; 
his education, both real and formal, is derived from that grand 
and mighty period of Athenian history ; his political principles 
are those which Pericles inculcated; and his style is, on the 
one hand, a representative of the native fulness and vigour of 
Periclean oratory, and on the other hand an offshoot of the 
antique, artificial rhetoric taught in the school of Antiphon.* 

§ 2. As an historian, Thucydides is so far from belonging to 
the same class as the Ionian logographi, of whom Herodotus 
was the chief, that he may rather be considered as having com- 
menced an entirely new class of historical writing. He was 





1 We have passed over in silence unimportant and doubtful points, as well as 
manifest errors, especially those introduced into the old biographies of the historian 
by the confusion between him and the more celebrated statesman, Thucydides, the 
son of Melesias, 

2 Thucyd, V., 26. 

8 The relation between Thucydides and Pericles is recognized by Wyttenbach, 
who, in the preface to his Zcloge Historice, justly remarks: Thucydides ita se ad 
Periclis imitationem composuisse videtur, ut, quum scriptum viri nullum exstet, ejus 
eloquentie formam efigiemque per totum historia opus expressam posteritati servaret, 
On the teaching of Antiphon, see Chap. X XXIII, ὃ 3. 


METHOD OF THUCYDIDES. 119 


acquainted with the works of several of these Ionians (whether 
or not with that of Herodotus is doubtful’), but he mentions 
them only to throw them aside as uncritical, fabulous, and 
designed for amusement rather than instruction. Thucydides 
directed his attention to the public speeches delivered in the 
public assemblies and the law-courts of Greece: this was the 
foundation of his history, in regard both to its form and its 
materials. While the earlier historians aimed at giving a vivid 
picture of all that fell under the cognizance of the senses by 
describing the situation and products of different countries, the 
peculiar customs of different nations, the works of art found in 
different places, and the military expeditions which were under- 
taken at different periods; and, while they endeavoured to 
represent a superior power ruling with infinite authority over 
the destinies of people and princes, the attention of Thucydides 
was directed to human action as it is developed from the 
character and situations of the individual, as it operates on the 
condition of the world in general. In accordance with this 
object, there is a unity of action in his work ; it is an historical 
drama, a great law-suit, the parties to which are the belligerent 
republics, and the object of which is the Athenian domination 
over Greece. It is very remarkable that Thucydides, who 
created this kind of history, should have conceived the idea 
more clearly and vigorously than any of those who followed in 
his steps. His work was destined to be only the history of the 
Peloponnesian war, not the history of Greece during the Pelo- 
ponnesian war: consequently, he had excluded everything per- 
taining either to the foreign relations or the internal policy of 
the different states which did not bear upon the great contest 
for the Hegemony, or chief power in Greece: but, on the other 
hand, he kas admitted everything, to whatever part of Hellas it 
referred, which was connected with this strife of nations. From 
the first, Thucydides had considered this war as a great event 





1 The supposed references to Herodotus in I. 20, IT. 8, 97, are not quite clear ; 
in the history of the murder of Hipparchus, which Thucydides refers to twice (I. 
20., VI. 54—59), in order to correct the false opinions of his contemporaries, 
Herodotus agrees almost entirely with him, and is free from those false opinions : 
see Herodotus, V. 55, VI. 123. Thucydides would probably have written differ- 
ently on several points had he been acquainted with the work of Herodotus, es- 
pecially the passages I. 74, II. 8. Comp. above Chap. XIX. § 3. 


. 


120 THE POLITICAL HISTORIOGRAPHY OF THUCYDIDES. 


in the history of the world, as one which could not be ended 
without deciding the question, whether Athens was to become a 
great empire, or whether she was to be reduced to the condition 
of an ordinary Greek republic, surrounded by many others 
equally free and equally powerful: he could not but see that 
the peace of Nicias, which was concluded after the first ten 
years of the war, had not really put an end to it; that it was 
but interrupted by an equivocal and ill-observed armistice, and 
that it broke out afresh during the Sicilian expedition: with 
the zeal of an interested party, and with all the power of truth, 
he shows that all this was one great contest, and that the peace 
was not a real one.’ 

§ 3. Thucydides has distributed and arranged his materials 
according to this conception of his subject. The war itself is 
divided according to the mode in which it was carried on, and 
which was regulated among the Greeks, more than with us, by 
the seasons of the year: the campaigns were limited to the 
summer; the winter was spent in preparing the armaments and 
in negotiation. As the Greeks had no general era, and as the 
calendar of each country was arranged according to some pecu- 
liar cycle, Thucydides takes his chronological dates from the 
sequence of the seasons, and from the state of the corn-lands, 
which had a considerable influence on the military proceedings; 
such expressions as, “ when the corn was in ear,” or “when 
the corn was ripe,” ’ were sufficient to mark the coherence of 
events with all needful accuracy. In his history of the different 
campaigns, Thucydides endeavours to avoid interruptions to the 
thread of his narrative: in describing any expedition, whether 
by land or sea, he tries to keep the whole together, and prefers 
to violate the order of time, either by going back or by antici- 
cipating future events, in order to escape the confusion resulting 
from continually breaking off and beginning again. That long 
and protracted affairs, like the sieges of Potidea and Platza, 
must recur in different parts of the history is unavoidable; 
indeed it could not be otherwise, even if the distribution into 
summers and winters could have been given ἀρ. For trans- 





1 Thucyd. V. 26. 2 περὶ ἐκβολὴν σίτου, ἀκμάζοντος τοῦ σίτου, &e. 
3 This is in answer to the censures of Dionysius, de Thucydide judicium, ο. IX., 
p. 826, Reiske. 


Sd εν 


em 


MANNER OF THUCYDIDES. 121 


actions like the siege of Potidea cannot be brought to an end 
in a luminous and satisfactory manner without a complete view 
of the position of the belligerent powers, which prevented the 
besieged from receiving succour. The careful reader of Thucy- 
dides will never be disturbed by any violent break in the history : 
and the event which, considered as one, was the most momen- 
tous in the whole war, and which the author has invested with 
the most lively interest,—namely, the Athenian expedition to 
Sicily, with its happy commencement and ruinous termination, 
—is told with but few (and those short) digressions.' The 
whole work, if it had been completed, would resolve itself into 
three nearly equal divisions: I. The war up to the peace of 
Nicias, which from the forays of the Spartans under Archidamus 
is called the Archidamian war; II. The restless movements 
among the Greek states after the peace of Nicias, and the com- 
mencement of the Sicilian expedition; III. The renewed war 
with the Peloponnesus, called by the ancients the Decelean war, 
down to the fall of Athens. According to the division into 
books, which, though not made by Thucydides, proceeded from 
an arrangement by some intelligent grammarians, the first third 
is made up of books II. III. IV.; the second of books V. VI. 
VII.; of the third, Thucydides himself has completed only one 
book, the VIIIth. 

§ 4. In discussing the manner in which Thucydides distri- 
buted and arranged his materials, we have still to speak of the 
ist book ; indeed this demands a more particular consideration, 
because its arrangement depends less upon the subject itself 
than upon Thucydides’ peculiar reflections. The author begins 
with asserting that the Peloponnesian war was the greatest 
event that had happened within the memory of man, and esta- 
blishes this by a retrospective survey of the more ancient history 
of Greece, including the Persian war. He goes through the 
oldest period, the traditions of the Trojan war, the centuries 
immediately following that event, and, finally, the Persian in- 
vasion, and shows that all previous undertakings wanted the 





1 How happily even these digressions are interwoven with the narrative of the 
Sicilian expedition ; ¢.g., the calamities produced at Athens by the occupation of 
Decelea, and the horrible massacre at Mycalessus by the Thracian mercenaries 
(Thucyd. VII. 27—30). 


122 THE POLITICAL HISTORIOGRAPHY OF THUCYDIDES. 


external resources which were brought into play during the 
Peloponnesian war, because they were deficient in two things,— 
money and a navy,'—which did not arise among the Greeks till 
a late period, and developed themselves only by slow degrees. 
In this way Thucydides applies historically the maxims which 
Pericles had practically impressed upon the Athenians, that 
money and ships, not territory and population, ought to be 
made the basis of their power; and the Peloponnesian war 
itself appeared to him a great proof of this position, because the 
Peloponnesians, notwithstanding their superiority in extent of 
country and in the number of their free citizens, so long fought 
with Athens at a disadvantage till their alliance with Persia had 
furnished them with abundant pecuniary resources, and thus 
enabled them to collect and maintain a considerable fleet. 
Having shown by this comparison the importance of his sub- 
ject, and having given a short account of the manner in which 
he intended to treat it, the historian proceeds to discuss the 
causes which led to the war. He divides these into two classes ; 
—the immediate causes, or those which lay on the surface, and 
those which lay deeper and were not alleged by the parties.’ 
The first consisted of the negotiations between Athens and 
Corinth on the subject of Coreyra and Potideea, and the conse- 
quent complaint of the Corinthians in Sparta, by which the 
Lacedzemonians were induced to declare that Athens had broken 
the treaty. The second lay in the fear which the growing 
power of Athens had inspired, and by which the Lacedzemonians 
were compelled to make war as the only pledge of security to 
the Peloponnese. This leads the historian to point out the 
origin of this power, and to give a general view of the military 
and political occurrences by which Athens, from being the 
chosen leader of the insular and Asiatic Greeks against the 
Persians, became the absolute sovereign of all the Archipelago 





1 χρήματα καὶ ναυτικόν. 

2 Thucydides’ reasoning is obviously a correct one in reference to the policy of 
a state which, like Athens, was desirous of founding its power on the sovereignty 
of the coasts of the Mediterranean : but states which, like Macedon and Rome, 
strengthened themselves by a conquest of inland nations and great masses of the 
continent before they proceeded to contest the sovereignty of the coasts of the 
Mediterranean, had γῆ καὶ σώματα for the basis of their power, and the χρήματα 
καὶ ναυτικὸν afterwards accrued to them naturally. 3 αἰτίαι φανεραί. ---ἀφανεῖς. 








PURPOSE OF THUCYDIDES. 123 


and its coasts. Connecting these remarks on the causes of the 
war with the preceding discussion, we clearly see that Thucy- 
dides designed to give aconcise sketch of the history of Greece, 
at least of that part which seemed the most important to him, 
namely the developement of the power depending on money and 
shipping; in order that the causes of the great drama of the 
Peloponnesian war, and the condition and circumstances of the 
states which play the principal part in it, may be known to the 
reader. But Thucydides directs all his efforts to a description 
of the war itself, and in this aims at a true conception of its 
causes, not a mere delineation of its effects; accordingly, he 
arranges these antecedent events according to general ideas, 
and to these he is willing to sacrifice the chronological steps 
by which the more deeply rooted cause of the war (i.e. the 
growth of the Athenian power) connected itself with the account 
of the weakness of Greece in the olden time, given in the first 
part of the book. 

The third part of the first book contains the negotiations of 
the Peloponnesian confederacy with its different members and 
with Athens, in consequence of which it was decided to declare 
war; but even in this part we may discern the purpose of 
Thucydides,—though he has partially concealed his object,— 
to give the reader a clear conception of the earlier occurrences 
on which depended the existing condition of Greece, and espe- 
cially the dominion of Athens. In these negotiations, among 
other things, the Athenians call upon the Lacedzemonians to 
liberate themselves from the pollution which they had incurred 
by putting Pausanias to death in the temple of Pallas; upon 
this the historian relates the treasonable undertaking of 
Pausanias and his downfal: with which he connects, as a mere 
episode, an account of the last days of Themistocles. The fact 
that Themistocles was involved in the ruin of Pausanias is not 
sufficient to justify the insertion of this episode ; but the object 
of Thucydides is to present the reader with the last and least 
known occurrences in the life of this great man, who was the 
author of the naval power and peculiar policy of Athens; and 
in this to take an opportunity of paying the full tribute of just 
appreciation to the greatness of his intellectual character.’ 





1 See Thucyd., I. 138. 


124 THE POLITICAL HISTORIOGRAPHY OF THUCYDIDES. 


§ 5. Thus much may suffice for the general distribution and 
plan of the work ; we now turn to the manner in which he has 
treated his materials. The history of Thucydides is not a 
compilation from books, but is drawn immediately from the life, 
from the author’s own observation, and from oral communica- 
tions ; it is the first written record of an eye-witness, and bears 
the stamp of fresh and living truth, which can only appear in a 
history of this kind. Thucydides, as he tells us himself, fore- 
saw what kind of a war it would be, and commenced his de- 
scriptions with the war itself :' in its progress, he set down the 
different events as they occurred, either from his own expe- 
rience or from careful information, which he derived, not with- 
out much trouble and expense, from persons of both parties ;? 
and he laboured at his history partly in Athens before his 
banishment, and partly in Scapte-Hyle during his exile. At 
the latter place the plane-tree under which Thucydides used to 
write was shown long after his death. All that he wrote in 
this way, during the course of the war, was only a preliminary 
labour, of the nature of our Memoirs ;* he did not commence 
the actual arrangement of his materials till after the end of the 
war, when he was again residing in his native country. This 
is shown partly by the frequent references to the duration, the 
issue, and the general connexion of the war ;* but especially by 
the fact that the history was left unfinished ; whence we may 
conclude, that the memoirs which Thucydides had written dur- 
ing the war, and which necessarily extended to the surrender of 
Athens, were not so complete as to supply the defects of the 
work. There is much plausibility, too, in the statement, that 
of the work, as it has come down to us, the last book was left 
incomplete at the death of the author, and was expanded by the 
copyist and first added to the others by a daughter of Thu 
cydides, or by Xenophon: only we must not seek to raise any 
doubt as to the genuineness of the VIIIth book ; all that we are 





1T. 1. ἀρξάμενος εὐθὺς καθισταμένου. 

2 See Thucyd., V. 26; VII. 44. Comp. Marcellinus, § 21. 

3 These are called by the ancients, ὑπομνήματα, or commentariit rerum gestarum. 

4 See Thucyd., I. 13, 93; Il. 65; V. 26. The tone of many passages, too, is 
such that we may clearly see that the historian is writing in the time of the new 
Spartan hegemony; this applies particularly to 1, 77. 


ACCURACY OF THUCYDIDES. 125 


entitled to do is to explain, on this hypothesis, certain dif- 
ferences in the composition, and to infer from this that the 
work wants the last touches of the master’s hand.’ 

§ 6. We cannot form any opinion as to the manner in which 
Thucydides collected, compared, examined, and put together his 
materials, for the oral traditions of the time are lost: but, if 
perfect clearness in the narrative ; if the consistency of every 
detail as well with other parts of the history as with all we 
know from other sources of the state of affairs at that time; if 
the harmony of all that he tells with the laws of nature and 
with the known characters of the persons of whom he writes ; 
if all this furnishes a security for the truth and fidelity of an 
historian, we have this guarantee in its most ample form in the 
work of Thucydides. The ancients, who were very strict in 
estimating the characters of their own historians, and who had 
questioned the veracity of most of them, are unanimous in 
recognizing the accuracy and trustworthiness of Thucydides, 
and the plan of his work, considered in the spirit of a rheto- 
rician of the time, fully justifies his principle of keeping to a 
statement of the truth: even the singular reproach that he has 
chosen too melancholy a subject, and that he has not considered 
the glory of his countrymen in this selection, becomes, when 
properly considered, an encomium on his strict historical fide- 
lity. The deviations of later historians, especially Diodorus 
and Plutarch, upon close scrutiny, confirm the accuracy of 
Thucydides ;? and, in all the points of contact between them, 
in characterizing the statesmen of the day and in describing 
the position of Athens at different times, Thucydides and Aris- 
tophanes have all the agreement which we could expect between 
the bold caricatures of the comedian and the accurate pictures 
of the historian. Indeed we will venture to say, that there is 
no period of history which stands before us with the same dis- 
tinctness with which the first twenty-one years of the Pelopon- 
nesian war are presented to us in the work of Thucydides, 





1 On the speeches wanting in this book, see below, § 11. 

2 Diodorus, in the history of the period between the Persian and Peloponnesian 
wars, though he adopts the annalistic mode of reckoning, is far from being as exact 
as Thucydides, who only gives a few notes of time. All that we can use in Diodorus 
is his leading dates, successions of kings, years of the deaths of individuals, &c. 


126 THE POLITICAL HISTORIOGRAPHY OF THUCYDIDES. 


where we are led through every circumstance in all its essential 
details, in its grounds and occasion, in its progress and results, 
with the utmost confidence in the guiding hand of the historian. 
The only thing similar to it in Roman history is Sallust’s 
account of the Jugurthan war and of the Catilinarian conspiracy. 
The remains of Tacitus’ contemporary history (the Historie), 
although equally complete in the details, are very inferior in 
clear and definite narratives of fact. Tacitus hastens from one 
exciting occurrence to another, without waiting to give an ade- 
quate account of the more common events connected with 
them.’ Thucydides himself designed his work for those who 
wish to learn the truth of what has happened, and to know 
what is most for their interest in reference to the similar cases, 
which, according to the course of human affairs, must again 
occur ; for such persons Thucydides bequeaths his book as a 
lasting study.?_ In this there is an early indication of the ten- 
dency to pragmatical history, in which the chief object was the 
training of generals and statesmen,—in a word, the practical 
application of the work; while the narration of events was 
regarded as merely a meaus to an end: such a pragmatical his- 
tory we shall find in the later ages of ancient literature. 

§ 7. Thucydides would never have been able to attain this 
truth and clearness in his history had he contented himself with 
merely setting down the simple testimonies of eye-witnesses, 
who described what they saw and felt, and had only inserted 
here and there his own views and reasonings. Its credibility 
rests mainly on the circumstance, that Thucydides, as well by 
education as by his natural abilities, was capable of inferring, 
from the conduct of the persons who figure in his history, the 
motives which actuated them on every occasion. It is only in 
particular cases, where he expressly mentions his doubts, that 
Thucydides leaves us in the dark with regard to the motives of 
the persons whose actions he describes; and he give us these 





1 For instance, it is extremely difficult to get an entirely clear conception of the 
war in Upper-Italy, between the partisans of Otho and Vitellius. 

2 This is the meaning of the celebrated κτῆμα és del, I. 22: it does not mean an 
everlasting memorial or monument. Thucydides opposes his work, which people 
were to keep by them and read over and over again, to a composition which was 
designed to gratify an audience on one occasion only. 


SPEECHES IN THUCYDIDES. 127 


motives, not as a matter of supposition and conjecture, but as 
matter of fact. Asan honest and conscientious man, he could not 
have done this unless he had been convinced that these views and 
considerations, and these alone, had guided the persons in ques- 
tion. Thucydides very seldom delivers his own opinion, as such ; 
still more rarely does he pronounce sentence on the morality or 
immorality of a given action. Every person who appears in 
this history has a strongly marked character, and the more sig- 
nificant his share in the main action, so much the more clearly 
is he stamped with the mark of individuality ; and though we 
cannot but admire the skill and power with which Thucy- 
dides is able to sum up in a few words the characters of cer- 
tain individuals, such as Themistocles, Pericles, Brasidas, Nicias, 
Alcibiades, yet we must admire still more the nicety with which 
he has kept up and carried out all the characters, in every 
feature of their actions, and of the thoughts and opinions which 
guided them.’ 

§ 8. The most decided and the boldest proof which Thucy- 
dides has given of his intention to set forth the events of the 
war in all their secret workings, is manifested in that part of 
his history which is most peculiarly his own—the speeches. It 
is true that these speeches, given in the words of the speakers, 
are much more natural to an ancient historian than they 
would be to one at the present day. Speeches delivered in the 
public assembly, in federal meetings, or before the army, were 
often, by virtue of the consequences springing from them, im- 
portant events, and at the same time so public, that nothing 
but the infirmities of human memory could prevent them from 
being preserved and communicated to others. Hence it came 
to pass, that the Greeks, who in the greater liveliness of their 
disposition were accustomed to look to the form as well as to 
the substance of every public communication, in relating the 
circumstance were not content with giving an abstract of the 
subject of the speech, or the opinions of the speaker in their 
own words, but introduced the orator himself as speaking. 
As in such a case, the narrator supplied a good deal from his 





1 Marcellinus calls Thucydides δεινὸς ἠθογραφῆσαι, as Sophocles, among the poets, 
was also renowned for the ἠθοποιεῖν. 


128 THE POLITICAL HISTORIOGRAPHY OF THUCYDIDES. 


own head, when his memory could not make good the deficiency ; 
so Thucydides does not give us an exact report of the speeches 
which he introduces, because he could not have recollected 
perfectly even those which he heard himself. He explains 
his own intention in this matter, by telling us that he en- 
deavoured to keep as closely as possible to the true report of 
what was actually said; but, when this was unattainable, he 
had made the parties speak what was most to the purpose in 
reference to the matter in hand.’ We must, however, go a step 
further than Thucydides, and concede to him greater freedom 
from literal tradition than he was perhaps conscious of him- 
self. The speeches in Thucydides contain a sum of the mo- 
tives and causes which led to the principal transactions ; namely, 
the opinions of individuals and of the different parties in a state, 
from which these transactions sprung. Speeches are introduced 
whenever he thinks it necessary to introduce such a develope- 
ment of causes: when there is no such necessity, the speeches 
are omitted; though perhaps just as many were actually de- 
livered in the one case as in the other. Accordingly, the 
speeches which he has given contain, in a summary form, much 
that was really spoken on various occasions ; as, for instance, 
in the second debate in the Athenian assembly about the mode 
of treating the conquered Mitylenzans, in which the decree 
that was really acted on was passed by the people; in this the 
opinions of the opposing parties—the violently tyrannical, and 
the milder and more humane party—are pourtrayed in the 
speeches of Cleon and Diodotus, though Cleon had, the day 
before, carried the first inhuman decree against the Mitylenzeans,? 
and in so doing had doubtless said much in support of his motion 
which Thucydides has probably introduced into his speech in 
the second day’s debate. In one passage, Thucydides gives us 





1 χὰ δέοντα μάλιστα, Thucyd. I. 22. 2 Thucyd. III. 36. 

3 The speeches often stand in a relation to one another which could not have 
been justified by existing circumstances. Thus, the speech of the Corinthians 
in I. 120, seqq., is a direct answer to the speech of Archidamus in the Spartan 
assembly, and to that of Pericles at Athens, although the Corinthians did not hear 
either of them. The reason of this relation is, that the speech of the Corinthians 
expresses the hopes of victory entertained by one portion of the Peloponnesians, 
while Archidamus and Pericles view the unfavourable position of the Peloponnese 
with equal clearness, but from different points of view. Compare also the remarks 
on the speeches of Pericles in Chap. XXXI. 


ee il 


SPEECHES IN THUCYDIDES. 129 


a dialogue instead of a speech, because the circumstances 
scarcely admitted of any public harangue: this occurs in the 
negotiations between the Athenians and the council of Melos, 
before the Athenian attack upon this Dorian island, after the 
peace of Nicias: but Thucydides takes this opportunity of 
stating the point at which the Athenians had arrived in the 
grasping, selfish, and tyrannical policy, which guided their 
dealings with the minor states.’ 

ὃ 9. It is unnecessary to mention that we must not look for 
any mimic representation in the speeches of Thucydides, any 
attempt to depict the mode of speaking peculiar to different 
nations and individuals; if he had done this, his whole work 
would have lost its unity of tone and its harmony of colouring. 
Thucydides goes into the characteristics of the persons whom 
he introduces as speaking, only so far as the general law of his 
history permits. In setting forth the views of his speakers, he 
has regard to their character, not only in the contents and sub- 
ject of the speeches which he assigns to them, but also in the 
mode in which he developes and connects their thoughts. To 
take the first book alone, we have admirable pictures of the 
Corcyrzans, who only maintain the mutual advantages resulting 
from their alliance with Athens; of the Corinthians, who rely 
in some degree on moral grounds; of the discretion, mature 
wisdom, and noble simplicity of the excellent Archidamus ; and 
of the haughty self-confidence of the Ephor Sthenelaidas, a 
Spartan of the lower order: the tone of the composition agrees 
entirely with the views and fundamental ideas of their speeches ; 
as, for instance, the searching copiousness of Archidamus and 
the cutting brevity of Sthenelaidas. The chief concern of 
Thucydides in the composition of these speeches was to exhibit 
the principles which guided the conduct of the persons of whom 
he is writing, and to allow their opinions to exhibit, confirm, 
and justify or exculpate themselves. This is done with such 
intrinsic truth and consistency, the historian identifies himself 
so entirely with the characters which he describes, and gives 





1 Dionysius says (de Thucyd. judic., p. 910), that the principles unfolded in this 
dialogue are suited to barbarians and not to Athenians, and blames Thucydides 
most violently for introducing them: but these were really the principles on which 
the Athenians acted. 


Vou. II. K 


130 THE POLITICAL HISTORIOGRAPHY OF THUCYDIDES. 


such support and plausibility to their views and sentiments, 
that we may be sure that the persons themselves could not have 
pleaded their own cause better under the immediate influence 
of their interests and passions. It must indeed be allowed, that 
this wonderful quality of the historian is partly due to the so- 
phistical exercises, which taught the art of speaking for both 
parties, for the bad as well as the good; but the application 
which Thucydides made of this art was the best and most bene- 
ficial that could be conceived ; and it is obvious, that there can 
be no true history unless we presume such a faculty of assuming 
the characters of the persons described, and giving some kind 
of justification to the most opposite opinions, for without this 
the force of opinions can never be adequately represented, 
Thucydides developes the principles which guided the Athenians 
in their dealings with their allies with such a consistent train 
of reasoning, that we are almost compelled to assent to the 
truth of the argument. In a series of speeches, occurring in 
very different parts of the history, but so connected with one 
another that we cannot fail to recognise in them a continuation 
of the same reasoning and a progressive confirmation of those 
principles, the Athenians show that they did not gain their 
power by violence, but were compelled by the force of cireum- 
stances to give it the form of a protectorate ; that in the existing 
state of things they could not relinquish this protectorate with- 
out hazarding their own existence ; that as this protectorate had 
become a tyranny, it must be maintained by vigour and severity ; 
that humanity and equity could only be appealed to in dealings 
with an equal, who had an opportunity of requiting benefits 
conferred upon him;’ till at last, in the dialogue with the 
Melians, the Athenians assert the right of the stronger as a 
law of nature, and rest their demand, that the Melians should 
become subject to them, on this principle alone. ‘ We desire 
and do,’ say they, ‘only what is consistent with all that men 
conceive of the gods and desire for themselves. For as we 
believe it of the gods, so we clearly perceive in the case of men, 





1 Thucyd. 171. 37. 40. This is said by Cleon, who, in the case in question, 
was defeated by the more humane party of Diodotus ; but this exception, made in 
the case of the Mitylenzans, remained an exception in favour of humanity; as a 
general rule, the spirit of Cleon predominated in the foreign policy of Athens. 


SPEECHES IN THUCYDIDES. 131 


that all who have the power are constrained by a necessity of 
nature to govern and command. We did not invent this law, 
nor were we the first to avail ourselves of it; but since we have 
received it as a law already established and in full force, and 
since we shall leave it as a perpetual imheritance to those who 
come after us, we intend, on the present occasion, to act in ac- 
cordance with it, because we know that you and all others would 
act in the same manner if you possessed the same power.’ 
These principles, according to which no doubt Greeks and other 
men had acted before them, though perhaps under some cloak 
or disguise of justice, are so coolly propounded by the historian 
in this dialogue, he has delivered them so calmly and dis- 
passionately, so absolutely without any expression of his own 
opinion to the contrary, that we are almost led to believe that 
Thucydides recognised the right of the strongest as the only rule 
of politics. But there is clearly a wide difference between the 
modes of thinking and acting which Thucydides describes with 
such indifference as prevailing in Athens, and his own convictions 
as to what was for the advantage of mankind in general and of 
his own countrymen in particular. How little Thucydides, as 
an honest man, approved of the maxims of Athenian policy 
established in his own time, is clear from his striking and in- 
structive picture of the changes which took place in the political 
conduct of the different states after the first years of the war, in 
consequence chiefly of the domestic strife of factions—changes 
which Thucydides never intended to represent as beneficial, for 
he says of them, that ‘ simplicity of character, which is the 
principal ingredient in a noble nature, was in those days ridi- 
culed and banished from the world”? The panegyric on the 
Athenian democracy, and on their mode of living, which occurs 
chiefly in the funeral oration of Pericles, is modified con- 
siderably by the assertion of Thucydides, that the government 
of the Five-thousand was the best administered constitution 
which the Athenians had enjoyed in his time ;° and also by the 
incidental remark that the Lacedzmonians and Chians alone, 
so far as he knew, were the only people who had been able to 





1 Thucyd. V. 105, according to Dr. Arnold’s correct interpretation. 
2 IIT. 83: τὸ εὔηθες, οὗ τὸ γενναῖον πλεῖστον μετέχει, καταγελασθὲν ἠφανίσθη. 
3 Thucyd. VIII. 97. 


K 2 


132 THE POLITICAL HISTORIOGRAPHY OF THUCYDIDES. 


unite moderation and discretion with their good fortune.’ And 

thus, in general, we must draw a distinction between the sound 

and serious morality of Thucydides, and the impartial love of- 
truth, which led him to paint the world as it was; and we must 

not deny him a deep religious. feeling, because his plan was to 

describe human affairs according to their relation of cause and 

effect ; and because, while he took account of the belief of others, 

as a motive of their actions, he does not obtrude his own belief 
on the subject. Religion, mythology, and poetry, are sub- 

jects which Thucydides, with a somewhat partial view of the 
matter,’ sets aside as foreign to the business of ἃ his- 
torian; and we may justly regard him as the Anaxagoras of 
history, for he has detached the workings of Providence from 
the chain of causes which influence the life of man as distinctly 
and decidedly as the Ionian philosopher separated the νοῦς from 
the powers which operate on the material world.’ 

§ 10. The style and peculiar diction of Thucydides are so 
closely connected with the character of his history, and are so 
remarkable in themselves, that we cannot but make an attempt, 
notwithstanding the necessary brevity of the sketch, to set them 
before the reader in their main features. 

We think we have already approximated to a right concep- 
tion of this peculiar style, in the remark, that in Thucydides 
the concise and pregnant oratory of Pericles was combined with 
the antique and vigorous but artificial style of Antiphon’s 
rhetoric. 

In the use of words, Thucydides is distinct and precise, 
and every word which he uses is significant and expressive. 
Even in him this degenerates, in some passages, into an attempt 
to make distinctions, after the manner of Prodicus, in the use 
of nearly synonymous words.‘ 

This definiteness of expression is aided by great copiousness 





1 Thucyd. VIII. 24. 

2 It would be easy to show that Thucydides sets too low a value on the old civi- 
lization of Greece ; and, in general, the first part of the first book, the introduction 
properly so called, as it is written to establish a general proposition for which Thu- 
cydides pleads as an advocate, does not exhibit those unprejudiced views for which | 
the main part of the work is so peculiarly distinguished. 

See Vol. I., p. 247. 
4 I. 69; IT. 62; IIT. τό, 39. 


STYLE OF THUCYDIDES. 133 


of diction, and in this, Thucydides, like Antiphon, uses a great 
number of antique, poetical words, not for the mere purpose of 
ornament, as is the case with Gorgias, but because the language 
of the day sanctioned the use of these pithy and expressive 
phrases.'. In his dialect, Thucydides kept closer to the old 
Attic forms than his contemporaries among the comic 
poets.” 

Similarly, the constructions in Thucydides are marked by a 
freedom, which, on the whole, is more suitable to antique 
poetry than to prose; and this has enabled him to form con- 
nexions of ideas, without an admixture of superfluous words, 
which disturb the connexion, and, consequently, with greater 
distinctness than would be possible with more limited and regu- 
lar constructions. An instance of this is the liberty of con- 
struing verbal-nouns in the same way as the verbs from which 
they are derived. These, and other things of the same kind, 
produce that rapidity of description, as the ancients call it,* 
which hits the mark at once. 

In the order of the words, too, Thucydides takes a liberty 
which is generally conceded to poets alone; inasmuch as he 
sometimes arranges the ideas rather according to their real 
connexion or contrast than according to the grammatical con- 
struction.’ 

In the connexion of his sentences there is sometimes an in- 
equality and harshness,’ very different from the smooth and 
polished style of later times. Moreover he does not avoid 
using different grammatical forms (cases and moods) in the 





1 These expressions, which had become obsolete in the mean time, were called 
in later times γλῶσσαι ; hence, Dionysius complains of the γλωσσηματικὸν in the 
style of Thucydides. 

2 See chap. XX VII. at the end. 

3 This is the origin of such expressions as the following : ἡ οὐ περιτείχισις, ‘the 
circumstance that a hostile city was not surrounded by walls of circumvallation ;’ 
τὸ αὐτὸ ὑπὸ ἁπάντων ἰδίᾳ δόξασμα, ‘the case in which every individual, each for 
himself, entertains the same opinion ;’ ἡ ἀκινδύνως δουλεία (not the same as ἀκίνδυνος), 
*a, state of slavery in which one can live comfortably and free from all apprehen- 
sions.’ 

4 τάχος τῆς σημασίας. 

5 As in IIL. 39: μετὰ τῶν πολεμιωτάτων ἡμᾶς στάντες διαφθεῖραι, where 
the first words are placed together for the sake of contrast. 

8 ἀνωμαλία, τραχυτής. 


134 THE POLITICAL HISTORIOGRAPHY OF THUCYDIDES. 


corresponding members of the sentence,’ or allowing rapid 
changes in the grammatical structure, which are often not ex- 
pressly indicated but tacitly introduced, an expression required 
by the sentence being supplied from another similar one.’ 

§ 1s. The structure of periods in Thucydides, like that of 
Antiphon, stands half-way between the loose connexion of sen- 
tences in the Ionian writers and the periodic style which subse- 
quently developed itself at Athens. The greater power and 
energy in the combination of thoughts is manifested by the 
greater length of the sentences. In Thucydides there are two 
species of periods, which are both of them equally characteristic 
of his style. In one of them, which may be termed the descend- 
ing period, the action, or result, is placed first, and is imme- 
diately followed by the causes or motives expressed by causal- 
sentences, or participles, which are again confirmed by similar 
forms of speech.* The other form, the ascending period, begins 
with the primary circumstances, developing from them all sorts 
of consequences, or reflexions referring to them, and concludes, 
often after a long chain of consequences, with the result, the 
determination, or the action itself Both descriptions of pe- 
riods produce a feeling of difficulty, and require to be read 
twice in order to be understood clearly and in all respects; it 
is possible to make them more immediately intelligible, more 
convenient and pleasant to read, by breaking them up into the 
smaller clauses suggested by the pauses in the sentence; but 
then we shall be forced to confess that when the difficulty is 





1 e.g., when he connects by καὶ two different constructions of cases, as the 
grounds of an action, or when, after the same final or conditional particle, he places 
first the conjunctive, and then the optative, in which the distinction’ is obvious.— 
[See Arnold’s Thucydides, III. 22.—Ep, ] 

3 The σχῆμα πρὸς τὸ σημαινόμενον, also the ἀπὸ κοινοῦ, is very common in Thu- 
cydides, 

3 Examples, I. 1: Θουκυδίδης ξυνέγραψε x.7.r. 1. 25: Κορίνθιοι δὲ κατὰ το δίκαιον 
---ἤρχοντο πολεμεῖν" and everywhere. 

4 Examples, I. 2: τῆς γὰρ ἐμπορίας x.7.r. I. 58: Ποτιδαιᾶται δὲ πέμψαντες κ.τ.Ἁ. 
IV. 73: οἱ γὰρ Μεγαρῆς---ἔρχονται. It is interesting to observe how Dionysius 
(de Thucyd. judic., p. 872) subjects these ascending periods to his criticism, and 
resolves them into more intelligible and pleasing, but less vigorous forms, by 
taking out of the middle a number of the subordinate clauses and adding them, by 
way of appendix, at the end. Antiphon resembles Thucydides in this particular 
also; ¢.g. in the sentence (Tetral. 1, a. ὃ 6): ἐκ παλαιοῦ γὰρ κ.τ.λ, 


STYLE OF THUCYDIDES. 135 


once overcome, the form chosen by Thucydides conveys the 
strongest impression of a unity of thought and a combined 
working of every part to produce one result. 

This mode of constructing the sentence is peculiar to the 
historical style of Thucydides: but he resembles the other 
writers of the age in the symmetrical structure which prevails 
in his speeches, in separating and contrasting the different 
ideas, in comparing and discriminating, in looking backwards 
and forwards at the same time, and so producing a sort of equi- 
librium both in the diction and in the thoughts. As we have 
already said, in speaking of Antiphon, this antithetical style is 
not mere mannerism ; it is a natural product of the acuteness 
of the people of Attica; but at the same time it is not to be 
denied, that under the influence of the sophistical rhetoric it 
degenerated into a sort of mannerism ; and Thucydides himself 
is full of artifices of such a nature that we are sometimes at a 
loss whether we are to admire his refined discrimination, or 
wonder at his antique and affected ornaments,—especially when 
the outward graces of Isocola, Homeoteleuta, Parecheses, &c., 
are superadded to the real contrasts of thoughts and ideas.’ 

On the other hand, Thucydides, even more than Antiphon, 
is free from all those irregularities of diction which proceed 
from passion or dissimulation ; he is conspicuous for a sort of 
equable tranquillity, which cannot be better described than by 
comparing it to that sublime serenity of soul which marks the 
features of all the gods and heroes seulptured by Phidias and 
his school. It is not an imperfection of language, it is rather 
a mark of dignity, which predominates in every expression, and 
which, even in the most perilous straits which necessarily called 
into play every passion and emotion—fear and anguish, indig- 
nation and hatred—even in these cases, bids the speaker main- 
tain a tone of moderation and reflexion, and, above all, con- 
strains him to content himself with a plain and impressive 





1 As when Thucydides says (IV. 61): of 7 ἐπίκλητοι εὐπρεπῶς ἅδικοι 
ἐλθόντες, εὐλόγως ἄπρακτοι ἀπίασιν ι. ε.,) ‘and thus those who with specious 
pretexts came here on an unjust invitation, will be sent away on good grounds 
without having effected their object.’ We have other examples in I. 77. 144; 
III. 38. 57. 82; IV. 108. The old rhetoricians often speak of these σχήματα τῆς 
λέξεως in Thucydides; Dionysius thinks them μειρακίωδη, puerilia. Compare 
Aulus Gellius, NV, .A., XVIII. 8. 


136 THE POLITICAL HISTORIOGRAPHY OF THUCYDIDES. 


statement of the affair which he has in hand. What passionate 
declamation a later rhetorician would have put into the mouths 
of the Theban and Platzean orators, when the latter are plead- 
ing for life and death against the former before the Spartans, 
and yet Thucydides introduces only one burst of emotion: 
‘ Have you not done a dreadful deed ?”? 

It will readily be imagined, on the slightest comparison be- 
tween these speeches and those of Lysias, how strange this 
style and this eloguence—with its fulness of thoughts, its terse 
and nervous diction, and its connexions of sentences not to be 
understood without the closest attention—must have appealed 
to the Athenians, even at the time when the work of Thucy- 
dides first began to attract notice. In reference to the speeches, 
Cratippus—a continuer of the history—was perhaps right when 
he assigned, as a reason for the omission of speeches in the 
VIIIth book, that Thucydides found them no longer suited to 
the prevailing taste.” Even at that time these speeches must 
have produced much the same effect upon the Attic taste as 
that which Cicero, at a later period, endeavoured to convey to 
the Romans, by comparing the style of Thucydides with old, 
sour, and heavy Falernian.* Thucydides was scarcely easier to 
the later Greeks and Romans than he is to the Greek scholars 
of the present time; nay, when Cicero declares that he finds 
the speeches in his history almost unintelligible, modern phi- 
lologers may well congratulate themselves that they have sur- 
mounted all these difficulties, and left scarcely anything in them 
unexplained or misunderstood. 





1 Πῶς οὐ δεινὰ εἴργασθε; III. 66. There is a good deal more liveliness and cheer- 
fulness (probably intended to characterize the speaker) in the oration of Athena- 
goras, the leader of the democratic party at Syracuse. (Thucyd. VI. 38, 39.) 

2 Cratippus, apud Dionys. de Thucyd. judic., c. XVI., p. 847: τοῖς ἀκούουσιν 
ὀχληρὰ εἶναι. 

3 Cicero, Brutus 83. § 288. 


137 


CHAPTER ΧΧΧΥ. 


THE NEW CULTIVATION OF ORATORY BY LYSIAS. 


§ 1. Events which followed the Peloponnesian war. The adventures of Lysias. 
Leading epochs of-his life. § 2. The earlier sophistical rhetoric of Lysias. ὃ 3. 
The style of this rhetoric preserved in his later panegyrical speeches. § 4. 
Change in the oratory of Lysias produced by his own impulses and by his em- 
ployment as a writer of speeches for private individuals. § 5. Analysis of his 
speech against Agoratus. § 6. General view of his extant orations. 


Sok, HE Peloponnesian war, terminating, as it did, after 

enormous and unexampled military efforts, in the 
downfall of the power of Athens, was succeeded by a period of 
exhaustion and repose. Freedom and democracy were indeed 
restored by Thrasybulus and his party, but Athens had ceased 
to be the capital of a great empire, the sovereign of the sea 
and of the coasts; and it was only by the prudence of Conon 
that she recovered even a part of her former supremacy. The 
fine arts which, in the time of Pericles, had been carried to 
such perfection by Phidias and his school, were checked in their 
further progress; and did not resume their former vigour till 
a generation later (Ol. 102. B.c. 372), when they sprung up 
into new life in the later Attic school of Praxiteles. Poetry, 
in the later tragedy and in the dithyramb, degenerated more 
and more into rhetorical casuistry or empty bombast. That 
higher energy, which results from a consciousness of real great- 
ness, seemed to have vanished from the arts, as it did from 
the active life of man. 

And yet it was at this very time that prose literature, freed 
from the fetters which had bound it hitherto, began a new 
career, which led to its fairest development. liysias and 
Isocrates (the two young men whom Socrates opposes one to 
another in Plato’s Phedrus, bitterly reproaching the former, and 
forming the most brilliant expectations with regard to the latter) 
gave an entirely new form to oratory by the happy alterations 


138 THE NEW CULTIVATION OF ORATORY BY LYSIAS. 


which they, in different ways, introduced into the old prose 
style. 

Lystas was descended from a family of distinction at Syracuse. 
His father, Cephalus, was persuaded by Pericles to settle at 
Athens, where he lived 30 years:' he is introduced in Plato’s 
Republic, about the year Ol. 92, 2. B.c. 411,7 as a very old man, 
respected and loved by all about him. When the great colony 
of Thurii was founded by an union of nearly all Greece (Ol. 84, 
I. B.C. 444), Lysias went thither, along with his eldest brother 
Polemarchus, in order to take possession of the lot assigned to 
his family ; at that time he was only 15 years old. At Thurii 
he devoted himself to rhetoric, as taught in the school of the 
Sicilian Sophists: his instructors were the well-known Tisias, 
and another Syracusan, named Nicias. He did not return to 
Athens till Ol. 92, 1. B.c. 412, and lived there some few years 
in the house of his father Cephalus, till he set up for himself as 
a professed Sophist.? Although he did not enjoy the rights of 
citizenship at Athens, but was merely a resident alien,‘ he and 
his whole family were warmly engaged in favour of the demo- 
cracy. On this account, the Thirty compelled his brother Pole- 
marchus to drink the cup of hemlock, and Lysias only escaped 
the rage of the tyrants by flying to Megara. He was thus all 
the more ready to aid Thrasybulus and the other champions of 
freedom at Phyle with the remains of his property, and for- 
warded with all his might the restoration of democracy at 
Athens.° 

He was now once more settled at Athens as proprietor of 
a shield-manufactory, also teaching rhetoric after the manner 
of the Sophists, when a new career was opened to him by an 





1 See Lysias, in Hratosth., ὃ 4. 

2 According to the date of the Republic, as fixed by Béckh in two Programmes 
of the University of Berlin for the years 1838 and 1839. 

3. Avolas ὁ σοφιστὴς is mentioned in the speech against Nera (p. 1352 Reiske), 
and there is no doubt that the orator is meant. 

4 Méroixos, Thrasybulus wished to have made him a citizen, but circumstances 
did not favour his design, and the orator remained an ἰσοτελής, one of a privileged 
class among the μέτοικοι. As ἰσοτελεῖς the family had, before the time of the Thirty, 
served as choregi, like the citizens. 

5 With an obvious manifestation of personal interest, Lysias (in his funeral ora- 
tion, ὃ 66) commemorates the strangers, ὁ. 6. the resident aliens, who fell fighting 
in the Peirzeus by the side of the liberators of Athens, 


ADVENTURES OF LYSIAS. 139 


event which touched him very nearly. LEratosthenes, one of 
the Thirty, wished to avail himself of the advantage granted to 
the Thirty Tyrants under the general amnesty, namely, that it 
should extend to them also, if they would submit to a public 
inquiry, and so clear themselves of all guilt. Eratosthenes 
relied on having belonged to the more moderate party of The- 
ramenes, who, on account of his greater leniency, had fallen a 
victim to the more energetic and violent Critias. And yet it 
was this very Eratosthenes who had, in accordance with a 
decree of the Thirty, arrested Polemarchus in the open street, 
carried him off to prison, and accomplished his judicial murder. 
When his conduct was submitted to public investigation,’ Lysias 
came forward in person as his accuser, although, as he says 
himself, he had never before been in court, either on his own 
business or on that of any other person.? He attacks Erato- 
sthenes, in the first instance, on account of liis participation in 
the death of Polemarchus and the other misfortunes which he 
had brought upon his family; and then enters on the whole 
career and public life of Eratosthenes, who had also belonged 
to the Four-hundred, and was one of the Five Ephori whom 
the Heterie, or secret associations, got elected after the battle 
of Aigospotami: and in this he maintains, that Theramenes, 
whose leniency and moderation had been so much extolled, 
had, by his intrigues, been a principal cause of all the calami- 
ties that had befallen the state. The whole speech is pervaded 
_ by a feeling of the strongest conviction, and by that natural 
warmth which we should expect in the case of a subject so im- 
mediately affecting the speaker. He concludes with a most 
vehement appeal to the judges: ‘I shall desist from any further 
accusations ; ye have heard, seen, and experienced :—ye know !— 
decide then !” 

§ 2. This speech forms a great epoch in the life of Lysias, 
in his employments and studies, in the style of his oratory, and 
we may add, in the whole history of Attic prose. Up to that 
time, Lysias had practised rhetoric merely as a Sophist of the 
Sicilian school, instructing the young and composing school- 
exercises. The peculiarity and mannerism, which must have 





1 εὐθύνη. 3 οὔτ᾽ ἐμαυτοῦ πώποτε οὔτε ἀλλότρια πράγματα πράξας, Eratosth. ὃ 3. 


140 THE NEW CULTIVATION OF ORATORY BY LYSIAS. 


naturally resulted from such an application of eloquence, were 
the less likely to be escaped in the case of Lysias, as he was 
entirely under the influence of the school which had produced 
Gorgias. Lysias shared with Gorgias in the endeayour to 
evince the power of oratory, by giving probability to the im- 
probable, and credibility to the incredible; hence resulted a 
love of paradox, and an unnatural and forced arrangement of 
the materials, excessive artifice of ornament in the details, and 
a total want of that natural earnestness which springs from 
conviction and a feeling of truth. The difference between these 
teachers of rhetoric consisted in this one feature: that Gorgias, 
who had naturally a taste for smart and glittering ornaments, 
went much farther than Lysias in the attempt to charm the 
ear with euphonies, to captivate the imagination with splendid 
diction, and to blind the understanding with the magic of ora- 
tory ; whereas Lysias (who was, at the bottom, a man of good, 
plain common sense, and who had imbibed the shrewdness and 
refinement of an Attic mind by his constant intercourse with 
the Athenians, having belonged to their party even at Thurii),' 
combined, with the usual arts of sophistic oratory, more of his 
own peculiarities—more of subtle novelty in the conception, and 
more of terseness and vigour in the expression. 

We derive this notion of the earlier style of Lysias principally 
from Plato’s Phedrus, one of the earliest works of that great 
philosopher,’ the object of which is to exalt the genuine love 
of truth high above that sporting with thoughts and words to 
which the Sophists confined themselves. The dialogue intro- 
duces us to Phedrus, a young friend of Socrates, whom an 
essay of Lysias has filled with enthusiastic admiration. This 
essay he reads to Socrates at his request, and partly by serious 
argument, partly by a more sportive vein of reasoning, is led to 
recognise the nothingness of this sort of oratory. It is pro- 
bable that Plato did not borrow the essay in question immedi- 
ately from Lysias, but composed it himself, in order to give a 





1 Lysias left Thurii when, after the failure of the Sicilian expedition, the Lace- 
dzmonian party there got the upper hand, and domineered over the Athenian 
colonists. 


2 According to the old tradition, it was written before the death of Socrates (Ol. 
95, I. B.O. 399). 


SOPHISTICAL RHETORIC OF LYSIAS. 141 


comprehensive specimen of the faults which he wished to point 
out. Its theme is, to persuade a beautiful youth that he should 
bestow his affections upon one who loved him not, rather than 
upon a lover. As the subject of the essay is quite of a sophistic 
nature, so the essay itself is merely the product of an inventive 
genius, totally devoid of spirit and earnestness. The arguments 
are brought forward one after the other with the greatest exact- 
ness, but there is no unity of thought, no general comprehension 
of ideas, no necessary connexion of one part with the other ; 
nor are the different members grouped and massed together so 
as to form one consistent whole: hence, the wearisome mo- 
notony of conjunctions by which the sentences are linked 
together.'’ The prevalent collocation is the antithesis tricked 
out with all its old-fashioned ornaments, the Jsocola, Homeo- 
teleuta, & The diction is free from the poetic ostentation of 
Gorgias ; but it is so carefully formed, and with so many arti- 
ficial turns, that we are at once struck with the labour which 
such a school-exercise must have cost the writer. 

§ 3. In the extant collection of the works of Lysias we have 
no school-exercise (μελέτη) of this kind, and generally, no 
speech anterior in date to the accusation of Eratosthenes: we 
have only those works which he composed in his riper years, 
and which exhibit the more matured taste of their author.’ 
Among these, however, there is one which presents traces of 
his earlier declamation ; the reason of which is to be sought in 
the difference of subject. The Funeral Oration for the 
Athenians who fell in the Corinthian war, which was written by 
Lysias after Ol. 96, 3. B.c. 394, but could hardly have been 
delivered in public, belongs to a class of speeches formally dis- 





1 Tn this short essay, three sentences begin with ἔτι δὲ. .., and four with καὶ 
μέν δὴ... 

2 In the passages (p. 233) : ἐκεῖνοι γὰρ καὶ (a) ἀγαπήσουσι, καὶ (Ὁ) ἀκολουθήσουσι, 
καὶ (6) τὰς θύρας ἥξουσι, καὶ (α) μάλιστα ἡσθήσονται, καὶ (β) οὐκ ἐλαχίστην χάριν 
εἴσονται, καὶ (γ) πολλὰ ἀγαθὰ αὐτοῖς εὔξονται, the sentences a, β, Ὕ are manifestly 
divided into three only for the sake of an equipoise of homeoteleuta. 

8 With the exception, as it seems, of the singular little speech, πρὸς τοὺς συνου- 
σιαστὰς κακολογιῶν, which is neither a judicial speech nor yet a mere μελέτη. It 
seems to be based upon real occurrences, but is altogether sophistical in the execu- 
tion. Itis a tract in which Lysias renounces the friendship of those with whom 
he had been on terms of intimacy and friendship. 


142 THE NEW CULTIVATION OF ORATORY BY LYSIAS. 


tinguished from the deliberative’ and judicial’ orations, because 
it was not designed to produce any practical result. On this 
very account, the sort of speeches to which we refer, and which 
are called ‘ speeches for display,’ ‘ show-speeches,’* were removed 
from the influence of the impulses which imparted a freer and 
more natural movement to orations of the practical kind. They 
were particularly cultivated by the Sophists, who professed to 
be able to praise and blame everything; and, even after the 
time of the Thirty, they retained their sophistic form. Such 
a work is the Epitaphius of Lysias. This oration, following 
the fashion of such ‘ show-speeches’ (ἐπιδείξεις), goes through 
the historical and mythical ages, stringing together the great 
deeds of the Athenians in chronological order; dwelling at 
great length on the mythical proofs of Athenian bravery and 
humanity, such as their war with the Amazons, their exertions 
in obtaining the sepulture of the heroes who fell at Thebes, and 
their reception of the Heracleide ; then recounting the exploits 
of the Athenians during the Persian invasion; but passing 
rapidly over the Peloponnesian war ;—in direct contrast to the 
plan of Thucydides ;—and in general laying the greatest stress 
on those topics which were most adapted for panegyrical decla- 
mation.* These ideas are worked out in so forced and artificial 
a manner, that we cannot wonder at those scholars who have 
failed to recognise in this speech the same Lysias that we find 
in the judicial orations. The whole essay is pervaded by a 
regular monotonous parallelism of sentences, the antithesis 
being often one of words rather than one of thoughts ἢ Polus, 
or any other pupil of Gorgias, could hardly have revelled more 
in assonances,’ and such-like jingling rhetoric. 





1 συμβουλευτικὸν γένος, deliberativum genus. 

2 δικανικὸν judicrale genus. 

3 ἐπιδεικτικὸν, πανηγυρικὸν γένος. 

4 The only passage in which he evinces any real interest in his subject is that in 
which he extols those who put down the tyranny of the Thirty, and among them, 
the strangers who fought for the democracy on that occasion, and consequently 
obtained in death the same privileges as the citizens themselves (§ 66). 

* As when Lysias says (δ 25): ‘sacrificing their body, but for virtue’s sake 
setting no value on their life :’ where body and life (ψυχὴ), form no real opposi- 
tion, but only a ψευδὴς ἀντίθεσις, according to the striking remark of Aristotle, 
λοι. TIT., 9 extr, 


§ παρηχήσεις, such as μνήμην παρὰ τῆς φήμης λάβων, Epitaph. ὃ 3. 


CHANGE IN THE ORATORY OF LYSIAS. 143 


§ 4. It is probable that Lysias would never have escaped 
from this forced and artificial style, had not a real feeling of 
pain and anger, like that which was excited in his bosom by the 
audacious impudence of the ex-tyrant Eratosthenes, given a 
more lively and natural flow, both to his spirits and to his 
speech. Not that we fail to recognise, even in the speech 
against Eratosthenes, the school in which Lysias had lived up 
to that time ; for the tendency to divide, compare, and oppose, 
peeps out in the midst of the most violent and energetic decla- 
mation. But this tendency is here subordinated to the earnest 
vehemence with which Lysias unveils the baseness of his 
opponent. 

This occasion convinced Lysias what style of oratory was 
both the most suited to his own character and also least likely 
to fail in producing an effect upon the judges. He now began, 
in the soth year of his life, to follow the trade of Antiphon, 
and wrote speeches for such private individuals as could not 
trust to their own skill in addressing a court. For this object 
a plain, unartificial style, was the best suited, because the 
citizens, who called in the aid of the speech writer, were just 
those who had no skill in speaking and no knowledge of rhe- 
toric : and thus Lysias was obliged to lay himself out for such 
a style, in which, of course, he became more and more con- 
firmed by habit. The consequence was, that for his contempo- 
raries, and for all ages, Lysias stands forth as the first, and, in 
many respects, the most perfect pattern of the plain (or homely) 
style. 

Lysias distinguished, with the accuracy of a dramatist, 
between the different characters into whose mouths he put his 
speeches, and made every one, the young and the old, the rich 
and the poor, the educated and the uneducated, speak according 
to his quality and condition: this is what the ancient critics 
praise under the name of his Ethopwia.* The prevalent tone, 





1 See Quinctil., Znstit. Or. IIL. 8, ὃ 50, 51: Nam sunt multe a Grecis Latinis- 
que composite orationes, quibus alii uterentur, ad quorum conditionem vitamque 
aptanda, que dicebantur, fuerunt :—ideoque Lysias optime videtur in iis, que 
scribebat indoctis, servasse veritatis fidem. 

* ὁ ἰσχνὸς, ἀφελὴς χαρακτήρ, tenue dicendi genus. 

% Dionys. Halic. de Lysia jud., c. 8,9, p. 467 Reiske, Comp. de Iso, c. 3, Pp. 
589. 


144 THE NEW CULTIVATION OF ORATORY BY LYSIAS. 


however, was that of the average man; accordingly, Lysias 
adhered to the looser collocation of sentences,’ which is observed 
in ordinary conversation, and did not trouble himself with the 
structure of periods, which were just coming into fashion : 
although, at the same time, he shows that he understands the 
art of combining sentences in one whole; and, when the occa~ 
sion serves, he can group his thoughts together and present 
them to his hearers with a vivid conception of their unity.” The 
figures of thought, as they are called, which we have mentioned 
above as interruptions to the natural current of our feelings, 
are used by Lysias very sparingly; but, at the same time, he 
altogether neglects the figures of speech, which made up the 
old-fashioned ornaments of rhetoric, and indeed, the more so in 
proportion as the tone of the particular speech is plainer and 
more simple. In the individual words and expressions Lysias 
keeps strictly to the ordinary language of everyday life, and 
repudiates all the trickery of poetic diction, compound words, 
and metaphors. His object is to supply his client with as many 
convincing arguments as he can deliver before the judges in the 
short time which the water-clock (clepsydra) allowed to the 
plaintiff and defendant in an action. The procemium is designed 
solely to produce a favourable impression, and to conciliate the 
good will of the judges: the narrative part of the speech, for 
which Lysias was particularly famous, is always natural, inte- 
resting, and lively, and is often relieved by a few mimic touches 
which give it a wonderful air of reality ; the proofs and confu- 
tations are distinguished by a clearness of reasoning, and a 
boldness and confidence of argument, which seem to leave no 
room for doubt; in a word, the speeches of Lysias are just 
what they ought to be in order to obtain a favourable decision, 
which was the only object proposed by their writer; an object 
in which, as it seems, he often succeeded. 

§ 5. The most conspicuous among the speeches of Lysias are 





1 λέξις διαλελυμένη, nearly the same as εἰρομένη. 

5 Ἢ συστρέφουσα τὰ νοήματα καὶ στρογγύλως λέξις, as it is called by Dionys. 
Hal., de Lysia jud., 6, p. 464. He differs from Thucydides in placing the con- 
firmatory sentences and participles sometimes before and sometimes after the 
main sentence: 6. g. the external circumstances first, and the subjective reasons 
afterwards. 


SPEECH AGAINST AGORATUS. 145 


those which are designed to resent the injuries brought upon 
Athens and her individual citizens, in the time of their depres- 
sion, by means of the oligarchical intrigues which preceded the 
tyranny of the Thirty, and by means of that tyranny itself, and 
in which Lysias and his family had so grievously suffered. To 
this class belongs the speech against Agoratus, which, among 
his extant orations, immediately follows that against Erato- 
sthenes ;' and, although not delivered in the author’s name, pre- 
sents many points of resemblance to the latter. By suggesting 
that the party accused is the common enemy of the judges and 
of the accuser, the procemium at once conciliates the good will 
of the judges. It draws the attention of the audience to a 
highly interesting narrative, in which the fall of the democracy 
is connected with the ruin of Dionysodorus, whom the accuser 
seeks to avenge. ‘This narrative, which at the same time un- 
folds the state of the case, and is premised as the main point in 
it,” begins with the battle of Aigos-potami, and details all the 
detestable manceuvres by which Theramenes endeavoured to 
deliver up his native city, unarmed, into the power of her 
enemies. The fear of Theramenes lest the leaders of the army 
should detect and thwart his intrigues, led to the guilt of 
Agoratus ; according to the orator’s account of the matter, 
Agoratus willingly undertook to represent the commanders as 
enemies of the peace, in consequence of which they were appre- 
hended and judicially murdered by the Council under the Thirty 
Tyrants. This narrative, which is given in the most vivid 
colours, and, in its main features, is supported by evidence, con- 
cludes, with the same artful and well-contrived simplicity which 
reigns throughout the speech, in a scene in the dungeon, where 
Dionysodorus, after disposing of his property leaves it as a 
sacred duty to be performed by his brother and brother-in-law, 





1 Tt was delivered Ol. 94, 4. B.c. 401, and is an accusation ἀπαγωγῆς, i.e. di- 
rected towards an immediate execution of the punishment, because the accuser 
regards Agoratus as a murderer, who, in defiance of the established law against 
murderers, still frequented the temples and public assemblies. 

2 The διήγησις is elsewhere used by Lysias as the κατάστασις, or definition of the 
status cause, and immediately follows the exordium ; whereas Antiphon follows up 
the exordium, without the introduction of any κατάστασις, by a part of the proofs, 
6. g. the direct proof or formal nullification, and then at last introduces the διήγησις 
to pave the way for other proofs, such as those springing from probability. 

Vou. II. L 


146 THE NEW CULTIVATION OF ORATORY BY LYSIAS. 


the accuser, and all his friends, nay, even by his unborn child, 
that they should take vengeance for his death on Agoratus, 
who, according to the Athenian way of viewing the matter, was 
considered as the chief author of it. The accuser now briefly 
sketches the mischiefs done by the Thirty—who could not have 
got their power without the intrigues here referred to ; confutes 
some pleas which Agoratus might bring forward in his justifica- 
tion, by a careful scrutiny of all the circumstances attending 
his denunciation ; then enlarges upon the whole life of Agoratus ; 
the meanness of his family, his usurpation of the rights of 
citizenship, his dealings with the liberators at Phyle, with whom 
he sought to identify himself,’ but was rejected by them as a 
murderer; then justifies the harsh measure of the summary 
process (ἀπαγωγῆ), which the accuser had thought fit to 
employ against Agoratus ; and finally proves, that the amnesty 
between the two parties at Athens did not apply to Agoratus. 
The epilogue very emphatically lays before the judges the 
dilemma in which they were placed, of either condemning 
Agoratus, or justifying the execution of those persons whose 
ruin he had effected. The excellence of this brief but weighty 
speech will be perceived even from this summary of it: it lies 
open to only one censure, which is generally brought against 
Lysias by the old rhetoricians—that the proofs of his accusa- 
tion, which follow the narrative, hang together too loosely, and 
have not the unity which might easily have been produced by a 
more accurate attention to a closer connexion of thought. 

§ 6. Lysias was, in these and the following years, wonderfully 
prolific as an orator. The ancients were acquainted with 425 
orations which passed under his name; of these, 250 are recog- 
nized as genuine: we have 35 of them, which, by the order in 
which they have come down to us, appear to have belonged to 
two separate collections.’ One of these collections originally 
comprised all the speeches of Lysias arranged according to the 
causes pleaded in them, a principle of arrangement which we 





1 Here an obscure point remains to be settled—what induced Agoratus to join 
the exiles at Phyle? The orator gives no reason for this conduct, but only adduces 
it as a proof of his shameless impudence, § 77. 

2 According to the discovery made by a young friend of the Author, which will 
probably be soon brought out in a complete and finished state. 


: 
. 


ORATIONS OF LYSIAS. 147 


have already discovered in the case of Antiphon. Of this col- 
lection we have but a mere fragment, containing the last of the 
speeches on manslaughter, the speeches about impiety, and the 
first of the speeches about injuries:’ either from accident or 
from caprice, the Funeral Oration is placed among these. The 
second collection begins with the important speech against 
Eratosthenes. It contains no complete class of speeches, but 
is clearly a selection from the works of Lysias, the choice of 
speeches being guided by their historical interest. Conse- 
quently, a considerable number of these speeches carry us deeply 
into the history of the time before and after the tyranny of the 
Thirty, and are among the most important authorities for the 
events of this period with which we are not sufficiently acquainted 
from other sources. As might be expected, none of these 
speeches is anterior in date to the speech against Eratosthenes :ἢ 
nor can we show that any one of them is subsequent to Ol. 98, 
2. B.C. 387,° although Lysias is said to have lived till Ol. 100, 
2 or 3 B.c. 378.4 The arrangement is neither chronological, 
nor according to the causes pleaded; but is an arbitrary com- 
pound of both. 





1 The speech for Eratosthenes is an ἀπολογία φονοῦ, and is followed by the speech 
against Simon, and the following περὶ τραύματος, which also belong to the φονικοὲ 
λόγοι ; then come the speeches περὶ ἀσεβείας, for Callias, against Andocides, and 
about the Olive: then follow the speeches κακολογιῶν, to his comrades, for the 
warriors, and against Theomnestus. The speech about the Olive is cited by Har- 
pocration, v. σηκός, as contained ἐν τοῖς τῆς ἀσεβείας, and so his τῶν συμβολαίων 

λόγοι, ἐπιτροπικοὶ λόγοι, are also quoted. 

2 The speech of Polystratus does not belong to the time of the Four-hundred, 
but was delivered at the scrutiny (δοκιμασία) which Polystratus had to undergo as 
an officer of his tribe, and at which he was charged with having belonged to the 
Four-hundred. The speech δήμου κατυλύσεως ἀπολογία was delivered under similar 
circumstances. 

3 The speech about the property of Aristophanes probably falls under this 
year. 

4 A speech in the first series (that against Theomnestus) was written later, —Ol. 
98, 4, Or 99, I. B.C. 384. 


148 


CHAPTER XXXVI. 


ISOCRATES. 


§ 1. Early training of Isocrates; but slightly influenced by Socrates. ὃ 2. School 
of Isocrates ; its great repute ; his attempts to influence the politics of the day 
without thoroughly understanding them. § 3. The form of a speech the prin- 
cipal matter in his judgment. § 4. New developement which he gave to prose 
composition, ὃ 5. His structure of periods. ὃ 6. Smoothness and evenness of 
his style. § 7. He prefers the panegyrical oratory to the forensic. 


§ 1. TT is very doubtful whether Plato would have accorded 

to IsocratEes in his maturer age those high praises 
which he has bestowed upon him in the earlier years of his life, 
or would have preferred him so decidedly to Lysias. Isocrates, 
the son of Theodorus, was born at Athens in Ol. 86, 1. B.c. 
436, and was, consequently, about twenty-four years younger 
than Lysias. He was, no doubt, a well-conducted youth, eager 
to acquire information ; and, to get himself thoroughly educated, 
became a pupil, not only of the Sophists Gorgias and Tisias, but 
also of Socrates. In the circle of his friends so strong an im- 
pression was created in his favour, that it was believed that ‘ he 
would not only in oratory leave all other orators behind him 
like children, but that a divine instinct would lead him on to 
still greater things. For that there was an earnest love of 
wisdom in the heart of the man.’ Such is the prophecy con- 
cerning him which Plato puts into the mouth of Socrates him- 
self. Notwithstanding this, however, Isocrates seems to have 
made no use of the great philosopher beyond acquiring from 
him such a superficial knowledge of moral philosophy as would 
enable him to give a colouring of science to his professional 
exertions. Rhetoric was, after all, his main occupation, and no 
age before his had seen so much care and labour expended on 
this art. Accordingly, Isocrates essentially belongs to the 
Sophists, differmg from them only in this, that he could not 
any longer oppose the Socratic philosophy by the bold proposal 


SCHOOL OF ISOCRATES. 149 


of making all things equally true by argument : on the con- 
trary, he considered speech as only a means of setting forth, in 
as pleasing and brilliant a manner as possible, some opinion, 
which, though not very profound, was, at any rate, quite praise- 
worthy in itself. If, however, he was less concerned about en- 
larging his ideas and getting a deeper insight into the reality of 
things, or, in general, comprehending the truth with greater 
clearness and accuracy, than about perfecting the outward form 
and ornamental finish of his style, it follows that Plato, if he 
had criticized him when farther advanced in his career, must 
have classed him among the artizans, who strove after a mere 
semblance of truth in opposition to the true philosophers. 

§ 2. Isocrates had a strong desire to give a political turn to 
the art of speaking which, with the exception of the panegyrical 
species, had hitherto been cultivated chiefly for the contests of 
the courts :*? but bashfulness and physical weakness prevented 
him from ascending himself the bema in the Pnyx. Conse- 
quently, he set up a school, in which he principally taught 
political oratory ; and so sedulously did he instruct young men 
in rhetoric, that his industry was fully recognized by his con- 
temporaries, and his school became the first and most flourishing 
in Greece.* Cicero compares this school to the wooden horse of 
the Trojan war, because a similar number of oratorical heroes 
proceeded from it. Public speakers and historians were his 
principal auditors ; and the reason of this was, that Isocrates 
always selected for his exercises such practical subjects as 
appeared to him both profitable and dignified, and chiefly pro- 
posed as a study to his hearers the political events of his own - 
time—a circumstance which he has himself alleged as the main 
distinction between himself and the Sophists.* | The orations 
which Isocrates composed were mostly destined for the school ; 





1 See the speech περὶ ἀντιδόσεως, ὃ 30, where he justly repudiates the charge, 
that he was corrupting the youth by teaching them to turn right into wrong in the 
courts of justice. Comp. § 15. 

2 τὸ δικανικὸν γένος. Isocrates, in his speech against the Sophists, § 19, blames 
earlier rhetoricians for making the δικάζεσθαι the chief point, and so bringing for- 
ward the least agreeable side of rhetoric. 

3 He soon had about roo hearers, each of whom paid a fee of rooo drachme 
(one-sixth of a talent). 

4 See especially the panegyric on Helen, § 5, 6. 


150 ISOCRATES. 


the law-speeches which he wrote for actual use in the courts 
were merely a secondary consideration. However, after the 
name of Isocrates had become famous, and the circle of his 
scholars and friends extended over all the countries inhabited by 
Greeks, Isocrates calculated upon a more extended publicity for 
many of his orations than his school would have furnished, and 
especially for those which touched on the public transactions of 
Greece: and their literary circulation, by means of copies and 
recitations, obtained for him a wider influence than a public 
delivery from the bema would have done. In this manner, 
Isocrates might, even from the recesses of his school, have pro- 
duced a beneficial effect on his native land, which, torn with 
internal discord, was striving against the powerful Macedonian ; 
and, to say the truth, we cannot but allow that there is an effort 
to attain this great object in those literary productions which 
he addressed at different times, to the Greeks in general, to the 
Athenians, to Philip, or to still remoter princes ;' nay, we some- 
times find in them a certain amount of plain-speaking ;? but it is 
quite clear that Isocrates had none of those profound views of 
policy which could alone have given weight and efficiency to 
his suggestions. He shows the very best intentions, always 
exhorts to concord and peace, lives in the hope that every state 
will give up its extravagant claims, set free its dependent allies, 
and place itself on an equal footing with them, and that, in con- 
sequence of these happy changes, something great will be under- 
taken against the barbarians. We find nowhere in Isocrates 
any clear and well-based conception of the principles by which 
Greece may be guided to this golden age of unity and concord, 
especially of the rights of the states which would be affected by 
it, and the claims which would have to be set aside. In the 





1 In this manner Isocrates endeavoured to work upon the island of Cyprus, 
where at that time the Greek state of Salamis had raised itself into importance. 
His Zvagoras is a panegyric on that excellent ruler, addressed to his son and suc- 
cessor, Nicocles. The tract Nicocles is an exhortation to the Salaminians to obey 
their new ruler; and his harangue to Nicocles is an exhortation addressed to the 
young ruler, on the duties and virtues of a sovereign. 

2 1 am accustomed to write my orations with plainness of speech,’ says he in 
his letter to Archidamus (IX.), § 13. This letter is undoubtedly genuine; but the 
following, that to Dionysius (X.), is, as clearly, the work of a later rhetorician of 
the Asiatic school. 


SPEECHES OF ISOCRATES. 151 


speech about the peace, which was published during the Social 
War, he advises the Athenians, in the first part, to grant inde- 
pendence to the rebellious islanders; in the second part, he 
recommends them to give up their maritime supremacy— 
judicious and excellent proposals, which would only have the 
effect of annihilating the power of Athens, and checking every 
tendency to manly exertion. In his Areopagiticus he declares 
that he sees no safety for Athens, save in the restoration of 
that democracy which Solon had founded, and Cleisthenes had 
revived ; as if it were possible to restore, without the least 
trouble in the world, a constitution, which, in the course of 
time, had undergone such manifold changes, and, with it, the 
old simplicity of manner, which had altogether disappeared. In 
his Panegyricus, he exhorts all the Greeks to give up their ani- 
mosities, and to direct their ambition against the barbarians ; 
the two chief states, Athens and Sparta, having so arranged as 
to divide the hegemony or leadership between them: a plan 
very sensible at the time, and not altogether impracticable, but 
requiring a totally different basis from that which Isocrates lays 
down ; for presuming a violent objection on the part of the 
Lacedzmonians, he proves to them, from the mythical history 
of early times, that Athens was more deserving of the leader- 
ship than Sparta.’ The only true and correctly conceived part 
of the speech is that in which he displays the divided condition 
of Greece, and the facility with which the Greeks, if only united, 
could make conquests in Asia. Lastly, in his Philip, a tract 
inscribed to the king of Macedon, when this prince, in conse- 
quence of the treaty concluded by Aischines, had placed Athens 
in a disagreeable predicament, he exhorts the Macedonian to 
come forward as mediator between the dissident states of Greece 
—the wolf as mediator in the quarrels of the sheep—and then 
to march along with their united force against the Persians— 
the very thing which Philip wished to do, but then he desired 





1 What Isocrates says in this speech (written about Ol. 100, 1. B.C. 380): τὴν 
μὲν ἡμετέραν πόλιν pddiov ἐπὶ ταῦτα προαγαγεῖν, at all events does not accord with 
the result of the negotiations given in Xenoph., Hellen. VI. 5, ὃ 3, 4; VII. 1, 
§ 8 and 14 (Ol. 102, 4. B.c. 369); where Athens renounces the only practical 
method of sharing the Hegemony, by landand water, which the Lacedemonians 
had offered. 


152 ISOCRATES. 


to do so in the only possible way by which it could be brought 
about, namely, as their leader, and, under this name, as the 
ruler of the free states of Greece. 

How strange, then, must have been the feelings of Isocrates, 
when news was brought to him of the downfal of Athenian 
power and Greek independence at Cheronea! His benevolent 
hopes must have been so rudely dashed to the ground by this 
one stroke, that probably it was disappointment, no less than 
patriotic grief for the loss of freedom, that induced him to put 
an end to his life. 

§ 3. The manner in which he speaks of them himself makes 
it evident that his heart was but little affected by the subjects 
treated of in these speeches. In his Philip he mentions that 
he had treated on the same theme—the exhortation to the 
Greeks to unite themselves against the barbarians—in his Pane- 
gyricus also, and dwells on the difficulty of discussing the same 
subject in two different orations ; ‘ especially since,’ to use his 
own words, ‘ the first published is.so accurately composed that 
even our detractors. imitate it, and tacitly admire it more than 
those who praise it most extravagantly.”’ In the Panathenaicus, 
an eulogium on Athens, written by Isocrates when far advanced 
in age, he says, that he had given up all earlier kinds of rhetoric, 
and had devoted himself to the composition of speeches which 
concerned the welfare of the city and of Greece in general ; 
and, consequently, had composed discourses ‘full of thoughts, 
and decked out with not a few antitheses and parisoses, and 
those other figures which shine forth in the schools of rhetoric 
and compel the hearers to signify their applause by shouting 
and clapping ;” at the present time, however, being 94 years 
old, he did not think it becoming in him to use this style, but 
would speak as every one thought himself capable of speaking 
if he chose, though no one would be able to do so who had not 
bestowed upon his style the necessary attention and labour.’ 
It is clear, that, while Isocrates pretends to be casting his glance 
over all Europe and Asia, and to have his soul filled with anxiety 
for his native land, the object which he really has in his eye is 





1 Tsocrat. Philipp., § 11. See the similar assertion in the Panegyricus itself 
§ 4. 2 Isocrat. Panathen., ὃ 2. 


SPEECHES OF ISOCRATES. 153 


the approbation of the school and the triumph of his art over 
all rivals. So that, after all, these great panegyrical orations 
belong to the class of school-rhetoric, no less than the Praise of 
Helen and the Busiris, which Isocrates composed immediately 
after the pattern of the Sophists, who frequently selected mythi- 
cal subjects for their encomiastic or vituperative discourses. 
In the Praise of Helen he blames another rhetorician for writing 
a defence of this much maligned heroine, after having professed 
to write her eulogium. In the Busiris he shows the Sophist 
Polycrates how he should have drawn up his encomium of this 
barbarous tyrant, and also incidentally sets him right with 
regard to an ill selected topic which he had introduced into an 
accusation of Socrates, composed by him as a sophistical exer- 
cise. Polycrates had given Socrates the credit of educating 
Alcibiades; ‘a fact which no one had remarked, but which 
redounded rather to the credit than to the discredit of Socrates, 
seeing that Alcibiades had so far excelled all other men.?' In 
this passage Isocrates merely criticizes Polycrates for an inju- 
dicious choice of topics, without expressing any opinion upon 
the character of Socrates, or the justice of his sentence ; which 
were considerations foreign to the question. Isocrates attempts 
to pass off his own rhetorical studies for philosophy,’ but he 
really had very little acquaintance with the philosophical strivings 
of his age. Otherwise he would not have included in one class, 
as ‘the contentious philosophers,’ the Eleatics Zeno and Me- 
lissus, whose sole object was to discover the truth, and the 
Sophists Protagoras and Gorgias.’ 

ὃ 4. Little as we may be disposed, after all these strictures, 
to regard Isocrates as a great statesman or philosopher, he is 
not only eminent, but constitutes an epoch in himself, as a 
rhetorician or artist of language. Over and above the great 
care which he took about the formation of his style, Isocrates 





1 Busiris, § 5. 

2 ¢.g. in the speech to Demonicus, § 3; Nicocles, § 1; Concerning the Peace, 
8 5; Busiris, ὃ 7; Against the Sophists, ὃ 14; Panathenaicus, ὃ 263. In his περὲ 
ἀντιδόσεως, ὃ 30, he opposes the περὶ τὰς δίκας καλινδούμενου to the περὶ τὴν 
φιλοσοφίαν διατρίψαντες. 

3 Praise of Helen, § 2—6: ἡ περὶ τὰς ἔριδας φιλοσοφία. Similarly in the speech 
περὶ ἀντιδόσεως, § 268, he mixes up the physical speculations of the Eleatics and 
Pythagoreans with the sophisms of Gorgias. 


154 ISOCRATES. 


had a decided genius for the art of rhetoric ; and, when we read 
his periods, we may well believe what he tells us, that the 
Athenians, alive as they were to beauties of this kind, felt a 
real enthusiasm for his writings, and friends and enemies vied 
in imitating their magic elegance. When we read aloud the 
panegyrical orations of Isocrates, we feel that, although they 
want the vigour and profundity of Thucydides or Aristotle, 
there is a power in them which we miss in every former work 
of rhetoric—a power which works upon the mind as well as 
upon the ear; we are carried along by a full stream of harmo- 
nious diction, which is strikingly different from the rugged 
sentences of Thucydides and the meagre style of Lysias. The 
services which Isocrates has performed in this respect reach far 
beyond the limits of his own school. Without his reconstruc- 
tion of the style of Attic oratory we could have had no Demo- 
sthenes and no Cicero; and, through these the school of Iso- 
crates has extended its influence even to the oratory of our own 
day. 


Isocrates started from the style which had been most culti- © 


vated up to his time, namely, the antithetical.’ In his earlier 
labours he took as much pains with this symmetrical structure 
as any Sophist could have done: but in the more flourishing 
period of his art he contrived to melt down the rigidity and 
stiffness of the antithesis, by breaking through the direct and 
immediate opposition of sentences, and by marshalling them in 
successive groups and in a longer series. 

Isocrates has always one leading idea, which is in most cases 
of suitable importance, fertile in its consequences, and capable 
of evoking not only thought but feeling ; hence his fondness for 
general political subjects, which furnished him best with such 
topics. In these leading thoughts he seizes certain points op- 
posed to one another, such as the old and the new times, or the 
power of the Greeks and that of the barbarians; and expanding 
the leading idea in a regular series of sequences and conclusions, 
he introduces at every step in the composition the propositions 
which contradict it in its details, and in this way unfolds an 
abundance of variations always pervaded and marked by a re- 
currence of the original subject; so that, although there is great 


1 ἀντικειμένη λέξις. 





a 


STYLE OF ISOCRATES. 155 


variety, the whole may be comprehended at one glance. At 
the same time, Isocrates is careful that the ear may be cogni- 
zant of the antitheses which are presented to the thoughts, and 
he manages this after the fashion of the older Sophists: but he 
differs from them, partly in not caring so much about the 
assonances of individual words, as about the rhythm of whole 
sentences ; partly by seeking to break up the more exact cor- 
respondence of sentences into a system less marked by the stiff 
regularity of its members; and partly by introducing into the 
longer sets of antithetical sentences, a gradual increase in the 
force and intensity of his language ; this he effected by extending 
the sentences, especially in the third member and at the end ;’ 
and thus an entirely new vigour of movement was given to the 
old antithetical construction. 

δ 5. The ancients recognize Isocrates as the author or first 
introducer of the circle of language, as it was called,’ although 
the Sophist Thrasymachus, a contemporary of Antiphon, is 
acknowledged to have been master of ‘the diction which con- 
centrates the ideas and expresses them roundly.” It was the 
same Thrasymachus whose chief aim it was to have the power 
of either rousing or quieting the anger of his hearers (e.g. the 
judges), and, in general, of working at pleasure on the feelings 
of men. ‘There was a work of his called ‘The Commiseration 
Speeches ’ (ἔλεοι), and it is to be remarked that this tendency 
of his eloquence must have induced him at the same time to 
give an easier and more lively flow to his sentences. It was 
Isocrates, however, above all others, who by a judicious choice 
of subjects, imparted to his language the harmonious effect 
which is so closely connected with the circle of language, as it - 
is called. By this we understand such a formation and distri- 
bution of the periods that the several members follow one 
another as integral parts of one whole, and the general conclusion 





1 “Tn composite sentences,’ says Demetrius, de Elocut., ὃ 18, ‘the last mem- 
ber must be longer than the others.’ 2 κύκλος, orbis orationis. 

3 ἡ συστρέφουσα τὰ διανοήματα Kal στρογγύλως ἐκφέρουσα λέξις. See Theophras- 
tus (apud Dionys. de Lys. judic., p. 464), who lays claim to this art on behalf of 
Lysias also. What is meant by the στρογγύλον appears clearly from the example 
which Hermogenes (Walz. Rhetores III., p. 704) has given from Demosthenes : 
ὥσπερ γὰρ, εἴτις ἐκείνων ἑάλω, σὺ τάδε οὐκ ἂν ἔγραψας" οὕτως, ἂν od viv ἁλῷς, ἄλλος 
οὐ γράψει. Such a sentence is like a circle which necessarily returns to itself. 


156 ISOCRATES. 


is expected by the hearer in the very place where it occurs, and 
is, as it were, almost heard before it is uttered.’ This im- 
pression is produced partly by the union of the several sentences 
in larger masses, partly by the relation of these masses to one 
another, so that, without counting or measuring, we feel that 
there is a sort of harmony which a little, either more or less, 
would utterly destroy. This is not merely true of primary and 
subordinate sentences, in the proper sense of the word, which 
are mutually developed by the logical subordination of thoughts 
to one another,’ but also holds of the co-ordinate masses of 
opposed sentences (in that antithetical style * to which Isocrates’ 
longer periods mostly belong), if a periodical cadence is intro- 
duced into them. ‘The ancients themselves compare a period 
in which there is a true equilibrium of all parts with a dome * 
in which all the stones tend with equal weight to the middle 
point. It is obvious that this must be regulated by the rhe- 
torical accent, which is the same in oratory that the grammati- 
cal accents are in language, and the arsis and thesis in rhythm: 
these accents must regularly correspond to one another, and 
each fully occupy its own place: an improper omission, and 
especially a loss of the fuller accent at the end of the period, is 
most sensibly felt by a fine and correct ear. The ancients, 
however, like the moderns, rather leave this main point to be 
fixed by a sort of general feeling, and reserve definite rules for 
the subordinate details, upon which Isocrates has bestowed most 
extraordinary pains in his panegyrical speeches. Euphonious 
combinations of sound, avoidance of hiatus, certain rhythmical 
feet at the beginning and end of sentences, these are the objects 
which he aims at with labour far more than proportioned to the 
effects which they produce on the hearer. This sort of prose has, 
in these particulars, a great resemblance to tragedy, which 
also avoided the hiatus more than any other kind of poetic 
composition.’ : 





1 Compare Cicero’s admirable remarks, Orator. 53, 177, 178. 

2 Such as temporal, causal, conditional, and concessive protases, with their 
apodoses. 3 ἀντικειμένη λέξις. 4 περιφερὴς στέγη. 

5 The ancients frequently express their well-founded opinion, that the juxta- 
position of vowels in words and collocations of words produ€es a soft (molle quid- 
dam, Cicero) and melodious effect (μέλος, is the expression of Demetrius), such as 
was suitable to epic poetry and the old lonic prose. The contraction and _elision 
of vowels, on the other hand, make language more plain and compact; and, when 


STYLE OF ISOCRATES. 157 


§ 6. Isocrates was justly impressed with the necessity of 
having a certain class of subjects for the developement of this 
particular style. He is accustomed to combine the substance 
and form of his oratory, as when he reckons himself among 
those ‘who wrote no speeches about private matters, but 
Hellenic, political, and panegyrical orations, which, as all persons 
must allow, are more nearly akin to the musical and metrical 
language of the poets than to those speeches which are heard in 
the law-courts.’’ The full stream of Isocratic diction neces- 
sitates the recurrence of certain leading ideas, such as are 
capable of being brought out in the details with the greatest 
possible variety, and of being proved by a continually increasing 
weight of conviction. The predominance of the rhetoric of 
Isocrates consequently banished from the Attic style more and 
more of that subtilty and acuteness which seeks to give a 
definite and accurate expression to every idea, and to obtain this 
object a sacrifice was made of the correspondence of expressions, 
grammatical forms, and connexions of sentences, which formed 
the basis of that impressive and significant abruptness of diction 
by which the style of Sophocles and Thucydides is distinguished. 
The flowing language and long periods of Isocrates, if they had 
had any of this abruptness, would have lost that intelligibility 
without which the hearers would not have been able to foresee 
what was coming, and to feel the gratification resulting from a 
fulfilment of their expectations. In Thucydides, on the con- 
trary, we can scarcely feel confident of having seized the mean- 
ing even when we get to the end of the sentence. Hence it is 
that Isocrates has avoided all those finer distinctions which vary 
the grammatical expression. His object manifestly is to con- 
tinue as long as possible the same structure with the same case, 
mood, and tense. The language of Isocrates, however, though 
pervaded by a certain genial warmth of feeling, is quite free 
from the influence of those violent emotions, which, when com- 
bined with a shrewdness and cunning foreign to the candid dis- 





all collisions of vowels at the end and beginning of words is avoided, a kind of 
smoothness and finish is produced, such as was necessary for dramatic poetry and 
panegyrical oratory. According to Dionysius, every hiatus is removed from the 
Areopagiticus of Isocrates; to produce this, however, there must have been a 
greater number of Attic contractions (crases) than we find in the present state of 
the text. 1 Isocrates, περὶ ἀντιδόσεως, ὃ 46, 


158 ISOCRATES. 


position of Isocrates, produce the so-called figures of thought. 
Accordingly, though we find in his speeches vehement questions, 
exclamations, and climaxes, we have none of those stronger and 
more irregular changes of the expression which such figures 
beget. Isocrates also seeks a rhythmical structure of periods, 
which seldom admits of any relation of the sentences calculated 
to cause surprise by their inequality :’ he aims at an equability 
of tone, or at least a tranquillity of feeling ; deep and varied 
emotions would necessarily break the bonds of these regular 
periods, and combine the scattered members in a new and bolder 
organization. The ancients, therefore, agree that Isocrates was 
entirely deficient in that vehemence of oratory which transfers 
the feelings of the speaker to his audience, and which is called 
δεινύτης in the narrower sense of the word; not so much 
because the labour of polishing the style in its minor details 
mars this vigour of speech (as Plutarch says of Isocrates : ‘ How 
could he help fearing the charge of the phalanx, who was so 
afraid of allowing one vowel to come in contact with another, or 
of giving the tsocolon one syllable less than it ought to have’’), 
but because this smoothness and evenness of style depended for 
its very existence upon a tranquil train of thoughts, with no 
perturbations of feeling to distract the even tenor of its way. 

§ 7. In the well-founded conviction that his style was 
peculiarly adapted to panegyrical eloquence, Isocrates rarely 
employed it in forensic speeches; in these he approximates 
more nearly to Lysias. However, he was not, like the orator 
just mentioned, a professed speech-writer, or logographus. The 





1 σχήματα τῆς διανοίας, Chap. XXXITI., ὃ 5. 

2 As in the beautiful antithetic period at the beginning of the Panathenaicus, 
the first part of which, with the μέν, is very artificially divided by the opposition 
of negation and position, and the developement of the negation in particular by 
the insertion of concessive sentences ; while the second part is broken off quite 
short. If we express the scheme of the period thus :— 


a aa, 
I II 
.--- - λον ᾿ 
᾿ α,α, ὃ, β, 9, ab 
B consists only of the words viv δ᾽ οὐδ᾽ ὁπωσοῦν τοὺς τοιούτους, In this Isocrates 
may have imitated Demosthenes. 
3 Plutarch, de gloria Athen., ο. VIII. Demetrius (de Elocut., § 247) remarks, 
that antitheses and paromeea are not compatible with δεινότης. 


STYLE OF ISOCRATES. 159 


writers of speeches for the law-courts appeared to him, as com- 
pared with his pursuits, to be only doll-makers as compared 
with Phidias ;' he wrote comparatively few speeches for private 
persons and for practical purposes. The collection which has 
come down to us, and which comprises the majority of the 
speeches recognized by the ancients as the genuine works of 
Isocrates,’? contains fifteen admonitory, panegyrical, and scholastic 
discourses, which were all designed for private perusal, and not 
for popular assemblies or law-courts; and after these come six 
forensic orations, which, no doubt, were written for actual 
delivery in a court of justice.’ Isocrates also wrote, at a later 
period, a theoretical treatise, or τέχνη, embodying the principles 
which he had followed in his teaching, and which he had 
improved and worked out by practice. This work was much 
esteemed by ancient rhetoricians, and is often quoted.* 

We have now brought the history of Attic prose, through a 
series of statesmen, orators, and rhetoricians, from Pericles to 
Isocrates: we have not yet arrived at its highest point; but 
still this was a remarkable eminence. We now go back again 
for a few years, in order to recognize, in the Athenian sage, 
Socrates, a new beginning, not only of Attic training, but of 
human cultivation in general, and to take under consideration 
a series of remarkable appearances springing from that source. 





1 περὶ ἀντιδόσεως, ὃ 2. 

3 Cecilius acknowledged as genuine only 28 speeches. We have 21. 

3 The speech about the exchange (περὶ ἀντιδόσεως) does not belong to this class. 
Τὸ is not a forensic speech, but written when Isocrates was compelled by the offer 
of an exchange to sustain ἃ most expensive liturgy,—the Trierarchy. In order to 
correct the false impressions which were entertained with regard to his profession 
and income, he wrote this speech as ‘a picture of his whole life, and of the plan 
which he had pursued,’ § 7. 

#The most important citation from it 1s that contained in a Scholium on 
Hermogenes. See Spengel, Zuvaywyh τεχνῶν, p. 161. 








ΤῈ": - [ δ 


\TION OF MULLER’S HISTORY. a 


p - 
- 
ἦν δ: : 
ts - 
« 
1 
: 
! 
ἂν» 
‘ 
τω Α ᾿ "ὦ 
( iJ 
ἢ + 





A 


HISTORY OF THE LITERATURE 


OF 


ANCIENT GREECE; 


FROM THE FOUNDATION OF THE SOCRATIC SCHOOLS TO THE 
TAKING OF CONSTANTINOPLE BY THE TURKS, 


BEING 


A CONTINUATION OF K. 0. MULLER’S WORK. 


BY 


JOHN WILLIAM DONALDSON, D.D. 


CLASSICAL EXAMINER IN THE UNIVERSITY OF LONDON ; 
AND LATE FELLOW OF TRINITY COLLEGE, CAMBRIDGE, 





161 


CHAPTER XXXVII. 


THE NEW BEGINNING OF ATTIC TRAINING—-FOUNDATION OF THE 
SOCRATIC SCHOOLS. 


δ 1. Socrates; his literary importance. ὃ 2. Aristocratic tendency of Athenian 
literature during the Peloponnesian war. § 3. How far Socrates was the 
founder of dialectical reasoning and moral philosophy, § 4. Imperfect Socratic 
schools; Eucleides and the Megarics. ὃ 5. Antisthenes and the Cynics. ὃ 6. 
Aristippus and the Cyrenaics. 


δ 1. LTHOUGH Socrates left no writings behind him, and 

perhaps does not, strictly speaking, deserve a place 
among the contributors to Greek literature, yet when we con- 
sider that the history of a nation’s literature is the history also 
of its intellectual developement, when we reflect how the intellect 
of Greece was affected by an extension of the principles of So- 
cratic philosophy, and especially when we remember that the 
greatest literary genius that ever appeared in Hellas owed 
much, if not most, of his mental training to his early inter- 
course with Socrates, we cannot well proceed any farther in our 
inquiries without bestowing a few pages on this great master, 
and the minor schools of philosophy which claimed him as their 
head. 

Socrates, the son of Sophroniscus, an Athenian sculptor, 
and of Phenarete, a midwife, was born in Ol. 78, 1. 8.6. 
468. He was brought up to his father’s profession, which he 
practised with some success, though he did not by any meana 
make it his principal occupation. A strong natural tendency 
to philosophical speculation, fostered and encouraged by fre- 
quent opportunities of intercourse with the eminent teachers of 
the day, soon drew him away to more congenial pursuits, and 
he became known, at an early period, as one devoted to the 
acquirement of knowledge, and not only willing, but eager, to 
converse with any one on those subjects which were con- 
sidered most interesting to the original thinkers of his day. 

Vou. 11. M 


162 NEW BEGINNING OF ATTIC TRAINING. 


Though strongly opposed to the tenets of Protagoras and Gor- 
gias, he was regarded by many of his countrymen as one of the 
same class of speculators: Aristophanes represents him as a 
mischievous innovator in education; and, many years after- 
wards, Aischines did not hesitate to speak of him as ‘ Socrates, 
the Sophist.’" After having served his country as a gallant 
soldier during the Peloponnesian war, and having survived the 
frightful anarchy which succeeded that struggle between demo- 
cracy and oligarchy, he was, shortly after the restoration of the 
old constitution at Athens, brought to trial charged with im- 
piety and with corrupting the minds of the rising generation ; 
and, partly in consequence of his own proud and unbending de- 
meanour at the trial, was sentenced to death, and condemned 
to drink the cup of hemlock, in Ol. 95, 2. B.c. 399. 

The circumstances which led to this catastrophe are, after 
all, those which render Socrates most particularly an object of 
interest in a literary point of view. We are not so much con- 
cerned about establishing the excellence of his moral character, 
or vindicating his claim to the first place in Greek philosophy, 
as about clearly understanding and explaining his influence on 
the literature and speculation of Greece, as they appeared after 
his time. 

§ 2. If we were asked what constituted the difference between 
the Greek literature of the fifth century B.c. and that of the 
preceding ages, we should be justified in answering, that litera- 
ture was Hellenic before that time, but that during the fifth 
century it became more and more exclusively Athenian.? Dur- 
ing this period almost every branch of literature was cultivated 
at Athens to a much greater extent than in all the rest of — 
Greece: the drama was peculiarly her own; oratory was — 
nowhere so powerful as in the Pnyx; the Attic prose style was — 
a model for every Greek writer; philosophy, whether native or — 
foreign, flourished only by the banks of the Ilissus; and, 
in every sense, Athens was the Prytaneum of Greek wis- 





1 Aschines, c. Timarch., p. 24: ἔπειθ᾽ ὑμεῖς, ὦ ᾿Αθηναῖοι, Σωκράτην τὸν co- — 
φιστὴν ἀπεκτείνατε. The connexion of Atrometus with the party of Thrasybulus 
(Aisch. Fals. Leg. p. 47), would partly account for his son’s unfavourable opinion of 
one who shrank from joining the liberators. 

2 See above, chapter XX. ὃ 2. 


LITERARY IMPORTANCE OF SOCRATES. 163 


dom,’ where the central fire blazed on its own altar, ministering, 
however, light and warmth to all the lands of Greece. Yet, 
though this great Attic literature had sprung up in the midst 
of democracy, and would, no doubt, have been checked in its 
free developement by any other form of government, it con- 
tained within itself a principle of antagonism which soon placed 
it in open opposition to that very political freedom in which it 
took its rise. In order to understand what this principle was, 
we must enter somewhat more deeply into the subject. 

When literary exertions are occasioned by something in the 
state of a country—its religion or its political constitution—as 
when the worship of Bacchus gave rise to the drama, or, more 
generally, the worship of Apollo necessitated some species or 
other of choral lyric poetry, or when the democratic constitutions 
of Greece created a school of oratory,—we may remark, that a 
conviction of the importance of the object in view stifles all 
literary vanity, and the poet is more apt to exult in the thought 
that he is a minister of the god or an influential servant of the 
state, than to take pride in the efforts of his genius. He is, in 
fact, rather a prophet than an artist. As time, however, wears 
on, the business of the literary man becomes more and more 
professional.? The poet begins to feel conscious of his own 
importance, and communicates this sentiment to others, till, at 
last, the writer of the song or hymn is more in the thoughts of 
his readers and hearers, than the deity in whose honour he has 
composed the poem. We remark something of this even in 
Pindar, for though he regards his superior endowments as na- 
tural rather than acquired,’ he is not the less disposed to maintain 
his professional superiority.“ But the tendency is more strikingly 
shown in the cultivation of prose. From the first beginning of 
artificial prose, in the time of the Sophists, down to its perfec- 
tion by Isocrates, we have seen that its prevailing feature is 





1 Plato, Protagoras, p. 337 C.: συνεληλυθότας τῆς Ἑλλάδος els αὐτὸ τὸ πρυτα- 
νεῖον THs σοφίας. 

2 Plato makes Protagoras say that all the δημιουργοί, or professional men, in the 
Homeric sense of the term, poets, physicians, and teachers of music, were sophists, 
who shrouded their one trade under the veil of these different accomplishments 
(ταῖς τέχναις ταύταις παραπετάσμασιν ἐχρήσαντο. Protag. p. 316 E.). 

5. Ol. Il. 86. 4 Ol. I, 115, 116. 

M 2 


164 NEW BEGINNING OF ATTIC TRAINING. 


self-consciousness. The prose-writer commences with an ac- 
knowledgment that he has a craft or art of his own—he is vain 
of his skill—and, either by his oral lectures, or by drawing up 
a τέχνη, or manual, professes to communicate to others the 
adroitness on which he prides himself.' From this conscious- 
ness of skill, or the power of doing what others cannot do so 
well, another feeling immediately results, namely, a sense of 
superiority in the exclusive possession of art. Hence the lite- 
rary man feels himself professional, or belonging to a class, in 
contradistinction to which all others are merely private in- 
dividuals, laymen, or ἰδιῶται, as they were somewhat contemp- 
tuously called; and at last literature, which was the type and 
the product of free democratical Athens, becomes aristocratic 
and exclusive, and paves the way to oligarchy, or, failing in this 
result, shrinks from all participation in the duties of citizenship, 
and consoles itself with the construction of imaginary and im- 
practicable forms of government, in which the philosopher alone 
is to guide and govern the state. 

This tendency developed itself more especially during the 
Peloponnesian war, which may be defined to have been the 
great critical struggle between the democratic and aristocratic 
parties in Greece. It was while Athens was outwardly con- 
tending against the aristocracy of birth, that this aristocracy 
of talent sprung up within her walls. The name by which the 
oligarchical party all over Greece delighted to be called— 
kaXoxayaSoi—properly implied education or accomplishment, 
as well as birth.” But we remark, that the Spartan nobles 
delighted more in being ἀγαθοί, ‘ well-born,’ than in their other 
title of καλοί, ‘ well-educated’ Indeed, although they usurped 
the whole name as one epithet of honour,’ the former part of 
it was not unfrequently used by them with rather a contemp- 
tuous application.*. With the literary aristocrats of Athens the 





1 See above, chapter XXXII. § 3. 

2 New Cratylus, §§ 322—325. 3 Thucyd. IV. 40. 

4 Pind., Pyth. ΤΙ, 72: μαθὼν καλός τοι πίθων παρὰ παισίν, where see the com- 
mentators, and for the proper reading compare the note on Sophocles, Antigone, 
714, p. 192. It was perhaps with some such contemptuous reference that Thera- 
menes, when drinking the hemlock, exclaimed, Κριτίᾳ τοῦτ᾽ ἔστω τῷ καλῷ (Xenoph., 
Hellen. IT. 3, ὃ 56). 


a a {ὰ.ὕ.. 


TENDENCY OF ATHENIAN LITERATURE. 165 


case was quite otherwise. Their principal renown was to 
be the pre-eminently καλοὶ, or ‘ accomplished? and they 
cared little or nothing for the distinctions of birth. They 
felt that they constituted, as, in fact, they did, a sort of 
middle class, whose interests were identical neither with 
those of the old nobles nor with those of the democracy. 
It would be difficult to name any very prominent literary 
man of this sera, with the single exception of Aristophanes, 
who did not belong to the literary aristocrats. Euripides, 
whose connexion with Socrates has long been sufficiently 
understood, expressly declares, that of the three classes in the 
state the middle one saves the city ;" Sophocles was one of the 
πρόβουλοι, or commissioners, who were selected as agents in 
the middle-class movement which preceded the oligarchy at 
Athens ;* and Thucydides does not hesitate to say, that, in his 
opinion, this movement, which is generally known as the 
government of the Five-thousand, was the first good constitu- 
tion which the Athenians had enjoyed in his time.‘ The poli- 
tical personage who was at the head of this movement in favour 
of the middle classes was Theramenes, and all the hopes of those 
who conceived it possible to have a government of the καλοὶ, or 
educated men, without falling into oligarchy, rested upon this 
versatile and not very honest statesman. Critias, on the other 
hand, was for upholding the principles of the old oligarchies, 
and cared as little for the claims and interests of the middle 
classes as he did for those of the great mass of his fellow- 
citizens. This opposition between the parties of Critias and 
Theramenes—between the old-fashioned oligarchy and the aris- 
tocracy of talent—appears to us to solve the whole problem as 
far as Socrates and his literary affinities are concerned. That 
Socrates disapproved of the views of Critias,° and would not 
contribute to carry out his nefarious measures for the aggran- 
dizement of his party,° is established by the most express testi- 





1 That is to say, they were neither τὸ φαῦλον, ‘the illiterate,’ nor τὸ πάνυ dxpiBes, 
‘the minute philosophers’ (Thucyd. VI. 18). For φαῦλος as an epithet of the 
common people, see Eurip., Bacche 431 ; Aischin., ὁ. Ctesiph. p. 65, 1. 

2 Suppl. 247: τριῶν δὲ μοιρῶν ἡ ν μέσῳ σώζει πόλιν. 

8 Thucyd. VIII. τ. Aristot., Rhetor. III. 18, ὃ 6. 

4 Thucyd. VIII. 97. 5 Xenophon, Mem. I. 2, ὃ 32. 

6 Plato, Apologia Soer. p. 32, ¢. 


166 NEW BEGINNING OF ATTIC TRAINING. 


mony. At the same time, he remained at Athens during the 
whole period of the anarchy, and never joined the patriots of 
Phyle. The inference from this is plain: he agreed with many 
and most of the principles of the educated party—the καλοί---- 
and, upon the whole, preferred an aristocracy of talent and 
knowledge to the old constitution of his country ; and, though 
he made a courageous effort to save the head of his party, 
Theramenes, from the vengeance of his great rival,’ and would, 
no doubt, have contributed what he could to give a blow to the 
schemes of Critias and Charmides, he preferred his own Gi- 
rondist theories to the revived democracy which succeeded 
the downfal of the oligarchs ; and the knowledge of this, coupled 
with the belief, however erroneous, that he was still a mis- 
chievous agent of the middle-class party, not unnaturally 
induced Anytus, one of the leaders of the party of Thrasybulus, 
to indict him before the popular tribunal, and led the Athenians 
to involve themselves in the crime and disgrace of persecuting 
intolerance.” 

§ 3. These remarks on the political tendencies of the literary 
party at Athens, in which Socrates occupied such an influential 
and prominent position, were necessary to a right understanding 
of the new direction given to literature by Socrates and his 
associates. As self-consciousness was the distinguishing feature 
of this party, so we see that egoism, in forms more or less pro- 
nounced, is the strongest mark of the post-Socratic era of 
literature and philosophy. In philosophy this has long been 
recognized. It is well known that, as the speculations of the 
older philosophers, especially those of the Ionic school, were for 
the most part confined to physics, and therefore treated only of 
the outer world, so the business of Socrates and his followers 
was chiefly with man himself, considered as a thinking subject ; 
in other words, they were all, in some form or other, ethical 
philosophers.’ The celebrated precept inscribed on the temple 





1 Diodor, Sic. XIV. c. 5: Σωκράτης δὲ ὁ φιλόσοφος καὶ δύο τῶν οἰκείων προσδρα- 
μόντες ἐνεχείρουν κωλύειν τοὺς ὑπηρέτας, ὁ δε Θηραμένης K.T.r. 

2 Mr. Maurice thinks that the Athenians were unable to tolerate Socrates, 
because he did not put forth specific opinions, but was merely a seeker of truth 
(Ancient Philosophy, p. 119). This view seems to us to be contradicted by the 
terms of the indictment, and by the antecedents of the prosecutors, 

3 See Eusebius, Prep. Evang. pp. 25, 26, 853. 


METHOD OF SOCRATES. 167 


at Delphi,— Know thyself’ (γνῶθι ccavrov),—by which So- 
crates understood that sort of self-scrutiny, which leads to a 
conviction of our practical deficiencies,—was constantly on his 
lips, and served not only to remind him of his own duty as he 
conceived it, but also furnished him with a text to justify his 
cross-examination of others. Plato makes him excuse himself 
for not engaging in literary studies, by saying :* ‘I cannot as 
yet obey the Delphic inscription, which bids me know myself ; 
and it seems to me absurd for any one to inquire into that 
which does not concern him while he is still ignorant of this.’ 
In applying this precept to others as well as to himself, Socrates 
not only repressed any self-satisfaction on his own part, but 
also exposed and rebuked the self-conceit of others. And in 
making the inquiry after self-knowledge a test of moral progress 
or political competency, Socrates generally started from the 
admitted difference between the acquaintance with a particular 
subject possessed by the professional man as distinguished from 
those who had not specially studied it. He urged that, while 
every artist and-artizan enjoyed the professional self-conscious- 
ness to which we have already referred, while he could tell how 
he came by his knowledge, while he felt himself safe and strong 
in the exercise of it, and could, if necessary, teach it to another, 
the case was strikingly different in regard to those far more im- 
portant principles by which men are guided in their social 
and political conduct,—the principles, in fact, of ethical philo- 
sophy in all its applications; here every one professed to be as 
wise as every one else; all were ready to undertake the most 
important duties; and yet no one could give an account of 
his supposed qualifications ; could say how he acquired them, 
or how he would communicate them to others.’ It was by 
means of conversation, by a searching process of question and 
answer, amounting, in many cases, to a skilful cross-examination, 
that Socrates endeavoured to lead his associates, and all whom 





1 Xenophon, Mem. IV. 2, §§ 24—26. ‘Self knowledge,’ he says, ‘consists in a 
knowledge of our capacities, with regard to the usefulness of man as such ;’ 6 ἑαυτὸν 
ἐπισκεψάμενος ὁποῖος ἐστι πρὸς τὴν ἀνθρωπίνην χρείαν, ἔγνωκε τὴν ἑαυτοῦ δύναμιν. 

2 Plato, Phedr. p. 229 E. σ 

3 See Plato, Sympos. p. 221 E. Protagoras, Ὁ. 319, 320. Gorgias, p. 491 A, &e. 
This chapter was written and partly printed in 1842. Mr. Grote has since given 


168 FOUNDATION OF THE SOCRATIC SCHOOLS. 


he had an opportunity of interrogating, to a consciousness of 
their own ignorance, and thus to stir up in their minds an 
anxiety to obtain more exact views. By his peculiar skill in 
conducting this system of questioning, he raised it to the rank 
of a scientific process, and ‘ dialectics’ (διαλεκτική) or ‘ talk’ 
became a name for the method of reasoning and the science of 
logic. This method of sifting the truth had been practised 
before him by some of the Eleatic school, especially by ‘the 
asking and answering Zeno,’ as he was called.’ But it assumed, 
under the skilful management of Socrates, a more directly 
practical application, and a more systematic form; and the 
statement that there were ten distinct schools of Socratic phi- 
losophers’ shows, at all events, how important was the influence 
of Socrates on the thinkers of his generation, while the ten- 
dency exhibited by Plato and others to frame schemes for an 
Utopian polity, in which the wise and good alone would exercise 
authority, proves that the self-consciousness of superior or pro- 
fessional knowledge was still operating on the civic character 
as it did in the latter years of the Peloponnesian war. 

As far as Socrates was himself concerned, it may be said 
briefly, that he first awakened the idea of science, and first 
treated moral philosophy according to scientific principles. 
With regard to the combination of his scientific with his moral 
principles, it may be stated that his leading idea was a conviction 
of the unity of virtue and a consequent belief that it was teach- 
able as a matter of science; so that with him the scientific and 
the moral run into one another. Thus he held that a true 
knowledge of what is morally right leads of necessity to corre- 
sponding conduct, since no one wilfully departs from that which 





due prominence to the characteristics of Socrates, which are mentioned in the text. 
He says (vol. VIII. p. 597), ‘there was no topic on which Sokratés more frequently 
insisted than the contrast between the state of men’s knowledge on the general 
topics of men and society, and that which artists or professional men possessed in 
their respective special crafts. So perpetually did he reproduce this comparison, 
that his enemies accused him of wearing it threadbare.’ 

1 Aristotle, Sophist. Hlench. c. X. ὃ 2. 

2 Diog. Laért., II. § 47, p. 119, Casaubon : τῶν δὲ διαδεξαμένων αὐτὸν τῶν λεγομένων 
ZwparixGr, οἱ κορυφαιότατοι μὲν Πλάτων, Revopdr, ᾿Αντισθένης" τῶν δὲ φερομένων 
δέκα οἱ διασημότατοι τέσσαρες, Αἰσχίνης, Φαίδων, Εὐκλείδης, Ἀρίστιππος. The Pheedo, 
here mentioned, was the founder of the Eretrian school, which was virtually sub- 
ordinated to the Megarics by its second founder Menedemus. Phedo is best known 
by the dialogue of Plato which bears his name. 


MORAL PHILOSOPHY OF SOCRATES. 169 


he knows to be good. Accordingly the moral philosophy of 
Socrates was a deduction from his theory of consciousness, and 
_ his exposure of ignorance assumed the form of a moral rebuke. 
“This waking of the idea of science,’ says Schleiermacher,’ ‘ and 
its earliest manifestations, must have been, in the first instance, 
what constituted the philosophical basis in Socrates; and for 
this reason he is justly regarded as the founder of that later 
Greek philosophy, which in its whole essential form, together 
with its several variations, was determined by that idea. For 
by what other means could he have been enabled to declare 
that which others believed themselves to know to be no know- 
ledge, than by a more correct conception of knowledge, and by 
a more correct method founded upon that conception? And 
everywhere, when he is explaining the nature of non-science 
(ἀνεπιστημοσύνη), one sees that he sets out from two tests: one, 
that science is the same in all true thoughts, and consequently 
must manifest its peculiar form in every such thought: the 
other, that all science must form one whole. For his proofs 
always hinge on this assumption: that it is impossible to start 
from one true thought, and to be entangled in a contradiction 
with any other, and also that knowledge derived from any one 
point, and obtained by correct combination, cannot contradict 
that which has been deduced in like manner from any other 
point ; and while he exposed such contradictions in the current 
conceptions of mankind, he strove to rouse those leading ideas 
in all who were capable of understanding or even divining his 
meaning.’ The irony of Socrates has been well described by 
the same‘writer, as the coexistence in him of the idea of science 
with the want of clear and complete views on any object of 
science—in a word, as the knowledge of his ignorance. ‘ It 
is clear” says an English scholar,’ ‘ that Socrates possessed, 
consciously to himself, an idea of scientific method, and that his 
repeated asseveration, that he knew nothing, was grounded on 
the comparison of his own attainments with that idea’ The 
procedure, which Socrates derived from this self-consciousness, 





1 Translated by Dr. Thirlwall in the Philological Museum, II. 549. We have 
quoted this passage and that which follows (from Schleiermacher’s Philosoph. 
Werke, 111. 4. 9), in the Penny Cyclopedia, 5. v. ‘ Socrates.’ 

2 Professor Thompson, note on Butler’s Lectwres on Ancient Philosophy, vol. I. 
Ρ. 379. 


170 FOUNDATION OF THE SOCRATIC SCHOOLS. 


was a system of induction, by which he reduced under some 
one idea, a multitude of separate particulars combined with a 
system of definitions, by which he divided the genus into its 
species; and this is the procedure which is described in the 
Phedrus of Plato." The subject matter of this procedure was 
not physical but moral science, considered with special reference 
to politics. Both the method of Socrates and this application 
of it have been fully recognized by Aristotle. With regard to 
the latter he remarks:? ‘in the time of Socrates, moral and 
political philosophy was extended, and physical speculation 
ceased, and philosophers turned their attention to the virtue 
which was useful to individuals and communities.’ And in 
another passage he states both the method and the object of 
the Socratic dialectics: ‘ as Socrates,’* he says, ‘ busied himself 
about the moral virtues, and endeavoured first of all to give 
general definitions of these,—for Democritus and Pythagoras 
attempted only a few definitions—he consistently investigated 
the guid est (ro ri ἐστιν), the general idea. For he sought to 
draw logical conclusions (συλλογίζεσθαι) ; but the general idea 
is the basis of logical reasoning. At that time the faculty of 
dialectic did not yet exist, so that he should have been able to 
investigate opposites independently of the general idea, and so 
to see whether the science of opposites is identical. There 
are two things which one may justly attribute to Socrates,—in- 
duction and general definitions, both of which belong to the 
first principles of science.’* We cannot then give a briefer, and 
at the same time more correct account of what Socrates did 
for the philosophic literature of Greece, than by saying that he 
founded a system of dialectical reasoning resting on real defini- 





1 Prof. Thompson says, u.s. ; ‘ Induction was the bridge by which Socrates led 
his hearers from the common notion to the right conception implied in a term, pro- 
ceeding by the rejection and exclusion of that which was irrelevant or proper to 
the individual, or the subordinate species, per rejectiones et exclusiones debitas 
(Bacon, Nov. Org. I. 105). The two counter-processes of the dialectician are dis- 
cussed with great elegance in the Phedrus, 265 D., fol. (1.) Induction, or the 
gathering under one form the multitude of scattered partionlars, (2.) Division, or 
the dissection of the general into its subordinate species, κατ᾽ ἄρθρα ἣ πέφυκεν, by 
a natural not an arbitrary classification.’ 

2 De Part. Anim. I. 1, 44: ἐπὶ Σωκράτους τοῦτο μὲν ηὐξηθη, τὸ δὲ ζητεῖν τὰ wept 
φύσεως ἔληξε, πρὸς δὲ τὴν χρήσιμον ἀρετὴν καὶ τὴν πολιτικὴν ἀπέκλιναν οἱ φιλοσοφοῦντες. 

3 Metaphys. M. (XIII.) 4, p. 1078 b. 17. 

4 ἐκεῖνος δὲ εὐλόγως ἐζήτει τὸ τί ἐστιν. συλλογίζεσθαι yap ἐζήτει, ἀρχὴ δὲ τῶν 


IMPERFECT SOCRATIC SCHOOLS. 171 


tions, and that he applied this practical logic to a common-sense 
estimate of the duties of man, both as a moral being and as a 
member of a community; so that while on the one hand he 
gave intensity to the feeling of professional self-consciousness, 
on the other hand he induced men to exact from themselves 
and their associates a higher standard of qualification, and to 
seek the good government of the state as well as the morality 
of the individual, in an increase of mental discipline and useful 
knowledge. His especial position as a speculative teacher is 
best indicated by the statement to which we have already 
referred, that no less than ten schools of philosophers claimed 
him as their head. It is true that the majority of these very 
imperfectly represented his method and its applications. But 
by his influence on Plato, and through him, on Aristotle, he 
has constituted himself the founder of the philosophy which is 
still recognised in the civilized world. 

Reserving for special discussion the works of Xenophon, 
Plato, and Aristotle, which are the most striking literary repre- 
sentatives of Socrates and his teaching, in their effects on his 
own and the succeeding generation, we must here consider those 
imperfect Socratic schools, which either exaggerated the views 
of Socrates in regard to the relations of science and virtue, or 
distorted his teaching by subordinating, on contradictory prin- 
ciples, the speculative truth to the moral obligation. As, on the 
one hand, Socrates had insisted that virtue was dependent on 
the highest kind of speculative knowledge, one of the ablest of 
his disciples, Eucleides of Megara, who had previously adopted 





συλλογισμῶν τὸ τί ἐστιν, διαλεκτικὴ γὰρ ἰσχὺς οὔπω Tor’ ἣν, ὥστε δύνασθαι καὶ χωρὶς 
τοῦ τί ἐστι τἀναντία ἐπισκοπεῖν, καὶ τῶν ἐναντίων εἰ ἡ αὐτὴ ἐπιστήμη. δύο γὰρ ἐστιν ἅ 
τις ἂν ἀποδοίη Σωκράτει δικαίως, τούς 7 ἐπακτικοὺς λόγους καὶ τὸ ὁρίζεσθαι καθόλου. 
ταῦτα γὰρ ἐστιν ἄμφω περὶ ἀρχὴν ἐπιστήμης. In this important passage εὐλόγως 
means consistently, or in strict accordance with the definition. Thusin the Metaph. 
A. I. p. 989, a. 2: καὶ περὶ τῆς τῶν κινουμένων αἰτίας, πότερον ἕν ἢ δύο θετέον, οὔτ᾽ 
ὀρθῶς οὔτε εὐλόγως οἰητέον εἰρῆσθαι παντελῶς. Bonitz explains the adverb: ‘de 
moventium causarum numero, utrum una statuenda esset an due, Empedoclem 
disputasse ait nec recte (οὔτ᾽ ὀρθῶς), siquidem unum debere esse τὸ κινοῦν ἀκίνητον 
Aristoteles persuasum habet, nec sibimet ipsi constantem (οὔτ᾽ εὐλόγως), quoniam 
utriusque principii munera non potest ita, uti distinxit, servare distincta.’ The 
consistency of Socrates depended on his sticking to his definition of terms, as 
Xenophon tells us very plainly; Mem. 1V.6,§ 1: ὧν ἕνεκα σκοπῶν σὺν τοῖς συνοῦσι, 
τί ἕκαστον εἴη τῶν ὄντων οὐδέποτ᾽ ἔληγε. Arrian. Epictet. I. 17, 12: ἤρχετο ἀπὸ 
τῆς τῶν ὀνομάτων ἐπισκέψεως τί σημαίνει ἕκαστον. This is the λόγον διδόναι, which 
Simmias, in the Phedo, p. 763, is made to attribute exclusively to Socrates. 


172 FOUNDATION OF THE SOCRATIC SCHOOLS. 


the teaching of the Eleatic school, exaggerated this proposition, 
and substituted for the practical ethics of Socrates a system of 
logical refinements, involving a series of perplexities not unlike 
those which the schoolmen of the middle ages substituted for 
the simple lessons of Christian theology. As, on the other 
hand, Socrates had maintained that there was a necessary con- 
nexion between virtue and happiness, two of his hearers made 
this equation the basis of two opposite systems of morality ; for 
while Antisthenes asserted that virtue was happiness, Aristippus 
maintained that happiness was virtue; and while the former 
compelled the mind of man to surrender all its inclinations, the 
latter called upon nature to submit to the cravings of human 
appetite. The speculations of the Megaric school, duly sifted 
and criticised, paved the way for the idealism of Plato; and 
the Cynics, who claim Antisthenes for their founder, and the 
Cyrenaics, who took their rise with Aristippus, were represented 
with certain modifications by the Stoics and Epicureans re- 
spectively, the former being also the inheritors of the Megaric 
teaching of Stilpo. 

§ 4. Evciemes, of Megara, or, as Diogenes tells us some- 
what doubtingly, of Gela, in Sicily, was one of the most devoted 
associates of Socrates, and not only encountered some danger ~ 
in order to enjoy the advantage of his teaching,’ but was among 
those who attended him in his last moments.’ When the 
tragedy was accomplished, he opened his house at Megara as an 
asylum for those of his fellow-students* who found Athens no ἡ 
longer a safe or pleasant abode, and, among others, entertained 
Plato, who was destined to be the most distinguished ornament 
of the school. Before the period of his connexion with Socrates, 
Eucleides had made himself acquainted with the doctrines of 
the Eleatics ; and the peculiarities of his system, which regarded 
speculative science the summum bonum or moral end of man, 
must be attributed to the fact, that, under the influence of his — 
previous associations, he endeavoured to combine the Parme- 
nidean with the Socratic theory, and eagerly pursued the dia- 
lectics, while he neglected the practical ethics of his last teacher. 
Diogenes tells us that he wrote six dialogues, of which he gives 





1 Aulus Gellius, VN. A. VI. το. 2 Plat. Phedo p. 59 B. 
8. Diog. Laert. II. 108. 


‘ 


EUCLEIDES. 173 


us the titles ;' but not a fragment of his works has been pre- 
served. His views, however, are criticized in the Sophistes, 
Politicus, Parmenides, and Phiiebus, of Plato, and the doc- 
trines of his school are often referred to by ancient writers. 
Starting as an Eleatic philosopher, from the conception of 
unity, Eucleides maintained that it was ‘the good,’ though he 
designated it by different names,—sometimes calling it ‘ pru- 
dence,’ at another time ‘ God,’ at another time ‘ intellect,’ and 
so forth? This alone had being, and it was unalterable.’ Its 
opposite, therefore, or evil, was non-existent.* This optimism 
was, of course, purely metaphysical, and was not regarded in 
its practical result. Even the dialectics of Eucleides were 
logically unpractical. He rejected all reasoning by analogy, all 
comparisons, all formal demonstrations ; and ‘in arguing syl- 
logistically, for he seems to have invented the syllogism, he 
used to admit the premises and combat the conclusion.’ 
Whatever may have been the value of his teaching as a dis- 
cipline of the intellect, it was incapable of producing any im- 
portant results, and appeared as nothing but an endless logo- 
machy, fruitful only in ingenious quibbles. These idle sophistries 
assumed a worse form under Euvsutipes, the successor of Eu- 
cleides, who flourished about 340 B.c., and who is known as the 
inventor of the seven false or captious syllogisms so celebrated 
in the history of logic, namely, the ψευδόμενος or ‘liar,’ the 
ἐγκεκαλυμμένος or ‘veiled,’ the κερατίνης or ‘horned, the 
nAéxrpa or ‘unknown friend, the φαλακρὸς or ‘bald, the 
swpirne or ‘heap,’ and the διαλανθάνων or ‘hidden.’®> Much 





1 TI. $108. They were called Λαμπρίας, Αἰσχίνης, Φοίνιξ, Kpirwv, ᾿Αλκιβιάδης, 
Ἐρωτικός. 

2 Diog. Laért. IT. 108: ἕν τὸ ἀγαθὸν ἀπεφαίνετο πολλοῖς ὀνόμασι καλούμενον" ὅτε 
μὲν γὰρ φρόνησιν, ὅτε δὲ θεὸν, καὶ ἄλλοτε νοῦν καὶ τὰ λοιπά. 

8 Cic, Acad. Qu. II. 42: ‘id bonum solum esse [Megarici] dicebant, quod esset 
unum et idem semper.’ 

4 Diog. Laért. u.s.: τὰ δὲ ἀντικείμενα τῷ ἀγαθῷ ἀνήρει, μὴ εἶναι φάσκων. 

5 χα, ibid. : ταῖς ἀποδείξεσιν ἐνίστατο οὐ κατὰ λήμματα ἀλλὰ κατ᾽ ἐπιφοράν. Profes- 
sor Thompson remarks (Butler’s Lectwres, I. p. 402): ‘if, as Deycks supposes, 
these terms were invented by Eucleides, to him will belong the honour of having 
discovered the form of the syllogism, λήμματα being equivalent to the προτάσεις, 
ἐπιφορὰ to the συμπέρασμα of Aristotle.’ 

6 These seven sophisms may easily be reduced to four. The ‘veiled,’ the ‘un- 
known friend’ and the ‘hidden’ are all the same, namely, they are dependent on 
the quibble that Admetus or Electra would not know Alcestis or Orestes, if they 


174 FOUNDATION OF THE SOCRATIC SCHOOLS. 


the same was the procedure of the later Megarics, Droporus 
Cronus and Srripro, who flourished about 300 B.c., the former 
of whom denied motion, and the latter maintained that only 
identical propositions were true. Such a school well deserved 
to be called eristic or contentious. The Megarics were, in 
fact, as Schleiermacher has remarked,’ the overseers and critics 
of the formal proceedings of others, and they did this in the 
true Socratic spirit, which they had apprehended in its most 
positive form. Their imperfections consisted in their neglect of 
real knowledge ; but it may be said that wherever the Cynics 
were negative as Socratic philosophers, the Megarics were posi- 
tive, and so the two schools at last united in that of the 
Stoics, for Stilpo, who lived as a genuine Cynic of the higher 
kind, was a pupil of Crates, and the teacher of Zeno. 

§ 5. The Cynics, who were thus the counterpart and supple- 
ment of the Megarics, derived their doctrine and principles from 
ANTISTHENES, who has been well described? as a caricature of 
his teacher Socrates. Originally a scholar of Gorgias, Anti- 
sthenes devoted himself to Socrates, and was, like Eucleides, one 
of those who attended him in his last moments.’ Two decla- 
mations of doubtful authenticity, the Ajax and Ulysses, are still 
preserved as specimens of his-rhetorical skill. But his philo- 
sophical writings, which were voluminous, and distinguished by 
various excellencies of style and matter, are entirely lost, with 
the exception of a few fragments.’ These works, as we learn 





were veiled or otherwise concealed, so that one might be said to know and not to 
know the same person at the same time. This fallacy is as old as Eucleides, for 
Plato refers to it in his Theetetus, p. 165 B.: λέγω δὴ τὸ δεινότατον ἐρώτημα, dpa 
οἷόν τε τὸν αὐτὸν εἰδότα τι τοῦτο ὃ olde μὴ εἰδέναι. The ‘bald’ and the ‘heap’ are 
only the reversed forms of the same sophism ; they argued on the admission that the 
loss of a hair does not constitute baldness, or the addition of a grain make a heap. 
The ‘horned’ argues that you have what you have not lost—horns for instance. 
And the ‘liar’ maintains that if you say you lie when you speak the truth, you both 
lie and speak the truth at the same time (Cic. Acad. II. 29., Aristotle, Soph. El. 
XXV. 3). This fallacy, which depends on a confusion in the meaning of the 
predicate, furnished Chrysippus with the theme for six volumes of commentary, 
and was probably developed by Eubulides in his attack on the μεσότης of Aristotle’s 
ethics, 1 Werke zur Philosophie, II. τ. p. οὔ. 

2 By Schleiermacher, u.s. Ὁ. 91. 

3 Xen. Mem. 111, 11, 17, 11. 5. Sympos. II. το, III. 7, 1V. 34. Plat. Phedo, 
p. 59, B. 1 

4 Westermann, Gesch. d. Gr. Beredtsamkeit 2 33, note 2. 

5 Winckelmann, Antisthenis Fragmenta, Turici 1842. 


ANTISTHENES AND THE CYNICS. 175 


from Diogenes, were collected in ten books, and consisted chiefly 
of dialogues.’ Some of these were polemical criticisms, if they 
did not amount to personal and libellous attacks. Thus, we 
read of two dialogues called Cyrus, in the second of which 
he inveighed against Alcibiades, of his Politicus, in which he 
lampooned all the statesmen of Athens, of his Archelaus, in 
which he criticized Gorgias, of his Aspasia, in which he ca- 
lumniated the sons of Pericles, and of his Satho, in which Plato 
was scurrilously assailed.2 With the latter he was in constant 
antagonism, and we find traces of this in the Platonic dialogues. 
There can be no doubt that Antisthenes is aimed at in well- 
known passages of the Sophistes and Philebus.* Cicero informs 
us that, in his book called ὁ φυσικός, Antisthenes maintained 
the important proposition that, though there were many gods in 
the popular polytheism, there was only one real deity.* Although 
Theopompus ventured to insinuate that Plato was indebted to 
Antisthenes for many of his thoughts,’ it seems that the latter 
was remarkable rather for his wit and acuteness than for the 
elevation of his sentiments ;° and his general character would 
lead us to expect sarcastic humour rather than refined elegance 
in his writings. The same affectation which induced him to 
substitute ascetic extravagances for the natural simplicity and 





1 Diog. Laért. VI. 15. 

2 Athen. V., p. 220, C.D. Satho was a vulgar substitute for Plato’s own 

name: καὶ Πλάτωνα δὲ μετονομάσας Σάθωνα ἀσυρῶς καὶ φορτικῶς τὸν ταύτην ἔχοντα 
τὴν ἐπιγραφὴν ἐξέδωκε κατ᾽ αὐτοῦ. 
- 8 Soph. 251 B., 258 E., 259 D. Phileb. 45. c. Aristot. Ethica Nicom. X. 1. 
Professor Thompson (in a paper read before the Cambridge Philosophical Society in 
Noy. 1857) has rendered it probable that of the two parties in the gigantomachy 
(Soph. p. 246 A.) the gods, represent the Megarics, who, as idealists, are called 
ἡμερώτεροι, ‘more civilized’ or ‘more humane’ than their materialistic opponents, 
whereas the giants denote the school of Antisthenes, who, says Plato, think 
nothing real but that which they can take hold of with both their hands (Soph. 
247 ©.), and whom he elsewhere (Thectet. 155 E.) terms ‘hard,’ ‘stubborn,’ ‘quite 
illiterate’ (σκληροί, ἀντίτυποι, μάλ᾽ ed ἄμουσοι), the second of these epithets referring 
(as Mr. Thompson holds with Winckelmann) to the name as well as the character 
of Antisthenes, and the last being quite justified by the language of Aristotle, 
Metaphys. vu. 3. 7: οἱΑντισθένειοι καὶ of οὕτως ἀπαίδευτοι. 

4 Cic. De Nat. Deor. I. 13,32: ‘ Antisthenes, in eo libro qui physicus inscribitur, 
populares deos multos, naturalem unum esse dicens, tollit vim et naturam deorum.’ 
Cf. Clem. Al. Strom. V. p. 601. 

> Athen. XI., p. 508 p. The same claim is made on behalf of Aristippus and 
Bryson. 

® Cic. ad Att, XII. 38: ‘homo acutus magis quam eruditus.’ 


176 FOUNDATION OF THE SOCRATIC SCHOOLS. 


contempt for luxury, which were so conspicuous in Socrates, 
must have appeared in his literary compositions, and we may be 
sure that they were not deficient in the caustic bitterness which 
is attributed to his conversation.’ His personal habits were 
eminently offensive. So far was he from attracting a crowd of 
admirers, that he drove away all his pupils except Diogenes, who 
was a man of similar stamp. He always appeared in the most 
beggarly clothing, with the staff and wallet of mendicancy ; and 
this ostentation of self-denial once drew from Socrates the ex- 
clamation that he saw the vanity of Antisthenes through the 
holes in his garments.? It has been supposed that the appel- 
lation of ‘the dog, or the ‘ cynic,’ which is especially bestowed 
on Diogenes,’ and which furnishes a designation for the school 
founded by Antisthenes, was derived from the snarling temper 
and shameless effrontery of these philosophers. In all proba- 
bility, this name, which was found to be so appropriate, was 
suggested in the first instance by that of the Gymnasium of 
Cynosarges at Athens, where Antisthenes taught, close by the 
temple of his favourite deity Hercules. The philosophy of the 
Cynics, if it deserves to be called so, was a resolute maintenance 
of the principle that nothing was good but virtue. And by 
virtue they understood only firmness, and the abnegation of all 
natural desires. They even went so far as to identify pain with 
virtue, and to make physical discomfort a condition of moral 
felicity. Even infamy and despair might be regarded as 





1 The following are some of his sarcastic witticisms as recorded by Diogenes: πρὸς τὸ 
Ποντικὸν μειράκιον, μέλλον φοιτᾶν αὐτῷ καὶ πυθόμενον τίνων αὐτῷ det, φησὶ βιβλιαρίου 
καιν οὔ (καὶ vod), καὶ γραφείου καιν οὔ (καὶ vod), καὶ πινακιδίου κα ιν ο Ὁ (καὶ νοῦ), 
τὸν νοῦν παρεμφαίνων.---πρὸς τὸν ἐρωτώμενον ποδαπὴν γήμῃ, ἔφη, ἂν μὲν καλὴν 
ἕξεις κοιν ἦν, ἂν δὲ αἰσχρὰν ἕξεις ποιν ἡ .---κρεῖττον ἔλεγεν ἐν ταῖς χρείαις εἰς 
κόρακας ἢ εἰς κόλακας ἐμπεσεῖν" οἱ μεν yap νεκρόυς, οἱ δὲ ζῶντας ἐσθίουσιν. 
Aristophanes, by the way, has punned upon these last words, Vesp. 43—45. 

2 Diog. Laert. VI. 8, p. 370, Casaubon: στρέψαντος αὐτοῦ τὸ διερρωγὸς τοῦ τρίβωνος 
els τὸ προφανές, Σωκράτης ἰδών φησιν, “ὁρῶ σου διὰ τοῦ τρίβωνος τὴν φιλοδοξίαν.᾽ 

3 6, σ. Aristot. Rhet. III. 10, § 7. 

4 The Κυνόσαργες was a temple and gymnasium of Hercules, east of the city, and 
before the gate Diomea, It was designed for the use of illegitimate or base-born 
Athenians and foreigners (Dem, ¢. Aristocr. 692. 18). Hercules was the favourite 
godof Antisthenes, not only because he was himself, like that divinity, half-god, of good 
extraction by the father’s side only, his mother having been a Thracian or a Phry- 
gian, but also because Hercules was the representative of a laborious life. The 
Cynosarges was so called from the oracle about ἡ κύων ἡ λευκή (Pausan. I. 19, 2 3). 


ANTISTHENES. 1 


blessings,’ and madness was better than vicious pleasure? The 
virtue, which they regarded as the summum bonum, was, according 
to the Socratic principle, capable of being taught.’ But it was 
only Antisthenes, the founder of the school, and Zeno, who 
received instruction from Crates the disciple of Diogenes, that 
paid any attention to science as such. Even in the hands of Anti- 
sthenes science was really a denial of scientific principles. 
According to Aristotle,s he said ‘that it was impossible to 
define the substance of a thing (for that the definition was but 
a long description), but that you may teach what kind of a thing 
it is; for example, you cannot say what silver is, but you may 
say that it is like tin.’ According to the same authority,’ he 
insisted upon an identity of expression in speaking of the same 
subjects, so that he denied the possibility of contradiction, and 
almost of falsehood. It was therefore in a very different sense 
from Socrates that Antisthenes maintained that all instruction 
depended on an examination of words.’ For while Socrates 
insisted upon scientific definition, Antisthenes intended to insist 
only upon a fixed use of conventional terms. On the whole it 
may be said with truth, that the philosophy of the Cynics was 
a travesty and misrepresentation of that of Socrates, just as its 
founder was a caricature of his great teacher. And if Socrates 
may be called a Girondist, it is equally clear that Antisthenes 
and Diogenes were Sansculottes. The latter indeed was, either 
on his own account or that of his family,’ an outcast from his 
native city of Sinope; his asceticism was, in all probability, 
a refuge for his forfeited respectability and civic useful- 





1 Diog. VI. 11, p. 371: τὴν δὲ ἀδοξίαν ἀγαθὸν καὶ ἴσον τῷ πόνῳ. 

2 id. VI. 3: μανείην μᾶλλον ἢ ἡσθείην, 8: πρὸς τὸν ἐπαινοῦντα τρυφήν, ἐχθρῶν 
παῖδες, ἔφη, τρυφήσειαν. 

8 id. 10, p. 371: διδακτὴν ἀπεδείκνυε τὴν ἀρετήν. 

4 Metaphys. VIII. 3. p. 1043, b. 24: ὥστε ἡ ἀπορία ἣν οἱ ᾿Αντισθένειοι καὶ οἱ 
. οὕτως ἀπαίδευτοι ἠπόρουν ἔχει τινὰ καιρόν, ὅτι οὐκ ἔστιτὸ τί ἔστιν ὁρίσασθαι (τὸν 
yap ὅρον λόγον εἶναι μακρόν), ἀλλὰ ποῖόν τι ἐστιν ἐνδέχεται καὶ διδάξαι, ὥσπερ 
ἄργυρον τί μέν ἐστιν, οὔ, ὅτι δὲ οἷον καττίτερος. 

5 Metaphys. V. 29, p. 1024, b. 31: ὁ δὲ ψευδὴς λόγος οὐθενός ἐστιν ἁπλῶς λόγος" διὸ 
᾿Αντισθένης Beto εὐήθως μηθὲν ἀξιῶν λέγεσθαι πλὴν τὸ οἰκείῳ λόγῳ ἕν ἐφ᾽ ἑνός" ἐξ ὧν 
συνέβαινε μὴ εἶναι ἀντιλέγειν, σχεδὸν δὲ μηδὲ ψεύδεσθαι. 

6 Arrian, Dissert. Epictetit, I. 17.12: ᾿Αντισθένης δ᾽ οὐ λέγει; καὶ τίς ἐστιν ὁ 
γεγραφὼς ὅτι ἀρχὴ παιδεύσεως ἡ τῶν ὀνομάτων ἐπίσκεψις ; 

7? Diog. Laért. VI. 20, p. 377. 

Vox, II. N 


178 FOUNDATION OF THE SOCRATIC SCHOOLS. 


ness; and the socialism, which he openly preached, seemed to be 
inspired by the recklessness of a man who had no character to lose. 

§ 6. The opposite school of the Cyrenaics had at least the 
merit of eschewing all hypocrisy, and although the undisguised 
pursuit of selfish gratification is utterly repugnant to our higher 
moral sense, it is at least more natural and more honest than 
the affected austerity, which the Cynics used as a cloak for their 
malignity, or as an excuse for their shamelessness.' The 
peculiar character of Aristippus, the founder of this school, 
seems to have impressed itself on his followers. He was, in 
modern language, a selfish man of the world, who was willing to 
barter his real independence, and to let out his social and in- 
tellectual qualities, in order to obtain the largest possible amount 
of present enjoyment, and to escape as far as possible the ordinary 
troubles and annoyances of life. He believed, with all this, that 
he had made himself superior to the outer world, and was in- 
dependent of external circumstances.? ‘I possess, but am not 
possessed by things,’* was the maxim by which he expressed his 
indifferentism in regard to all things which he could not bring 
under his control. But his career shows that he was merely 
enabled by his want of a high moral character and fixed prin- 
ciples to accommodate himself to any circumstances, and so make 
the best of life.* 

Aristippus was the son of Aritades, an opulent merchant of 
Cyrene. He came to see the Olympic games, which, from 
Pindar’s time had been a favourite resort of his countrymen, and 
was led by the encomiums of Ischomachus, whom he met there, 
to extend his journey to Athens for the purpose of making the 





1 Cic. de Offictis, I. 41 : ‘Cynicorum natio tota ejicienda est; est enim inimica 
verecundiz, sine qué nihil rectum esse potest, nihil honestum.’ 
39 His avowed principles are well expressed in the lines of Horace, I. Zpist. I. 
17: 
Nunc in Aristippi furtim precepta relabor, 
Et mihi res non me rebus subjungere conor. 
3 ἔχω ἀλλ᾽ οὐκ ἔχομαι. Diog. Laért, II. 8, 75. This was said especially with 
reference to Lais. 
4 So Horace says of him (1. Zpist. XVII. 23) : 
Omnis Aristippum decuit color et status et res, 
Tentantem majora, fere presentibus equum. 
Diog. Laért. II. 8, 866 : ἣν δὲ ἱκανὸς ἁρμόσασθαι καὶ τόπῳ Kal χρόνῳ καὶ προσώπῳ 
καὶ πᾶσαν περίστασιν ἁρμονίως ὑποκρίνασθαι. 


ARISTIPPUS. 179 


acquaintance of Socrates. He attached himself to this phi- 
losopher, and was one of his regular associates till the time of 
his death; but his fellow-pupil, Plato, who had never much 
toleration for him, seems to intimate that, being close at hand, 
he allowed some inadequate excuse to prevent him from attending 
his master at the time when he drank the hemlock in prison.’ 
Although his native city has given its name to the school which 
he founded, Aristippus lived very little at Cyrene. Indeed he 
did not hesitate to avow to Socrates himself that he lived away 
from home in order to avoid the duties of a Greek citizen. His 
time was spent either at Athens, where he was a student, or at 
Corinth, where he lived with the notorious courtezan, Lais,’ or 
at Syracuse, where he was the obsequious parasite of the tyrant 
Dionysius.* It is said that he was once taken prisoner by 
Artaphernes the satrap.’ In his later years he returned to 
Cyrene, and spent the remainder of his long life there, being 
principally engaged in communicating his system of philosophy 
to his daughter Arete, by whom it was taught to her son, Aris- 
tippus,° and he is supposed by some to have completed and 
systematized the doctrines of his uncle. The highest praise 
that can be bestowed upon the character of Aristippus is that 
he seems to have enjoyed, either from natural temperament, or 
from diligent self-control, a very remarkable calmness and. tran- 
quillity, which would have done credit to any philosopher.’ And 
though he justified his self-indulgence, he declared that he should 
be able at any moment to relinquish his pleasures without a 
sigh. If the long list of his writings, which is given by 





1 Plutarch, de Cwrios.2, vol. III., p. 79, Wyttenbach: Plutarch says here, with 
regard to the philosophy of Socrates, ἧς ἣν τέλος ἐπιγνῶναι τὰ ἑαυτοῦ κακὰ καὶ 
ἀπαλλαγῆναι. 

3 Phedo, p.59 D: τί dal; ᾿Αρίστιππος καὶ Κλεόμβροτος παρεγένοντο; οὐ δῆτα" 
ἐν Αἰγίνῃ γὰρ ἐλέγοντο εἶναι. ; 

_ 8. Athenzeus, XII. p. 544. XIII. p. 588. Two of his works were entitled 
πρὸς Λαΐδα and πρὸς Λαΐδα rept τοῦ κατόπτρου (Diog. Laert, IT. 84). 

* Diog. Laért. vita Aristippi, passim. ὅ Brucker, Hist. Phil. II. 2,3. p.589 note u. 

6 Suidas, s.v. διήκουσε δὲ αὐτοῦ ἡ θυγάτηρ᾽ Ἀρήτη, ἀφ᾽ ἧς ὁ παῖς αὐτῆς ὁ νέος ᾿Αρί- 
στιππος ὃς ἐκλήθη Μητροδίδακτος. Cf. Diog. L. II. 86, from whom this is taken, 
and Ailian, Hist. Anim. IIT. 40. 

7 This is shown by the numerous anecdotes in Diogenes. 

_§ This is implied in the saying quoted by Diog. Laért. II. 69, p. 134: εἰσιών ποτε 
eis ἑταίρας οἰκίαν... οὐ τὸ εἰσελθεῖν, ἔφη, χαλεπόν, ἀλλὰ τὸ μὴ δύνασθαι ἐξελθεῖν. 
We Qa 


180 FOUNDATION OF THE SOCRATIC SCHOOLS. 


Diogenes Laértius, is at all correct, he must have been an in- 
dustrious man of letters. Sosicrates of Rhodes said that he 
wrote nothing, but the catalogue of his works is given on the 
authority of Sotion and Panetius.' Besides philosophical 
treatises on ‘virtue, ‘education,’ ‘fortune, &c., a history of 
Libya, in three books, is attributed to him. It is difficult to 
discriminate between the doctrines which were developed by 
Aristippus himself, and those which were elaborated by the 
other teachers of the Cyrenaic school. Aristotle, who mentions 
Aristippus as a Sophist,? attributes to Eudoxus, and not to him, 
the exaltation of pleasure to the rank of the swmmum bonum, 
which he combats in the tenth book of his Zthics.2 In general, 
it may be said, that Aristippus confined himself to a sort of 
moral philosophy which maintained that happiness (εὐδαιμονία) 
and pleasure (ἡδονή) were convertible terms; and which, by 
seeking the end of life in the materials of the world of sense, 
naturally led to atheism, as was shown by the surname Atheus, 
which is given to THroporus, one of this school. The five 
points of the system of Aristippus, which some have attributed to 
his nephew,’ are as follows :* (1.) ‘ Concerning things to be chosen 
and avoided’ (περὶ αἱρετῶν Kai φευκτῶν) : under this head he 
maintained that the end of life was transitory pleasure ; for that 
the present alone belongs to man, the past being no longer 
available, and the future precarious. (2.) ‘Concerning the 
affections’ (περὶ παθῶν) : under this head he gave his definition 
of pleasure. There were, he said, three conditions: pleasure, 
which he compared to calm and even motion, as when a vessel 
is borne to its haven by a gentle and favouring breeze; in- 
difference, which he compared to a dead and windless calm ; 





1 Diog. Laért. IT. 85, p. 144 B. 

2 Metaph. B. (III.) p. 996 a, 32: τῶν σοφιστῶν τινὲς οἷον ᾿Αρίστιππος προεπη- 
λάκιζεν αὐτάς. In one point at least Aristippus approximated to the Sophists, that 
he took fees for his teaching. Suidas, s.v. 

3 Eth. Nic. X. 2, τ. 

«4 Professor Thompson (Butler's Lectures, I. p. 452) says: ‘Aristippus the elder, 
' though the fact of his authorship is disputed (Diog. L. II. 8, 84), was undoubtedly 
the inventor of the Cyrenaic system. He must even have developed it in a logical 
and systematic form.’ This is argued from the references to his views in the 
Theetetus and Philebus, where they are made the subject of formal refutation. 

> Sextus Empiricus, Lib, VII. § 11. Adversus Logicos, p. 372, ed. Fabricius," 


ARISTIPPUS. 181 


pain, which he compared to a storm, in which the vessel is 
driven from its port, and exposed to danger. In this definition 
he stands directly opposed to the Epicureans, who insisted that 
pleasure was the state of absolute rest. (3.) ‘Concerning 
actions’ (περὶ πράξεων) : here he maintained that actions were 
neither good nor bad in themselves; that virtue consisted in 
that which conduced to pleasure of any kind; and he perverted 
the Socratic connexion between ‘knowing’ and ‘doing’ by making 
his virtue a sort of common sense, or presence of mind (φρόνησις), 
which, as he said of himself, enabled the philosopher to live 
happily anywhere. (4.) ‘ Concerning causes’ (περὶ αἰτίων) : in 
speaking of causes the Cyrenaics did not mean physical causes, 
but merely the outward occasions of our bodily sensations. In 
regard to these man is merely passive; and as it is the business 
of the wise man, in the Cyrenaic sense, to get the greatest 
amount of pleasure out of the world around him, he must as far 
as possible transform disagreeable sensations into sources of en- 
joyment, either by evading or by modifying them. In this part 
of his theory Aristippus is quite as much the object of Plato’s 
criticisms in the Theetetus, as Protagoras, who is mentioned 
there by name, and of course no one will doubt that the theory 
of pleasure, which it is one of the objects of the Philebus to 
controvert, must have been systematically put forward by the 
founder of the Cyrenaic philosophy. (5.) ‘Concerning proofs’ 
(περὶ πίστεων) : of the Cyrenaic views on this subject we have a 
definite and intelligible account in the pages of Sextus Em- 
piricus.’ From this statement it is quite clear that the school 
of Aristippus admitted no criterion except the senses: and 
these gave a different result for every man. In some respects 
they have found a modern representative of their views in Horne 





1 Lib. VII. adv. Logicos, §§ 191—200. We agree with Fabricius (ad Sezt. p. 
371,) that this passage refers to the πίστεις of the Cyrenaics. Some have thought 
that he is speaking περὶ αἰτίων, but he says at the beginning ὃ 191, that the Cyre- 
naics make the πάθη the κριτήρια, and that these alone are conceivable and not 
fallacious: τῶν δὲ πεποιηκότων τὰ πάθη (i.e. the atria) μηδὲν εἶναι καταληπτὸν μηδὲ 
ἄψευστον, and at the end of his explanation he remarks, ὃ 200: πάντων οὖν τῶν 
ὄντων τὰ πάθη κριτήριά ἐστι καὶ τέλη" ζῶμεν δέ, φασιν, ἑπόμενοι τούτοις ἐναργείᾳ 
μὲν κατὰ τὰ ἄλλα πάθη εὐδοκήσει δὲ κατὰ τὴν ἡδονήν. So that he is clearly speaking 
of the evidence of the senses, and not of that which produces sensation. 


182 FOUNDATION OF THE SOCRATIC SCHOOLS. 


Tooke,’ in others Bishop Berkeley is in agreement with them. 
When the ultra-nominalistic philologer declared that truth is 
only what each man troweth, he said much the same as the 
Cyrenaics, who maintained’ that ‘there was no common cri- 
terion for men, but that common names were used to designate 
their independent judgments.’ And when Berkeley denied the 
demonstrable existence of an external world, he did not differ 
from the Cyrenaics, who declared’ that ‘it is only the affection 
or sensation which appears to us, and that what is without us 
and is the cause of the sensation, may perhaps exist, but does 
not appear to us.’ 

The doctrines of Aristippus and his nephew were farther de- 
veloped by Hecrsias, THroporvus, and AwnnicERis,‘ and ulti- 
mately merged in the system of Epicurus. 

As a matter of literary curiosity, and for the light which they 
would have thrown on the criticisms of Plato and Aristotle, we 
must regret that we have no remains of the doctrinal writings 
of Eucleides, Antisthenes, and Aristippus. In themselves, how- 
ever, these philosophers can be regarded only as the authors of 
systems which pushed to extravagance the broad and distinctive 
features of the teaching of Socrates, and they perhaps produced 
the only permanent effect of which they were capable, when they 
exacted a formal refutation of their views from the searching 
dialectics of their great contemporary Plato. 





1 See New Cratylus, 8 61. 

3 Sext. Emp. VIT. § 195: ἔνθεν οὐδὲ κριτήριόν φασιν εἶναι κοινὸν ἀνθρώπων" 
ὀνόματα δὲ κοινὰ τίθεσθαι τοῖς κρίμασι. 

8 id. § 194: μόνον τὸ πάθος ἡμῖν ἐστὶ φαινόμενον" τὸ δ᾽ ἐκτὸς καὶ τοῦ πάθους ποιη- 
τικὸν τάχα μέν ἐστιν ὄν, οὐ φαινόμενον δὲ ἡμῖν. 

4 It is worth while to notice that Anniceris, who differed from Aristippus by 
maintaining the unselfish virtues of patriotism, friendship, &c., exhibited the prac- 
tical result of this improved philosophy by ransoming Plato from slavery. 


183 


CHAPTER XXXVIII,. 
XENOPHON AND CTESIAS. 


§ 1. Life and adventures of Xenophon. ὃ 2. The practical design of his writings. 
§ 3. His Grecian History; its merits and defects. § 4. The Anabasis. § 5. 
The Memorials and Apology of Socrates. § 6. The Cyropedia and Agesilaus. 
§ 7. Xenophon’s minor tracts. ὃ 8. The leading characteristics of his style. 
§ 9. Ctesias, a contemporary of Xenophon ; his works. 


§ 1. ENOPHON, the son of Gryllus, was born at Athens, 

probably about Ol. 84, 2. B.c. 443.’ Of his early years 
we know nothing beyond the fact that he fought in the battle of 
Delium (8.c. 424,) among the Athenian cavalry, and that his 
life was saved by Socrates, who, after he had fallen wounded 
from his horse, carried him for some distance from the field of 
battle: He had accidentally met with this philosopher, who 
was struck with his handsome and intelligent countenance, and 
almost constrained him to join his society. ‘Another of his 
intimates was Proxenus, a Beotian, and a disciple of Gorgias, 
who afterwards exercised an important influence on his destiny.’ 





1 The date of Xenophon’s birth is still, as it has always been, a doubtful point. 
Τὸ is very difficult to resist the general impression conveyed by the Anabasis, where 
he seems to be always spoken of as a comparatively young man, in B.c. 401. But 
the chief passage in that work (III. 1 § 25: οὐδὲν προφασίζομαι τὴν ἡλικίαν, ἀλλὰ 
καὶ ἀκμάζειν ἡγοῦμαι ἐρύκειν ἀπ᾽ ἐμαυτοῦ τὰ κακά) is rather for than against the 
supposition that he was then above 40 (see Thucyd. V. 26, and comp. ch. XXXIV. 
§ 1, p. 89 note), and the combination pointed out by Schneider, of the passages 
in Xen. Sympos. IV. ὃ 25, and Mem. I. 3, § το, proves that Xenophon must have 
been a young man in Ol. 89, 4. B.c. 421; consequently, he was born about B.c. 
442 or 443, and might therefore have been present at the battle of Delium, as 
Strabo expressly tells us that he was (p. 403). The statement of Pseudo- Lucian 
(Maerob. c. 21), that he was more than go years old when he died, combined with 
the statement of Stesicleides (Diog. Laért. II. 56), that he died in Ol. 105, 1. B.C. 
359, would imply that he was born even earlier than Ol. 84, 2; but there is reason 
to believe that Stesicleides is in error, and that Xenophon’s death did not take place 
till some years later than B.C. 359. 

2 An anecdote mentioned by Philostratus (vit. Prodici, p. 496) implies that 
Xenophon spent some time as a prisoner of war in Beeotia, and it has been sug- 
gested that this must have been after the taking of Oropus by the Beeotians in Ol, 
92, I. B.0. 412. Did this event lead to his intimacy with Proxenus ? 


184 XENOPHON AND CTESIAS. 


What was the tenor of his employments during the first forty 
years of his life, we do not know, but we can easily guess. It 
is quite clear that his chief wish was to become a well educated 
man, (καλὸς κἀγαθός) according to Socratic principles,’ and that 
he felt very little inclination to act a part in the important 
political events which were then taking place. That he was no 
friend to the Demus appears both from his subsequent career 
and also from the fact that he was unmolested by the Thirty. 
It is not improbable that it was immediately after the restora- 
tion of democracy by Thrasybulus, that he set down on paper 
the events of the last six years of the Peloponnesian War, and 
of the few years that succeeded; and the memoirs which he 
then composed form the first two books of his Hellenica, or 
Grecian history; a work which he afterwards continued in a 
very different spirit; for, though we do not detect in the first 
part any great partiality to the patriots of Phyle, and may, 
perhaps, remark a strong feeling in favour of Theramenes, it is 
at least free from that bitter animosity to the institutions of 
his country which he afterwards displayed. In the year 401, 
B.c., he received a letter from his friend Proxenus, who had 
entered into the service of Cyrus, urging him to come to Sardis, 
and pay his court to the Persian prince, whose favour, he, Proxe- 
nus, valued far more highly than any advantages which his native 
land could offer him. ‘The prospect thus held out to him of 
acquiring riches and honour in a foreign land was too tempting 
to a daring and restless character, to whom Athens, under its 
revived democracy, was already, perhaps, sufficiently distasteful ; 
and though he made a show of consulting his friend Socrates 
on the subject, it is. clear that Xenophon had already deter- 
mined to accept the proposal of Proxenus: for, when Socrates 
pointed out to him the probable effect which would be produced 
upon the minds of the Athenians in general by his attachment 
to the cause of one of their greatest enemies, and recommended 
him to consult the Delphian oracle, Xenophon merely asked of 
the god what preliminary sacrifices he ought to make in order 
to secure success in his undertaking, having made up his mind 
to brave all risks rather than lose such a promising chance.’ 





1 Diog. Laért. ΤΙ, 48. 2 Anabasis III. 1, § 6. 


XENOPHON AS A LITERARY MAN. 185 


Accordingly, he joined the Greek mercenaries of Cyrus, as a 

volunteer, and after the battle of Cynaxa became virtually their 
leader. The part which he played on the retreat belongs to 
Greek history, or rather to the history of the world, for it is 
not too much to say that he first demonstrated the problem 
which was practically solved some sixty years later by Alexander 
the Great. But the consequences of the step which he had 
taken were justly foreseen by Socrates. Instead of returning 
to Athens to resume his rights of citizenship, and to enjoy the 
riches and reputation which he had obtained by his courage and 
abilities, he was condemned to exile from his native city, and 
came back to Greece as a soldier in the army of Agesilaus. After 
fighting against his countrymen in the battle of Coronea, he 
took up his abode at Scillus in Elis, where the Lacedzemonians, 
to reward his services, had given him, together with the provenia, 
a grant of land and a house; and he subsequently purchased 
some ground in the neighbouring vale out of the proceeds of 
the votive tithe of his Asiatic booty. Here he built a small 
temple, dedicated to Diana of Ephesus, in whose honour he 
celebrated an annual festival, much frequented by the people of 
the neighbourhood. The temple was surrounded by meadow- 
lands, and forests rich in game, which enabled Xenophon to 
indulge in his favourite pastime of hunting. This exercise, the 
society of his friends, and the labours of authorship occupied 
all his time, and he died at a very advanced age, either at 
Corinth or in Athens, to which city he is said to have returned 
in consequence of a revocation of the edict of banishment passed 
against him many years before.’ 

§ 2. We must regard Xenophon, chiefly if not entirely, as a 
literary man. Great as were his exploits in Asia, we should 
scarcely have heard his name had it not been for his own 
writings. And yet it must be admitted ‘that his talents were 
not literary, or in general speculative, but, on the contrary, ex- 
clusively practical. The intellectual bearing, and the philoso- 





1 If Xenophon was born in B.0. 443, and died at the age of go, as the Pseudo- 
Lucian (i.e. Phlegon of Tarsus) tells us, the year of his death will be Ol. 106, 4. 
B.C. 353, and as he mentions the death of Alexander of Phere, B.c. 357, (Hellen. 
VI. 4, ὃ 35), and the beginning of the Sacred war Β.0, 356, 355, (de Veetig. V. 
§ 9), his death could not have taken place much before this, 


--- .... 


186 XENOPHON AND CTESIAS. 


phical consequences of the doctrines of Socrates, he seems to 
have been utterly incapable of appreciating, or even thoroughly 
comprehending : but no one was better able to understand the 
practical application of the rule that every man should discover 
and follow after that which was most for his happiness. Only 
it is to be feared, that if he did not, with some of the Cyrenaics, 
sacrifice morality to his love of pleasure, he at all events did 
not allow any patriotic feelings to interfere with his pursuit of 
the profitable. Ifthe awakening of the idea of science gene- 
rated the perfection of subjective reflection in the case of Plato, 
the γνῶθι σεαυτὸν of Socrates did not fail to produce in his 
other great disciple a notable concentration of practical selfish- 
ness. We observe traces of this in every one of his writings ; 
in fact it is their prevailing characteristic. Without such a love 
of self and the vanity which accompanies it, the works of Xeno- 
phon would most likely never have seen the light. They seem 
to have been, with one or two exceptions, designed to justify 
the author’s conduct: to explain to the world the causes which 
led to the failure of his selfish plans. A man like Xenophon, 
possessed of great abilities, but yet without moral strength, is 
fretfully careful about the opinion of the world: and we can 
readily imagine, that, little as he esteemed Athens, he would feel 
himself in a false position after his banishment, and would em- 
ploy his long years of leisure in giving the world some account, 
as favourable a one as he could contrive, of the circumstances 
which had led to his exile from the land of his birth. The 
great bulk of his works are memoirs and tracts more or less 
referring to this. Not to speak of his minor treatises, it is 
probable that he composed them in the following series. The 
first two books of the Hellenica, called by later writers the 
Paralipomena of Thucydides, appear to us to have been composed 
between B.c. 403 and 401. His history of the Anabasis, or 
expedition of Cyrus the younger, and the consequent retreat of 
the Ten Thousand Greek mercenaries, was probably the fruit of 
the first years of leisure which he spent at Scillus. The Memo- 
rabilia of Socrates were not written till some time after the 
death of that philosopher, but were certainly prior to the 
Cyropedia, a political romance relating to the founder of the 
Persian empire, not finished till after Ol. 104, 3. B.c. 362, and to 


WORKS OF XENOPHON. 187 


the last five books of the Hellenica, which were written after the 
beginning of Ol. 106, B.c. 356, and were therefore one of the 
last, if not the very last of his works. In speaking of the 
separate works, we shall treat of them in this order, with the 
exception of the Hellenica, which it will be more convenient to 
consider in its present state, that is, as one work. 

§ 3. Niebuhr was the first to point out the marks of time 
which prove the separate composition of the first two and of 
the five subsequent books of Xenophon’s Greek History." At 
the end of the second book, the author, speaking of the termi- 
nation of the expedition against Eleusis, says: ‘and having sworn 
to an amnesty, they still live together as fellow citizens, and the 
Demus abides by its oaths”? Now it appears from the termi- 
nation of the fourth chapter of the sixth book, that this part of 
the work was composed during the reign of Tisiphonus, the 
tyrant of Phere,’ which was forty-four years after the termina- 
tion of the anarchy. Consequently, it is scarcely conceivable 
that Xenophon could have written or published for the first 
time the first two books at the same time with the latter books 
thus referred to Ol. 106; otherwise he must have expressed 
himself very differently with regard to the observation of the 
amnesty, by the democratical party which had banished himself, 
punished Eratosthenes, condemned Socrates, and had not, for a 
long time after that period, forgotten all its old animosities ; 
though perhaps, in the end, it recalled Xenophon himself from 
exile. But, besides these marks of time we cannot mistake the 
strong internal evidence by which they are supported. The 
style and tone of the first part is totally at variance with that 
of the second, and we may see from the former, clear indica- 
tions of the fact that he must have composed his continuation 
of Thucydides at Atheus, and under the eyes of his fellow 
citizens. It is indeed stated, that he was the editor as well as 
the continuer of Thucydides,‘ and this is a sufficient proof that he 
must have written the continuation in his native city. Now he 
left Athens to join Proxenus in B.c. 401, and did not return 

1 See the Philolog. Museum, Vol. I. p. 485. 
2 IL. 3, § 43: ἔτι καὶ νῦν ὁμοῦ τε πολιτεύονται Kal τοῖς ὅρκοις ἐμμένει ὁ δῆμος. 
3 ἄχρι οὗ ὅδε ὁ λόγος ἐγράφετο, Τισίφονος---τὴν ἀρχὴν εἶχε. 


* Diog. Laért. ΤΙ, 57: λέγεται δ᾽ ὅτι καὶ τὰ τοῦ Θουκυδίδου βιβλία λανθάνοντα 
ὑφελέσθαι δυνάμενος αὐτὸς εἰς δόξαν ἤγαγεν. 





188 XENOPHON AND CTESIAS. 


thither till towards the end of his life. Since, then, it is pro- 
bable that Thucydides died soon after his own recal from exile, 
in Β. Ο. 403, and since his history would certainly be published 
soon after his death, it follows that Xenophon must have edited 
the history together with the continuation down to B.c. 403, 
some time between that year and B.c. 401. The first two books 
of the Hellenica, which formed this continuation, are certainly 
very far superior to the last five, but they are not to be men- 
tioned in the same breath with the work of Thucydides. There 
is not in any one of the writings of Xenophon a real developement 
of one great and pervading idea. In all of them there is singular 
clearness, and a certain picturesqueness of description which 
occasionally reminds one of Herodotus; but he has none of the 
dignity of history, and his most tragic scenes are painted less with 
the genius of a poet than with the minute precision of a collec- 
tor of anecdotes. The speeches which he has introduced are 
seldom long or laboured, and are clearly not inserted systema- 
tically like those of Thucydides: but some of them are very 
animated, especially those of Thrasybulus, in the second,’ and 
of Procles in the sixth book.? But he is more excellent in his 
dramatic sketches of isolated occurrences: his description of the 
interview between Agesilaus and Pharnabazes,’ and his account 
of Cinadon’s conspiracy ἡ are peculiarly effective in this respect. 
His mind seems to have dwelt upon minor particulars, and he 
hunted up trifling incidents with all the avidity of a modern 
book-maker. He is careful to give us the metrical despatch of 
Hippocrates,’ and, though with a half apology, the dying witti- 
cism of Theramenes ;° he makes Leotychides and Agesilaus dis- 
pute in Spartan Doric,’ and would, no doubt, have made his 
Satraps talk Persian, if either his readers or himself had been 
familiar with that language. These features of his history, 
combined with the facility and simplicity of his style, will 
always make him an entertaining author, and gain for him the 





1 TI. 4, ὃ 40, seqq. 2 VI. 5, ὃ 38, seqq. 

8 TV. τ, ὃ 29, seqq. 4 IIL. 3, ὃ 5, seqq. 

5 I. 1, §23. The first words are incorrectly written and explained by most, if 
not all, of the commentators. “Eppec τὰ κᾶλα (not τὰ καλά), means ‘the ships are 
lost ;? comp. Aristoph, Lysist. 1253. Ion, apud Athen. p. 412 B. 

6 II. 3, § 56. Above, p. 164. 7 III. 3, §:2. 


WORKS OF XENOPHON. 189 


admiration of those who do not look below the surface of 
things ; but criticism cannot allow him a place among great 
historians, and the scholar will hardly concede to Lucian that 
he was an impartial writer :' his devotion to Agesilaus, his love 
for Sparta, and the animosity with which he regarded the de- 
mocratic party at Athens, did not allow him to take a fair view 
of a contest, in which his hero played the principal part, and in 
which the city that cast him forth from her bosom was opposed 
to the state which had given him shelter and hospitality. 

The period included in the seven books of Xenophon’s 
Hellenica extends from Ol. 92, 3. B.c. 410 to Ol. 104, 3. 8.6. 
362. He does not mark the succession of events very accu- 
rately, but when he does so he adopts the notation of Thucy- 
dides, and counts by summers and winters. In the first two 
books we find also the names of archons and ephors and the 
numbers of Olympiads, but these are clearly interpolations of a 
later date. He sometimes gives the year of the Peloponnesian 
war, like his predecessor, but great errors have crept into his 
numbers in this respect. 

§ 4. The name of Xenophon is most favourably known from his 
Anabasis, or ‘ expedition up the country’ of Cyrus the younger, 
where the author has described, in the most lively and pleasing- 
manner, the celebrated retreat of the Ten Thousand, in which 
he bore so prominent a part. That this work was written by 
Xenophon is proved not merely by the style, but by the express 
testimony of Plutarch? and Diogenes Laértius ;* it was pub- 
lished, however, under the name of Themistogenes of Syra- 
cuse,* and is quoted by Xenophon himself under that title. 
It is stated that there was an author of this name, and that he 
wrote other works relating to Sicily ;° but it is more probable 
that Xenophon invented the name which he assumed.’ The 





1 Lucian, De Conscribendd Historia, ὃ 40, p. 52. 


2 De Glor. Ath., p. 345. 8 Vit. Xenoph. 11. ὃ 57. 
4. Plutarch, ubi supr.; Schol. ad Tzetz. Epist. XX1: ὥσπερ καὶ Ξενοφῶν ἐπέγραψε 
τὴν Κύρου ἀνάβασιν Θεμιστογένει Συρακουσίῳ. 5 Hellen. III. 1, ὃ 2. 


§ Suidas, 5. v.: Θεμιστογένης Συρακούσιος ἱστορικός. Κύρου ἀνάβασιν, ἥτις ἐν τοῖς 
Ξενοφῶντος Ἑλληνικοῖς φέρεται, καὶ ἄλλα τινὰ περὶ τῆς ἑαυτοῦ πατρίδος. 

7 Τὸ has been suggested that the name means, ‘a son of right, who became a 
Syrian (i.e. served the barbarian) against his will.’ Niebuhr thinks that the name 
refers to Dionysius and his princely birth. 


190 XENOPHON AND CTESIAS. 


reasons which induced him to write this history of his Eastern 
campaign also operated with him in withholding his name. It 
was designed as a justification of his conduct, and as a proof to 
the Athenians that they had deprived themselves of the services 
of a brave and skilful officer; and it is clear that such an 
apology would come with the best grace from a stranger’s pen. 
A Greek Lexicographer’ speaks of it as having formed part of 
the Hellenica : and it has been suggested by Niebuhr’ that, as 
the first two books of the Hellenica, added to the eight of 
Thucydides, formed the number ten, one in which the Athenians 
delighted, so the remaining five of the Hellenica added to the 
seven books of the Anabasis formed the number twelve, also of 
great importance in the arrangements of Ionie¢ states. In addi- 
tion to this we may observe that every book of the Anabdasis, 
after the first, with the exception of the sixth, which seems 
to have suffered some loss at the beginning, commences with a 
recapitulation of the preceding part of the narrative, and we 
may remark something of the same kind at the commencement 
of the third book of the Hellenica: so that the last five books 
of the latter may have heen originally appended to the Anabasis, 
and were not till afterwards attached to the continuation of 
Thucydides. Although Xenophon has called this history of 
his adventures the Anadasis, or expedition of Cyrus, that expe- 
dition, as far as Cyrus was concerned, finishes with the first 
book ; and the six remaining books are occupied with the far 
more interesting account of the manner in which the Greek 
mercenaries escaped from their perilous situation in the heart 
of the Persian empire, and, after fighting their way through 
hosts of barbarians, in Kurdistan and elsewhere, arrived at the 
Euxine, and so proceeded along the sea-shore till they came to 
the coast of the Aigzean. It is difficult to describe the charm 
which this book has always had for the modern reader; the 
minuteness of detail, the picturesque simplicity of the style, 
and the air of reality and truth which pervade it, have made 
it a favourite with every age: and it is still eminently interest- 
ing and instructive to the military reader and the geographer. 
But at the time when it appeared it must have been looked 





1 Suidas, s.v. Θεμιστογένης. 2 Philol. Mus. I., p. 488. 


WORKS OF XENOPHON. 191 


upon as practically one of. the most important works ever 
written, and many a Greek general and statesman, till Philip 
resolved on, and Alexander undertook, the proof of the proposi- 
tion, must have reflected on the author’s assertion, that ‘ the 
kingdom of Persia, though powerful from its extent and popu- 
lation, was yet by reason of the distance between one place and 
another, and the dispersion of its military force, weak as against 
an active general.’? 

§ 5. After having attempted to justify his own proceedings in 
Asia by the recital of his adventures, Xenophon seems to have 
thought it his next business to undertake the defence of his 
friend and teacher, Socrates, who had suffered the punishment 
of death during his absence from Europe. This he has done in 
two works, a slighter and more trivial essay called the Defence 
of Socrates, and a larger work, in four books, entitled the 
Memorials of Socrates. The latter seems to have been com- 
posed some little time after his return: he speaks of the death 
of Socrates in the same terms which he uses in speaking of the 
amnesty of Thrasybulus in his second book of Hellenica,’ which, 
we have seen, must have been written within two years of the 
events there narrated; and the general tone of the work would lead 
us to conclude that it could not have been published long after 
the death of the philosopher. In this work, asin his Anabasis, 
he justifies rather by narrative than by argument. In the first 
book, indeed, he attempts a series of answers to the five different 
points in the accusation, but few critical readers will think that 
he has made good the grounds of his defence. In general, he 
seems to have misunderstood the theoretical importance of the 
doctrines of Socrates, and to have wilfully misrepresented their 
practical bearing, which he so well understood and acted upon. 
It is agreed by scholars and philosophical writers that no 
adequate idea of the worth of Socrates as a philosopher can be 
derived from the Memorials of Xenophon. In regard to the 
higher matters of philosophy, the author of this book can only 
claim the dubious merits of a Boswell, who seeks to record, to 





1 Anabas. I. 5, § 9. 
2 Memor. IV. 8, § 11: τῶν δὲ Σ. γιγνωσκόντων, οἷος ἣν, οἱ ἀρετῆς ἐφιέμενοι πάντες 


ἔτι καὶ νῦν διατελοῦσι πάντων μάλιστα ποθοῦντες ἐκεῖνον, ὡς ὠφελιμώτατον ὄντα 
πρὸς ἀρετῆς ἐπιμέλειαν, 


192 XENOPHON AND CTESIAS. 


the best of his ability, the conversations of a very superior man, 
which he admired and listened to, but did not thoroughly com- 
prehend. With very little toleration for philosophy in general, 
aud no accurate conceptions as to the Socratic system of 
dialectics, it is not to be expected that his work should be a 
good exponent of the teaching of his master. At the same 
time, it is possible to gather from isolated passages some frag- 
ments of the moral philosophy of Socrates; and the method 
which results from a combination of these may be profitably 
compared with that which forms the basis of Plato’s ethics. 
Thus we find traces of the four-fold division of virtue which is 
so prominent in the writings of Plato. There is, however, this 
remarkable distinction between the Socratic opinions on the 
cardinal virtues as set forth by Xenophon and the same as 
developed by Plato. In Xenophon’s Memorials, Socrates is 
introduced as acknowledging three separate virtues—temperance, 
which is the foundation of them all,’ courage,’ and justice,’ and 
these are all included in the virtue of wisdom or prudence.’ 
This seems to be quite in accordance with the Socratic doctrine 
of self-consciousness as we learn it from Aristotle. For with 
Socrates there was always an interweaving of the scientific with 
the moral: in other words, knowledge is the moving cause of the 
will, and good is the final cause of knowledge; hence the 
knowledge of what justice is must lead to the being just, for no 
one would cf his own accord relinquish what he knows to be 
good. Plato, on the other hand, makes Socrates acknowledge 
three separate virtues—temperance (which in his earliest 
dialogue he seems to consider as the basis of all virtue), 
courage, and prudence or wisdom; while the harmony or 
unison of these constitutes justice. In this particular, we 
must admit that Xenophon has given us a truer representation 
of the teaching of Socrates than his more philosophical brother 
disciple. And this may perhaps serve as a specimen of the 
manner in which Plato has enlarged and modified the Socratic 
element in his philosophy. Both Socrates and Plato started 
from the four-fold division of virtue, but the theory of Plato’s 





17. 5, 8.4: τὴν ἐγκρατείαν ἀρετῆς εἶναι κρηπῖδα. 
2 TV. 6. § το. 3 IV. 4. § 12- ὃ 21, seqq. ae ἘΣ 


WORKS OF XENOPHON. 193 


Utopia necessitated a subordination of all virtue to justice, while 
the Socratic doctrine of knowledge or science assumed that all 
the virtues sprung from wisdom or prudence. The little allegory 
generally known as the Choice of Hercules, which has been often 
selected from Xenophon’s Memorials of Socrates as most pecu- 
liarly worthy of admiration, was probably an actual abridgment 
of the celebrated Epideixis of Prodicus, to whom Xenophon 
attributes it. Later writers speak of it as the Xenophontean 
or Socratic Hercules,’ perhaps because the original work was no 
longer extant, and because every one was familiar with the 
apologue as given by Xenophon. At all events, we know that 
Prodicus wrote such an allegory, and the manner in which 
Xenophon has introduced it, bears no analogy to Plato’s intro- 
duction in the Phedrus of a speech composed for Lysias to 
characterize and expose the peculiar defects of his style. 

The Apology of Socrates is a short and rather feeble tract, 
referring more immediately to the cause of that philosopher’s 
condemnation to death—namely, his contumelious behaviour 
after the verdict had been given against him. Xenophon 
endeavours to excuse this, by showing that Socrates really pre- 
ferred death to life, and that his consciousness of his own 
innocence prevented him from naming any punishment as due 
to the offence of which he had been convicted. The modern 
reader will smile at the impotent malice with which he has 
recorded the intemperance of the son of Anytus. 

§ 6. From the data at the end of the Cyropedia, it appears 
that this treatise was written after Ol. 104, 3. B.c. 362.7 That 
the work did not lay claim to be considered as a history, but 
was only a political and moral romance, like the Télemaque of 
Fenelon, is not only sufficiently clear from internal evidence, 
but is expressly acknowledged by many ancient writers.’ 
It was in fact the only mode in which Xenophon, with his habits 
- and peculiar bias, could draw up and set forth a theory of 
government, in accordance with the practice of most of the 
eminent post-Socratic writers. Some of the ancients tell us 





1 Cicero, ad Fam. V.12. Varro, ap. Non. p. 168, 539, 542. 
2 VIII. 8, § 4, where he alludes to circumstances which took place during the 
Aigyptian revolt against Artaxerxes Mnemon. 
3 e.g. Cicero, ad Quint. fr. I. τ, 8, 23. 
Vou. II, ο 


194 XENOPHON AND CTESIAS. 


that the Cyropedia was written in opposition to the Republic 
of Plato.’ Whatever we may think of this, it is at least clear 
that there is a remarkable contrast between them. This con- 
trast we consider as flowing immediately from the opposition 
between the characters and destinies of the two authors, though 
they both worked out the Socratic principle, each in his own 
way. Political theories were a prominent feature of the litera- 
ture which sprung from the Socratic school. It seems indeed 
to have been a natural consequence of the selfish system which 
was one practical result of that philosophy. In the older and 
simpler times of Greece, the member of a Greek community 
was quite content to perform the duties and enjoy the privileges 
of citizenship. To fight for his country in her militia, and to 
vote in her public assemblies, was the end of his wishes and the 
limit of his ambition. The general disorganization, however, 
produced by the Peloponesian war, swept away in its vortex 
both the citizen soldier and the citizen statesman; and while 
the warrior thought himself justified in letting out his strength 
or his skill to the best bidder, without any regard to the interests 
of his native land, the man of letters, full of his self-conscious- 
ness, and exulting in a sense of his superiority, framed political 
theories at variance with the constitution of his own city, and 
endeavoured to recommend, by fiction or by argument, his 
own abstract speculations respecting the best form of govern- 
ment. The older philosophers had busied themselves with exist- 
ing constitutions, holding public offices and administering the 
laws with a view to the amelioration of the actual state of 
things. But although Socrates had sought to work on Athens 
itself through the medium of his individual disciples, those of 
his scholars, who thought and wrote for themselves, were far 
from taking any state as their model or as the ground-work of 
their labours. They first formed for themselves some concep- 
tion of a perfect state, and then set about realizing their con- 
ception without reference to the institutions of any Grecian 
commonwealth. Thus Plato believed that the happiness of a 
state depended upon its having a philosophical ruler, under 
whose mild and beneficent government every part of virtue 





1 Diogen. Laert. Plato, (III. ὃ 34.). 


WORKS OF XENOPHON. 195 


would receive its due development: hence, his earnest and 
repeated attempts to give a right direction to the mind of the 
younger Dionysius; hence his intercourse with Dion; and 
hence the attempts of his scholars Euagon, Cheron, and 
Timzeus. Xenophon’s partialities were those of the mercenary 
soldier rather than those of the philosopher. Military men, with 
some traits of generosity and moderation to soften the asperity 
of their character, were the only heroes for him. He was quite 
prepared to idolize the younger Cyrus, as we see from his men- 
tion of various particulars connected with the fratricidal expedi- 
tion of that prince. But after his return from Asia, the Spartan 
Agesilaus was the sole object of his enthusiastic admiration; by his 
side he fought against his own country, and for his sake he 
eulogized the Spartan constitution, while he depreciated that of 
Athens. As, however, no man, not even Agesilaus, and no state, 
not even Sparta, quite came up to the idea which he had formed 
of a country under the absolute government of a wise and warlike 
but perfectly virtuous prince, he turned back to Persia and its 
first Cyrus, and, with reference no doubt to the younger Cyrus, 
whom he had wished to place on the Eastern throne, drew an 
elaborate picture of the various successes of the first Persian 
king, and the various measures which he took to secure the in- 
terests and happiness of his people. Feeling that his strong 
point was narrative, and considering himself entitled, as a cele- 
brated Persian traveller, to say something on the affairs of the 
East, he has not scrupled to mix up with his theory a good 
deal that is historical, and he concludes with remarks on the 
actual degeneracy of the Persians, as a sort of apology to his 
Greek readers for the selection of Persia as a model for a per- 
fect constitution. There is no doubt, however, that Xenophon, 
as well as Isocrates and many other Greeks, looked upon Persia 
as the new materials out of which such a government might be 
constructed, and considered it the duty and the proper business 
of Greece to conquer it: and it is equally clear that, if the great 
pupil of Aristotle had enjoyed a longer life, he would have 
attempted to give a comprehensive reality to schemes, which, at 
the time of his birth, were but dimly seen in the distant future. 
In his Panegyric on Agesilaus we perceive, even more clearly 
than in the Cyropedia, what sort of a king Xenophon would 
oy 7 


196 XENOPHON AND CTESIAS. 


have placed at the head of the great military commonwealth 
of Greece. In that tract, he tries his hero by the Socratic 
model, as it is set forth in his Memorials. Ue shows that 
Agesilaus was very attentive to the duties of religion,’ and that 
he possessed in an eminent degree the four cardinal virtues? of 
justice,®> temperance,* fortitude,’ and wisdom.’ He tells us, 
however, that the wisdom for which he praises him was rather 
practical than speculative,’ rather that of the statesman and 
warrior than that of the philosopher, and we may be sure that 
he would never have agreed with Plato in placing the philoso- 
phical above the military caste in his state. It is with great 
significance too that he remarks on the fondness of Agesilaus 
for Greece in general, and his hatred of the barbarians in general, 
and of the Persians in particular.*. When Agesilaus heard that 
nearly 10,000 Greeks of the party opposed to Sparta had fallen in 
the battle of Corinth, instead of rejoicing at the victory which his 
friends had obtained, he exclaimed, according to Xenophon, ‘ Alas 
for Hellas! those who have now fallen would have been sufficient to 
conquer all the barbarians,’—a manifest allusion to Xenophon’s 
celebrated retreat, and to the hopes of Eastern conquest in 
which so many Greeks indulged. 

The literary merits of the Cyropedia are by no means of a 
high order. The harangues, which are introduced on every 
occasion, important or unimportant, are exceedingly tedious. 
The whole work is pervaded by a feeble and mawkish tone which 
now and then degenerates into absolute childishness. The 
jests between Cyrus and his soldiers are vulgar and indecorous ; 
and many of the narratives are prolix and uninteresting. There 
are indeed several redeeming passages. There is much simple 
pathos in the episode of Panthea and Abradatas ;” the address 





1 Agesil. Ὁ. 3, § 2. 

3 It is remarkable that the panegyric on Love put into the mouth of Agatho, in 
Plato’s Symposium, (p. 196, B.), is made to attribute to that deity these four human 
excellences. It is just possible that Plato may have had in view the encomium of 
Agesilaus in this passage, as he is supposed to have had his eye on Xenophon’s Sym- 
posium in his own rival composition. 


Ses as 4 0,55. 5 ¢. 6, § 1, seqq. δ, 6, § 4, seqq. 
7 ¢. 11, § 9: καὶ σοφίαν ἔργῳ μᾶλλον ἢ λόγοις ἤσκει. 
8 ¢. 4. 9 6. 7, § 5. 


10° VI. 1, § 45, 4, § 2. VII. 3, δ 1, seqq. 


WORKS OF XENOPHON. 197 


of Cyrus to his sons is a pretty moral essay ;’ and his account 
of the soul’s immortality has more of exalted reasoning than 
we should expect to find in any work of Xenophon.* On the 
whole, however, we cannot share in the admiration with which 
this work was regarded by many illustrious Romans—especially 
Scipio Aimilianus and Cicero.’ 

§ 7. Several ancient writers have referred to the rivalry or 
jealousy supposed to have subsisted between Xenophon and 
Plato ; and though modern scholars are disposed to reject the 
allegation that there was any open misunderstanding between 
these eminent Socratic writers, there can be no doubt that Plato 
in his Laws has directed some censures against Xenophon’s 
Cyropedia,* and perhaps there is some truth in the assump- 
tion of Athenzeus that Plato had Xenophon’s Banquet in his 
eye when he wrote his own work bearing the same name.’ 
Xenophon’s Symposium or Banquet relates what happened at a 
feast given by Callias, at his house in the Pireus, in honour 
of a victory obtained at the Panathenzea by the young and 
handsome pancratiast, Autolycus. The guests, among whom 
are Socrates and Antisthenes, amuse themselves with the ab- 
surdities of a jester and the feats of a Syracusan stroller and 
his company, who performed, among other things, the ballet of 
Bacchus and Ariadne: but there is no method in their conver- 
sation; no one idea is worked out by the interlocutors ; and 
with all its grace and elegance it falls far short, even in these 
respects, of the rival work of Plato. 

Xenophon’s Ciconomicus, a treatise on agriculture and the 
management of a household, is conceived more in the spirit of 
Socrates than any of his minor writings. It is a dialogue 
between Socrates and Critobulus, which, but for its length, 
might have been introduced into the ᾿Απομνημονεύματα, for it 
begins abruptly, like the different chapters in that book, with: 
ἤκουσά ποτε αὐτοῦ διαλεγομένου, ‘I once heard him convers- 
ing” Like many of Plato’s dialogues, it is principally taken 
up with the narration by Socrates of another conversation held 

- by himself and one Ischomachus on the same subject. In this 





1 VIII. 7, § 8, seqq. ; 2 VIII. 7, § 17. 
8 Cicero, ad Famil. IX. 25, 1. Tuscul. Disput. II. 26, 62. 
4 Plato, Legg. Ill. p. 694, C. 5 Athen, XI. p. 504, E. 


198 XENOPHON AND CTESIAS. 


secondary dialogue, Xenophon is careful to show, that, in his 
opinion, the καλοκἀγαθὸς was one, who, while he paid due 
reverence to the gods, bestowed all his time and talents on the 
work of promoting and securing his own interests. In fact, 
even in Xenophon, there are few more candid avowals of the 
selfish principle, which, as he elsewhere expresses it, is simply 
this, that the καλὸν is identical with the ὠφέλιμον. We also 
see in this little work strong proofs of the practical bias of 
Xenophon’s mind, and his decided preference of the military 
man and the farmer above the literary man and philosopher. 
The incident related of Cyrus the younger’ is another indica- 
tion, among many, of Xenophon’s enthusiasm for this young 
and ambitious barbarian. He concludes the work with insist- 
ing on the importance of intellectual and moral training to 
every one who wished to rule over others without offering any 
violence to their inclinations—an object which he seems to 
have considered as the one most important to the practical phi- 
losopher, and which was certainly the point aimed at in all his 
political theories. 

The Hiero must be considered as a sort of qualification of 
the author’s general approbation of military government and 
the employment of mercenaries. It is a dialogue between the 
tyrant of Syracuse and the poet Simonides, and its object is to 
show, on the one hand, that the lot of the tyrant is far from an 
enviable one, and, on the other hand, that there are ways of 
obviating the inconveniences and disadvantages attendant on 
the possession of absolute power; that it is possible to rule 
despotically without forfeiting the affections of subjects; and 
that even mercenaries may be so employed as to become 
popular. 

Of his remaining treatises little need be said. His tracts on 
horsemanship and hunting are interesting to the antiquarian, 
and his Hipparchichus, or ‘ cavalry tactics,’ must have had its 
practical value at the time. His essays on the constitutions of 
Sparta and Athens are principally remarkable for the uncandid 
and partial views which the author seeks to defend, and for 
which he has but poorly atoned in the feeble pamphlet on the 





1c. 4. ὃ 17, seqq. 


STYLE OF XENOPHON. 199 


revenues of Athens, said to have been written by him after his 
return from exile, as an offering of peace to his forgiving 
countrymen. 

§ 8. The diction of Xenophon corresponds in its main 
features with the simple or plain style (ἀφελὴς λόγος) of Lysias ; 
but in his historical works especially he has tried to imitate the 
unperiodic diction (λέξις εἰρομένη) of Herodotus, whom he seems 
to have taken as his model, as far as was possible, both in his 
style and in his mode of treating his subjects.’ The ancient 
rhetoricians, Aristides, Dionysius, and Hermogenes, agree in 
considering Xenophon as a designedly plain and simple writer. 
The latter says that he is plain (apeAje) to the highest degree, 
and that he abounds in this characteristic more than all others 
of the declamatory style, insomuch that even when he attempts 
anything sublime in the conception, he softens it down to his usual 
plainness and simplicity (καθαιρεῖ καὶ [βιάζεται πρὸς τὸ ἀφελές). 
This peculiarity of Xenophon’s style is perhaps not altogether 
designed. The wandering life which he led, his long absence 
from his native land, and his constant intercourse with 
foreigners, would tend to remove from his language the diffi- 
culty and idiomatic raciness of the Attic dialect, and as Lysias, 
a foreigner living at Athens, adopted this plain style in the 
orations which he wrote for the Attic courts of law, so Xeno- 
phon, an Athenian residing in the Peloponnese, might naturally 
employ the same means of making himself understood to foreign 
readers. In fact, we seein Xenophon, more than in any of his 
contemporaries, a first approximation to the common dialect 
(κοινὴ διάλεκτος) which became afterwards the universal language 
of Greece. ‘The selfish, unpatriotic character of the man has 
deprived his language of any national individuality of colouring, 
and thus, although many of the later writers in particular have 
commended Xenophon’s style as the perfection of Attic Greek 
—calling him the Attic muse, the Attic bee, and so forth’— 
there is more of critical accuracy in the remark of Helladius, 
that ‘it is not a matter of wonder that a man like Xeno- 





1 Dionysius Hal. De precip. histor. IV. p. 777, Reiske: Hevopav μὲν γὰρ 
Ἡροδότου ζηλωτὴς ἐγένετο κατ᾽ ἀμφοτέρους τοὺς χαρακτῆρας, τόν Te πραγματικὸν καὶ 
τὸν λεκτικόν. 

2 Diog. Laert. II. § 57. Suidas, s.v. Ξενοφῶν. Comp. Cicero, Orat. 9, 32, 19, 62. 


200 XENOPHON AND CTESIAS. 


phon, who spent his time in military service and in intercourse 
with foreigners, should occasionally adulterate his mother- 
tongue; on which account no one should consider him as an 
authority in Atticism.”’ 

δ g. It seems desirable to mention in connexion with Xeno- 
phon a contemporary Greek historian, who also took service 
with the Persians, but, being on the winning side at the battle 
of Cynaxa, had an opportunity of writing about the country 
from observation and documents, instead of drawing on his ima- 
gination for a romance like the Cyropedia. Crxsias of Cnidus, 
the son of Ctesiochus or Ctesarchus, was brought up to the 
profession of medicine, of which Cnidus was one of the regular 
seats, and was probably induced by the promise of substantial 
advantages to take up his residence at the Persian court, where 
Greek physicians had been in great request since the time of 
Democedes. He became the body-surgeon of Artaxerxes 
Mnemon, and treated him for the wound which he received at 
Cynaxa.” As it is stated that he returned to his native country 
in B. c. 398, after seventeen years residence in Persia,® he must 
have taken service with Artaxerxes in B.c. 415. It was pro- 
bably after he was again settled at Cnidus that he drew up, in 
Ionic Greek, according to the old rule, the works for which he 
had obtained the materials during his sojourn in the east. 
These were: (1.) A history of Persia (Περσικά) in twenty-three 
books, derived from the royal archives (διφθεραὶ βασιλικαί). The 
first six books treated of the great Assyrian monarchy. The 
remainder of the work carried the history of Persia down to 
the year B.c. 599. Besides some fragments in the more recent 
writers, an extract from the later books has been preserved by 
Photius.’ Whatever may have been the faults of Ctesias,’ it is 
much to be regretted that we have lost this early contribution 
to oriental history. (2.) An account of India (᾿Ἰνδικά), ὁ. e., 
of the Punjab most probably. From this also we have an ex- 





1 Helladius apud Phot. Cod. CCLXXIX. p, 1589., Hoeschel. 

.2 Xenoph, Anab. 1. 8, § 26. 3 Diodor. XIV. τό. 

4 Strabo, XIV. p. 656. Diodor. XIV. 46. 5 Cod. LXXII. 

6 See the passages quoted and examined by Babr, Ctesie Cnidii Reliquie, 
Francof. 1824, pp. 35 sqq.; and for the strictures on his Ἰνδικά, οἵ, Miiller, in 
Didot’s collection of the fragments, p. 


WORKS OF CTESIAS. 201 


tract in Photius. As the materials were probably derived from 
Persian information, that is, at second hand, it was not more 
authentic than the accounts given us in Herodotus, though 
perhaps it entered into greater details. His other works were: 
(3.) A coasting-voyage of Asia (Περίπλους ᾿Ασίας) ;' (4.) On the 
tributes of Asia (περὶ τῶν κατὰ τὴν ᾿Ασίαν φόρων) 3 (5.) On 
mountains (περὶ ὀρῶν) ;* and (6.) On rivers (περὶ ποταμῶν). A 
reference in Galen’ has led to the inference that Ctesias also left 
some medical works, of which, however, there are no traces ; and 
not even the titles have been preserved. The style of Ctesias 
is highly commended by Demetrius Phalereus*® and Photius’, and 
his diction is compared with that of Xenophon by Dionysius of 
Halicarnassus.* 

We shall see in a future chapter’ that Arrian took. the 
parallel publications of Xenophon and Ctesias as the models for 
his principal works, writing his Epictetus, his Anabasis, and his 
treatise on hunting in imitation of Xenophon, and in the Attic 
dialect ; but making Ctesias his copy, and the Ionic dialect his 
diction, in the treatise on India, and also following Ctesias in 
his Periplus. 





1 Steph. Byz. s.vv. Κοσύτη, Σίγυνος. 
2 It is supposed by Miiller that this work was only an extract from the Περσικά. 


8 Two books are mentioned Plut. De flwviis, 21. 4 Id. ἐδ. το. 
5 V. p. 652, 1. 51, ed. Basil. 6 De Elocutione, ὃ 218. 
7 Cod. LXXTI. 


8 De Comp. Verb. το, p. 53. Reiske: ἡ δέ ye τοῦ Κνιδίου συγγραφέως Κτησίου 
[Aégts] καὶ ἡ τοῦ Σωκρατικοῦ Ξενοφῶντος ἡδέως μὲν [obyxerra] ws ἔνι μάλιστα, οὐ 
μὴν καλῶς γε ἐφ᾽ ὅσον ἔδει. 

. 93. Below, chapter LV. § 2. 


202 


CHAPTER XXXIX. 
PLATO. 


§ 1. Importance of Plato’s writings even in a literary point of view. § 2. Life of 
Plato. § 3. His political character and conduct. § 4. His literary relations to 
his contemporaries and predecessors.- ὃ 5. Why he wrote in dialogues. ὃ 6. 
Chronological order and scientific arrangement of his works. § 7. Plato’s dia- 
lectics. ὃ 8. His ethical system. ὃ 9. His physical speculations. ὃ 10, Pecu- 
liarities and excellences of his style. 


§ 1. bch year 429 8.0. is distinguished by two events of the 

greatest importance in regard to the literary glory 
and political power of Athens. On the 21st of May in that 
year the city gave birth to the most illustrious writer in all the 
catalogue of Attic authors, and in the following autumn the 
great statesman Pericles died at an advanced age, after having 
administered the affairs of his country in peace and war for 
forty years. By the latter event Athens lost her best hope of 
continuing that sovereignty, which took its rise in the glories of 
the Persian war, and was dissipated by the treason or incapacity 
of those who took the place of Pericles at the head of the 
government. By the former she became the founder of a 
literary empire far more extensive and durable than any which 
she could have established by the aid of her hoplites and triremes ; 
for there can be little doubt that the higher culture of Europe, 
since the days of Plato, has been directly or indirectly the re- 
presentative of that moral and intellectual philosophy, of which 
the teaching and writings of this great Athenian were the first 
definite expression.’ The place which Plato occupies among 
the leaders of human thought, the multifarious relations which 
connect his speculations and criticisms with those of his pre- 





1 Mr. Archer Butler, in his able and eloquent Lectures on the History of Ancient 
Philosophy (vol. II. p. 1), says that Plato’s philosophy ‘whether regarded in itself, 
or with reference to its influence upon the history of reflective man, rises before us 
in all the dignity of the mightiest and most permanent monument ever erected by 
unassisted human thought exercised upon the human destinies.’ 


IMPORTANCE OF PLATO’S WRITINGS. 203 


_decessors, and with the Jong series of his successors down to the 
present time, and the many forms in which Platonism is still 
an influential element in the religious and moral theories of 
Europe, would seem to indicate that a review of his writings 
would be a more appropriate subject for a separate treatise than 
for a chapter in the literary history of Greece. Fortunately, 
however, we are not required or expected on the present 
occasion, to deal with any of those subjects which have given a 
lasting and ever-present importance to the views which were 
originally expounded in the Academy. It is our business merely 
to tell who Plato was, what were the nature and development 
of his literary activity, and what were the leading characteristics 
of his genius as a writer. These points, and these only, we 
shall be able to discuss satisfactorily within the limits imposed 
upon us by the present work.’ 

But even setting aside philosophy, and regarding Plato’s 
writings merely from a literary point of view, it would be 
difficult to over-estimate his importance. We have seen that 
Socrates, who introduced the great revolution in philosophy, did 
not himself leave behind him any literary memorials of those 
discussions which he carried on so perpetually in the streets of 
Athens. And the same remark applies to the imperfect So- 
cratic schools. For whatever may have been the value of the 
Cynical or Cyrenaical systems, as partially representing the 
moral philosophy of Socrates, and whatever may have been the 
merits of the Megaric school, as an exponent of his dialectics, 
the leaders of these movements have no important position in 
the literature of Greece. We are obliged to learn what we 
know of them from scattered notices in various authors, or from 
the reviews which Plato has left us in the form of dialogues. 
It was in this, as in almost every effort of creative genius. The 
thought struggles for the literary expression. Great teachers 
go about among their fellow-men. They give oral instruction ; 
they awaken dormant ideas; they do and suffer. But their 





1 The author is to a certain extent prepared for this task by the more general 
survey of Plato’s philosophy which he contributed to the Penny Cyclopedia in 1840, 
Art. Plato, a paper to which he presumes a tacit reference in the present chapter ; 
for the subject and the writer being the same, even an occasional repetition of his 
own words has been inevitable. 


204 PLATO. 


influence is either confined to their own generation, and be- 
comes for posterity nearly as though it had never been; or it 
finds some man of literary genius, who casts the preacher’s 
thoughts in his own mould, and gives them a permanent form, 
and an indelible expression. This constitutes the literary im- 
portance of Plato. We should have known from Xenophon 
who Socrates was, and, in fact, the nature of his teaching. But 
we owe it to Plato that his ideas, or rather, the thoughts which 
he awakened, have been made the germ of one of the grandest 
systems of speculation that the world has ever seen, and that 
they have been conveyed to us in literary compositions, which 
are unequalled in refinement of conception, or in vigour and 
gracefulness of style. 

§ 2. According to the most definite and consistent accounts, 
Pxiato was born on the 7th day of Thargelion in Ol. 87, 3, in 
the archonship of Apollodorus, that is, according to our reckon~ 
ing, on the 21st May, 429 3B.c.; and his admirers used long 
afterwards to keep the anniversary of his birthday, which was 
also the natal feast of the Delian Apollo. His lineage was one 
of the noblest at Athens, for he traced his descent on the 
mother’s side to the family of Solon and Codrus. His father 
was Ariston, the son of Aristocles, and it is stated that Plato 
was originally called after his grandfather, his ordinary designa- 
tion, which was not uncommon among the Athenians at that 
time, being a surname derived from his broad chest or his 
expansive forehead, or, as some have imagined, from the breadth 
of his style, whatever may be the meaning of that phrase. 
When he changed his name is not known. But if modern 
scholars have rightly adopted the opinion of Diogenes and the 
old grammarians,' that Aristophanes in his Ecclesiazuse ridicules 
Plato’s proposal for a community of property and wives, and 
that the philosopher is directly alluded to in that play and the 
Plutus, which were acted in 392 and 388 B.c., under the con- 
temptuous diminutive Aristyllus, it would seem that the name 





1 Morgenstern, Commentatio de Republica Platonis, pp. 73, seqq. Meineke, 
* Historia Critica Comicorum Grecorum, pp. 287, seqq. The authorities quoted are 
Diog. Laért. III. 23, Aristoph. Zecles. 646, Plut. 313, Eustath. p. 989, Herodian, 
apud Etym. M. p. 142, F: ᾿Αρίστυλλος : ὄνομα παρὰ ᾿Αριστοφάνει, εἴρηται δὲ 
ὑποκοριστικῶς δ᾽ Δριστοκλῆς. Cf. Fischer, ad Weller. IL. p. 33. 


LIFE OF PLATO. 205 


by which he is now known had either not been adopted, or was 
not his familiar appellation at the time when, as we shall see, 
he wrote his most important works. Some of Plato’s relatives 
were very well known men. Crritias, the leader of the tyran- 
nical oligarchy at Athens, was a cousin of his mother’s, and her 
brother Charmides fell fighting by the side of Critias in the 
struggle with Thrasybulus in the Peirzus. It has been gene- 
rally supposed that Glaucon and Adeimantus, who play a pro- 
minent part in the great dialogue of the Republic, were Plato’s 
brothers, who are known to have borne those names ; but 
C. F. Hermann' has made it probable that these interlocutors 
belonged to an earlier generation; and the following may be 
accepted as the most probable representation of the philosopher’s 
family, and of his descent from the father of Solon :— 


Execestides. 


Solon. Dropides. 











Antipho I. Aristocles I. 
Critias I. 
| | | | ἜΣ, 
Callzschrus. Glauco I. Ἴ daughter. Aristo I. Pyrilampes, 
Critias IT. 
Charmides. | Glauco II. Antipho II. 
Adeimantus I. 





Perictione Aristo IT. 





| 
Prato (Aristocles II.), Glauco III., Aes hata αὐ 11. 


It is more than probable that Solon and Dropides were not 
brothers ; indeed Plato himself’ speaks of them merely as 
intimate friends and connexions; and the claim of a direct 
descent from Execestides was probably set up in later times, 
when Plato’s admirers lost no opportunity of exalting the family 
and person of a man whom they invested with almost godlike 
attributes. On the other hand, an attempt has been made to 





1 Platonische Philosophie, p. 24. 
2 Timeus, p. 20, E., where Critias is made to say of Solon: ἣν μὲν οὖν οἰκεῖος 
καὶ σφόδρα φίλος ἡμῖν Δρωπίδου τοῦ προπάππου, καθάπερ λέγει πολλάκις καὶ αὐτὸς 


ἐν τῇ ποιήσει, and the Scholiast on the passage remarks: λέγονται γὰρ οἰκεῖοι καὶ 
φίλοι. 


206 PLATO. 


deprive the Mother-city of the honour of having given birth to the 
greatest man in her literary history. About the time of Plato’s — 
birth, the Doric island of Agina was stript of its inhabitants, and 
colonized by Athenian settlers (κληροῦχοι), among whom was 
Aristophanes, the comic poet; and it has been stated’ that 
Plato’s family had emigrated also. But this seems to be a 
groundless tradition. 

Connected as he was with the most distinguished family at 
Athens, it is not surprising that Plato received the best educa- 
tion which was then attainable in Greece ; and we are told that 
he exhibited at an early age those qualities which raised him to 
literary eminence. He learned the elements of reading and 
writing (γράμματα) in the school of one Dionysius; Ariston, 
an Argive wrestler, instructed him in gymnastic exercises ; his 
music-masters were Draco of Athens, a pupil of the famous 
Damon, and Metallus, or Megallus, of Agrigentum, whom some 
identify with Megillus,? a Pythagorean writer on the theory of 
numbers.’ It is stated that he contended successfully as a 
wrestler in all the great games of Greece; and that he com- 
posed dithyrambic, lyric, elegiac, tragic, and epic poems. These 
are all lost ; for there can be no doubt that the thirty epigrams 
in the Anthologia, which are attributed to him, are a later 
fabrication. When we come to speak of his style we shall see 
that he retained to the last the traces of that poetical fancy 
which suggested the form of his earliest compositions. There 
is no improbability in the statement that he also applied him- 
self to painting, to which he refers in his dialogues in the 
language of an amateur.* 

We learn from Aristotle that Plato commenced his philo- 
sophical studies under the guidance of the Heracleitean 
Cratylus,’ who appears to have been a friend of Socrates. With 





1 Diog. III. 3. 

2 See Hermann, Platon. Philos. p. 99. 

3 His work περὶ ἀριθμῶν is cited in the Theologumena Arithmetice, p. 27, Ast., 
and the quotation shows that Plato may have derived some of his arithinatieal 
fancies from this source. 

4 See for example Thectet. p. 208, E., Resp. X. p. 602, C. 

* Aristot. Metaphys. I. c. 6: ἐκ νέου συγγενόμενος πρῶτον Κρατύλῳ καὶ ταῖς 
Ἡρακλειτείαις δόξαις. Apuleius, De dogm. Plat. p.2: ‘et antea quidem Heracleiti 
secta fuerat imbutus.’ 


LIFE OF PLATO. 207 


what other philosophical systems he made acquaintance before 
the year 410 B.c., when he first attached himself to Socrates, we 
have no means of knowing. Diogenes, indeed,’ asserts that 
Hermogenes, who maintains the Eleatic opinions in the dialogue 
called the Cratylus, was Plato’s instructor in that philosophical 
system ; but this is in all probability nothing more than an 
inference from the statement about Cratylus, and from their 
appearance in the same imaginary conversation. The circumstance 
which produced the greatest influence on his subsequent studies 
and pursuits, was undoubtedly the fact that he became one of the 
regular associates or pupils of Socrates at the early age of nine- 
teen or twenty, and did not leave his teacher until that martyr 
of intellectual freedom, or literary and philosophical insubordi- 
nation, drank the fatal cup of hemlock. He was present at the 
trial,? and was prevented by illness only from attending his 
master in his last moments.’ ΟΥ̓ his relations to his fellow 
pupils we are not able to speak with any certainty. The 
supposition that he was on unfriendly terms with Xenophon is 
not supported by any definite evidence. He does not refer to 
Aristippus and Antisthenes in favourable terms,’ but in most in- 
stances he speaks respectfully of the other disciples of Socrates. 
That the great teacher regarded Plato with kindly feelings of 
esteem may he inferred from the only passage in which 
Xenophon mentions our philosopher ; for he says that Socrates 
retained a lively interest in Glauco on account of Charmides 
and Plato.® 
_ The execution of Socrates in May, B.c. 399, was immediately 





1 171,6. 2 Apolog. p. 34, A.: οὑτοσὶ Πλάτων. 

8 Phedo, p. 59, B: Πλάτων δὲ οἶμαι ἠσθένει. 

4 There is a well-known treatise on this subject by A. Bockh, Commentatio Aca- 
demica de Simultate, que Platonit cwm Xenophonte intercessisse fertwr. Berol. 
1811. 

5 The absence of Aristippus from the death-scene of Socrates is merely mentioned 
in the Phedo, u.s. According to Demetrius, this was intended as a reproach (De 
elocutione, c. 288): οἷον ws ὁ Πλάτων ᾿Αρίστιππον καὶ Κλεόμβροτον λοιδορῆσαι 
θελήσας ἐν Αἰγίνῃ ὀψοφαγοῦντας δεδεμένου Σωκράτους ᾿Αθήνησιν ἐπὶ πολλὰς ἡμέρας 
καὶ μὴ διαπλεύσαντας ὡς τὸν ἑταῖρον καὶ διδάσκαλον. Plato manifestly glances at 
Aristippus in the Philebus, pp. 53, C. 54, D., and at Antisthenes in the Sophistes, 
pp. 251, B., 259, Ὁ. See above, p. 175. 

6 Xen. Mem. 111, 6,§ 1: Σωκράτης δὲ εὔνους dv αὐτῷ διά τε Kapplinv τὸν 
Γλαύκωνος καὶ διὰ Πλάτωνα. 


208 PLATO. 


followed by the retirement from Attica of those who had most 
warmly attached themselves to his person; and Eucleides, who 
had been one of those who attended the philosopher in his last 
moments, opened his house at Megara as an asylum for those 
who found it no longer safe to stay at Athens. Here Plato 
resided for some time, and his dialogues show that he availed 
himself of his intercourse with Eucleides to make himself 
thoroughly acquainted with that combination of Eleatic and 
Socratic doctrines which is known as the Megaric philosophy. 
He afterwards proceeded to Cyrene, on a visit to the mathema- 
tician Theodorus, who was also a friend of Socrates. It is 
worthy of remark that, while he professes to derive from a written 
report by Eucleides the three connected dialogues known as the 
Theetetus, the Sophistes, and the Politicus, the scene of which 
is laid at Athens, immediately before the trial of Socrates, 
Theodorus is represented as being present at all three conver-— 
sations, and in the first of the three advocates the doctrines of Pro- 
tagoras, in opposition to the searching criticisms of the Athenian 
philosopher. From Cyrene Plato is said to have travelled to 
Egypt, where we are told that he spent thirteen years in the 
study of all that the priests could teach him,’ and even in 
Strabo’s time the house, in which Plato and his companion 
Eudoxus had lodged, was exhibited among the things worth 
seeing at Heliopolis.” This journey to Egypt is also vouched 
for by Cicero,’ and it is not im itself improbable that he might 
have taken the opportunity while resident at Cyrene of making 
a tour in that wonderful country. But, independently of the 
known date of his return to Athens and of his journeys to 
Sicily, it is not at all likely that he spent there any consider- 
able time, and it is absurd to suppose that his residence extended 
to so long a period as thirteen years. His writings give no 
evidence of such a familiarity with Egyptian usages as would 
have resulted from such a lengthened sojourn.* And it is not 
improbable that the subsequent cultivation of his philosophy at 
Alexandria led to exaggerations on the subject. Still more 





1 Lactant. Instit. IV. 2. Clemens Alex. Protrept. p. 46, A. 

2 Strabo, p. 806, C. 

3 De Republ. I. το. 

4 See Professor Thompson’s note on Butler’s Lectwres, II. p. 15. 


LIFE OF PLATO. 209 


apocryphal are the stories about Plato’s intercourse with the 
Magi of Persia in their own country. He might have obtained 
some knowledge of their dualism without travelling into the 
heart of Asia. And the adoption of Platonic ideas by the early 
Christians was quite a sufficient inducement for them to invent 
or believe the story that he had borrowed some of these coin- 
cident views from the Divine revelation of the East. Plato’s 
Italian and Sicilian voyages are sufficiently authenticated. 
Whether we acquiesce, with Dr. Bentley’ and Mr Grote, in 
the genuineness of the epistles attributed to Plato, or, with 
Ast* and other critics, pronounce them to be spurious, we cannot 
deny what one of these latter writers* admits, that ‘they are in 
all probability the work of comparatively early authors, who 
may have been exactly informed of the historical particulars 
referred to in them.’ Now these epistles minutely describe 
Plato’s intercourse with the despots of Syracuse, Dionysius and 
his son, and with Dion the uncle of the latter. It appears that 
he paid three several visits to Sicily—the first in B.c. 389, 
when, having offended the elder Dionysius, he was, at the 
instigation of that tyrant, sold as a slave by Pollis the Spartan 
ambassador, in whose ship he was returning to Greece, but was 
redeemed from slavery by Anniceris of Cyrene, one of the 
scholars of Aristippus. Notwithstanding this treatment, he was 
induced in B.c. 367 to pay a second visit to Syracuse, at the 
request of Dion, who wished to secure his advice and instruc- 
tions for Dionysius the younger. This hopeless and thankless 
office was soon abandoned, for Dion was banished; and Plato 
returned to Greece after a four months’ sojourn in Sicily. 
His third and last visit, for the purpose of reconciling the uncle 
and nephew, was undertaken in B.c. 361, and he escaped from 
a place, which had become both dangerous and disagreeable, at 
some time in the following year. The interest which he took 
_in Dion, is perhaps also indicated by the fact that Speusippus, 
Plato’s nephew, who had been his companion on his second 





1 Remarks on Freethinking (in Randolph’s Enchiridion Theologicwm, II., pp. 
458, seqq.). 

2 History of Greece, X., p. 603. 

3 Platon’s Leben und Schriften, pp. 504, sqq. 

* Brandis, Handbuch, I1., p. 145. 


Vou. II. P 


216° PLATO. 


journey to Sicily, joined as a volunteer the body of adventurers 
by whose aid Dion, in 8.0. 357, succeeded in establishing himself 
at Syracuse. With the death of that chieftain in B.c. 353, 
Plato’s dealings with Sicily came to an end. His visit to 
Magna Grecia, in the south of Italy, was probably contem- 
porary with the first of his Sicilian journeys. He had no 
doubt gained some knowledge of the philosophy of Pytha- 
goras, and become familiar with the other Italian schools of 
philosophy at a much earlier period. As Philolaus had resided 
at Thebes where Simmias and Cebes heard him,’ and as Eche- 
crates was at Phlius about the time of the death of Socrates,’ 
Plato had abundant opportunities of making acquaintance with 
the leading Pythagoreans of the day, without going to Italy for 
the purpose. Still he might have felt some temptation, when 
in Sicily, to extend his travels to Tarentum, where he had the 
advantage of making himself personally known to Archytas and 
Eurytus, and learning from them many particulars of those spe- 
culations which entered so largely into his own system. How 
great was his interest in this development of philosophy may be 
learned from the statement that Plato induced Dion to buy for a 
large sum of money the treatise in which Philolaus for the first 
time expounded the doctrines of Pythagoras.’ It has been conjec- 
tured,* on the strength of a passage in the Theetetus,’ that 
Plato travelled to Ephesus, the birth-place of the Heracleitean 
philosophy in order to converse with the representatives of a 
school in which he had received very ample instructions from 
Cratylus, and a tradition speaks of his having been in Caria.° 
The journeys which we have described, with the exception of 
the voyage to Cyrene and the probable visit to Egypt, were 
undertaken after his return from Megara to Athens, which 
took place about four years after the death of Socrates, that is, 
not later than B.c. 395. There can be no doubt that his most 
celebrated works saw the light after this time, and in his native 





1 Cicero, De Finibus, Μ΄. 29. Diog. Laért. VIII. 46. 

3 Phedo,p. 57 A. Cicero (De Finibus, u.s.), and Valerius Maximus (VIII, 
ἡ, ext. 3), consider Echecrates as a teacher of Plato. 

3 Bockh, Philolaos, pp. 18, sqq. 

4 By Ast, Platon's Leben und Schriften, p. 23. 

5 p. 179 E. ὁ Plutarch, De dem. Socr. p. 579 B. 


POLITICAL CHARACTER OF PLATO. 211 


city. According to Cicero he carried on his literary labours 
till the day of his death," and except when interrupted by such 
absences from home as the journeys to Sicily which we have 
enumerated, he was engaged as a public lecturer on philosophy 
- throughout the latter half of his life. His lectures were at first 
delivered in the garden of the Academia, to the north-west of 
Athens, and afterwards in a neighbouring garden between the 
Academia and Colonus which he had purchased; and it has 
been observed, that these gardens ‘have left a proof of their 
celebrity in the structure of language, which has derived from 
them a term now common to all places of instruction”? En- 
gaged in these philosophical and literary pursuits, Plato died at 
the advanced age of eighty-one, in Ol. 108, 1. B.c. 347. He 
was succeeded in his school by his nephew Speusippus, though 
he had left Heracleides of Pontus as his representative at the 
Academy when he took Speusippus with him on his second journey 
to Sicily. Athenzeus* and Plutarch‘ give us counter lists of tyrants 
and good statesmen who received part of their training from 
Plato, and there were few eminent men of the day who are not 
stated to have been among the number of his hearers. 

§ 3. This general survey of the life of Plato would be in- 
complete without some inquiry respecting his political character 
and conduct, which have been made the subject of sharp criti- 
cisms. Niebuhr has said,’ that ‘ Plato may have been pre- 
judiced against his native city, in its constitutional form of 
government, by the warm feelings of his youthful heart, but it 
is not the less true that, if so, he was not a good citizen’ We 
have mentioned in a previous chapter,’ that it was a prominent 
characteristic of the post-Socratic philosophers, to reject the old 
forms of civil polity and to seek an approximation, at least, to 
an aristocracy of talent and knowledge. The state of the case 
in regard to Plato in particular, has been adequately exhibited 
by an eminent English scholar,’ who has compared the state- 





1 De Senectute, c. 5. 2 Butler’s Lectwres, IT., p. 18. 

3 XT. p. 508, sqq. 4 Adv. Colot. p. 1126. 

5 Kleine Schriften, p. 479. Philological Museum, A Ῥ. 494. 

® See chapter XX XVII. § 2. 

7 The Rev. W. H. Thompson, Regius Professor of Greek in the University of 
Cambridge, in his lectures on the Gorgias, delivered in 1854. By the kindness of 
Professor Thompson we have been permitted to quote from his manuscript notes. 

Es 


212 PLATO. 


ments of Plato himself, if he was the writer of the seventh 
Platonic epistle, with the feelings and principles so clearly dis- 
played in the Gorgias and Republic, which, it is with reason 
contended, must have been composed soon after Plato’s first 
return to Athens, in B.c. 395.’ In that elaborate epistle, Plato 
is made to describe the successive disappointments which pre- 
vented him from taking a part in politics; his disgust with the 
oligarchs; his still greater indignation when the leaders of the 
restored democracy procured the condemnation of his friend 
Socrates ; and how at last he arrived at the conviction that all 
existing forms of government were radically wrong; and that 
the crimes and misery of mankind would never come to an end 
until either the highest class of philosophic thinkers should step 
into the seats of power, or until the existing rulers should, by 
some divine miracle, become endued with a true philosophic 
insight.2 The sentiments thus expressed by Plato, or put into 
his mouth, find their echo most especially in the Gorgias and 
Republic ; and while the latter elaborates the theoretical recon- 
struction of the political fabric, the former may be considered 
as an ᾿Απολογία Πλάτωνος, an exposition of his reasons for pre- 
ferring the contemplative to the active, the philosophic to the 
rhetorical life. The manner in which Plato performed the 
duties of citizenship on his first return, his services as a soldier 
in the battles of Tanagra, Corinth, and Delium,’ possibly his 
cultivation of rhetoric, with a view to his appearance as a 
public orator,—all this may have induced his friends to hope 
that he was reconciled to the existing government of Athens, 





1 It appears to us that the description in Resp. 496 B. of the ὑπὸ φυγῆς κατα- 
ληφθὲν γενναῖον καὶ εὖ τεθραμμένον ἦθος κ.τ.λ., is a description of his own case, which 
Plato would hardly have written, except at a period shortly subsequent to his 
return from Megara. ξ 

2 Epist. VII., pp. 324 B., sqq. See especially the end of the paragraph, p. 
326 A. Β, 

8 Diog. Laért. III. 8. lian, V.H., VII. 14. 

4 Professor Thompson remarks: ‘The intimate knowledge which the author of 
the Phedrus displays of the writings of the leaders of both the great schools of 
oratory, the Attic and the Sicilian, may lead to the conjecture that he had at one 
period of his life studied rhetoric with a view to its public practice; and it is hard 
to doubt thai, under moderately favourable circumstances, his success as a speaker 
would have been brilliant.’ 


POLITICAL CONDUCT OF PLATO. 213 


and was willing to take an active part in the administration of 
affairs ;* and no doubt many a well-wisher among the democrats 
gave him warnings, like those which Callicles, in the Gorgias, 
addresses to Socrates.? To show that his dislike of the existing 
constitution was unconquerable, and to justify his abstinence 
from political action, he could not have taken a better method 
than that which is indicated in the supposed conversation with 
the veteran rhetorician of Leontini and his two admirers,— 
whereas the Republic fully developes those views of the neces- 
sity of a philosophical government, founded on the principles of 
eternal justice, which he would hold up to the politicians of 
the day as the best proof of the irreconcilable hostility between 
his views and those on which statesmen of the Callicles type 
professed to act.* That the Gorgias and the Republic may be 
safely referred to the time when Plato, after his first return to 
Athens, had to consider seriously whether he could consistently 
take a part in the public affairs of his own country, has been 
argued on the following grounds: ‘The warning of Callicles, 
and the prophecy of his own death, put into the mouth of 
Socrates,* could not have appeared in a dialogue written before 
B.C. 399, and the reference of the Gorgias exclusively to Athenian 
life leads to the conclusion that it must have been written at 
Athens, and therefore after the writer’s return in B.c. 395. 
Again, the statement in Athenzus,’ that Gorgias himself read 





1 That these ideas on the part of his friends might have been very justifiable is 
clear from his own expressions (Hp. VII. p. 325 A.) in regard to his feelings on 
the re-establishment of the democracy by Thrasybulus : πάλιν βραδύτερον μὲν, εἷλκε 
δέ με ὅμως, ἡ περὶ τὸ πράττειν τὰ κοινὰ Kal τὰ πολιτικὰ ἐπιθυμία. 

2 Gorgias, p. 521 C. 

3 Compare the Republic, VI. pp. 488 sqq. with the passage referred to above, 
p- 212, note 2. 

4 Gorgias, p. 521 D: οὐδέν ye ἄτοπον εἰ ἀποθάνοιμι. The idea of the helplessness 
of the philosopher, when obliged to defend himself in a court of justice, is beauti- 
fully worked up in a well-known passage of the Theetetus (p. 174 B. sqq.), which must 
have been published soon after Plato’s return from Megara, and therefore accord- 
ing to Mr, Thompson’s view, at the same epoch as the Gorgias. He say chat he 
had these views at the time of his first journey to Italy and Sicily: Zp, VII. p. 
326 8. 

5 Athen. XI. p. 505: λέγεται δὲ ὡς καὶ dTopylas αὐτὸς ἀναγνοὺς τὸν ὁμώνυμο 
αὑτῷ διάλογον πρὸς τοὺς συνήθεις ἔφη, Ὥς καλῶς οἷδε Πλάτων ἰαμβίζειν---ἄλλοι δέ 
φασιν ὡς ἀναγνοὺς ὁ Topyias τὸν Πλάτωνος διάλογον πρὸς τοὺς παρόντας εἶπεν ὅτι 
οὐδὲν τούτων οὔτε εἶπεν οὔτε ἤκουσε. 


214 PLATO. 


the dialogue, and the reasonable inference’ that the great rhe- 
torician died shortly before 8.0. 388, oblige us to conclude that 
the dialogue was written before Plato started for Sicily in B.c. 

389, which will fix the date of this treatise approximately for 
some time within the limits of Plato’s first residence at Athens 
after the death of Socrates. With regard to the Republic, if, 
as we have mentioned above, the Ecclesiazuse of Aristophanes, 
with its commonwealth of women, is a satirical attack on 
Plato’s speculation, it will follow that the first sketch, at all 
events, of that long dialogue, was written and known to the 
public before B.c. 392, and this date for the Republic will affect 
that of the Gorgias also. Accordingly, in the first three years 
after his return to Athens, Plato had not only formed for him- 
self, but he had communicated to the world, a determination to 
take no part in the public business at Athens. The principles 
of the literary aristocracy, to which we have referred in a pre- 
vious chapter,’ were carried out by Plato to their fullest extent. 
But finding no probability that these principles would ever take 
root and germinate at Athens, he was content to do his best to 
instil his own convictions into the minds of those, who must 
sooner or later become politicians, and confine his practical 
politics to a share in the legislation of other states, or to an 
attempt to philosophize the minds of the adventurers who had 
made themselves masters of the fairest Greek city in Sicily. 

§ 4. The position which Plato thus assumed, as a writer 
rather than a speaker or practical politician, was in accordance 
with his whole career as a literary man, in the strictest sense 
of the term. He was not only a writer himself, but he was 
one of the earliest collectors of books,’ and was professedly a 
reader and reviewer of the writings of others. We have already 
seen how much pains he had taken to make himself acquainted 
with all existing systems of philosophy. ‘On the death of 
Socrates,’ says Cicero,’ ‘ Plato first went to Egypt to add to 
his stock of knowledge, and afterwards travelled to Italy and 
Sicily in order to learn thoroughly the doctrines of Pythagoras ; 





1 Foss supposes from various data that Gorgias was born about B.c. 496, and 
died about B.c. 388. 

2 Above, chapter XX XVII. § 2 

3 Proclus ὧν Tim. I. p. 28. Diog. VIII. 15. 4 De Republ. I. το. 


LITERARY RELATIONS OF PLATO. 215 


he had a great deal of intercourse with Archytas of Tarentum, 
and with Timzus the Locrian, and procured the commentaries 
of Philolaus; and as Pythagoras then enjoyed a great reputa- 
tion in that part of the world, Plato applied himself to the 
society of Pythagorean philosophers and to the study of their 
system. Accordingly, as he was devotedly attached to Socrates, 
and wished to put everything into his mouth, he interwove the 
elegance and subtlety of the Socratic mode of arguing with the 
obscurity of Pythagoras and the many branches of learning 
which the Pythagorean philosophy included.” This account, 
though containing much that is true, is very far from describing 
the extent and variety of Plato’s studies or the use which he 
made of his acquired knowledge. Of the importance of the 
Socratic and Pythagorean elements in Plato’s philosophy there 
can be no doubt. But he transmuted all that he touched into 
his own forms of thought and language, and there was no branch 
of speculative literature which he had not mastered. LEpi- 
charmus, the great comedian, who was also a renowned Pytha- 
gorean philosopher, was one of his favourite authors, and Plato 
may be said to have fulfilled his prophecy,—that some future 
writer would confute and overthrow all opponents, by adopting 
his sayings and clothing them in a different dress.’ Sophron, 
the mimographer, was constantly in his hand, and he is said to 
have had a copy of the Mimes under his pillow when he died.’ 
He was also familiar with Empedocles,*® who stands half way 
between the Pythagoreans and the Eleatics, and who, as Dr. 
Thirlwall suggests,* may probably be regarded as the predecessor 
of Plato, in his eclectic view of philosophy. Besides these 
Sicilian writers, Plato was thoroughly conversant with all the 





1 Above p. 57, note. That Epicharmus the poet and Epicharmus the philosopher 
were the same person is fully shown by Clinton, Fasti Hellenici II. p. XXXVI. 
note g. Plato sometimes quotes Epicharmus by name, and in one passage (Thecetet. 
152 E.) names him and Homer as the two chief poets, the one of comedy and the 
other of tragedy. 

2 Quintil. Znst. Orat. I. το, ὃ 17. 

3 The doctrines of Empedocles are directly referred to in the Sophistes, p. 242 D. 
G. Hermann recognizes the very words of this philosopher in the Phedrus, p. 246, 
B.C., and has endeavoured to restore them to their original form (Opusec. VII. p. 
106). It is doubtful whether Empedocles or Anaxagoras is alluded to in the Lysis, 
p- 214 B. See Heindorf and Stallbaum on the passage. 

* History of Greece, IL. p. 139, note. 


216 PLATO. 


works of Philolaus, Archytas, Parmenides, Zeno, Heracleitus, 
Anaxagoras, and Protagoras ; whatever was committed to writing 
by the Sophists had come into his hands; he did not neglect 
his own contemporaries of the Socratic school; and many of 
his dialogues may be regarded as reviews or controversial tracts, 
referring to the published opinions of such writers as Aristippus, 
Antisthenes, and Eucleides. It would, however, be a great 
mistake to suppose that because Plato was so actively cognizant 
of the speculations of his predecessors and contemporaries, he has 
therefore forfeited his claim to be considered as a man of ori- 
ginal genius. If this were the case there could be no such 
thing as literary originality. Every man who writes gives an 
expression, under a new form and with new developments, to 
thoughts which have been growing up im the society to which 
hz belongs. Every age leans upon the preceding age, and the 
man of most creative genius can only work with the materials 
committed to him.’ It would be as preposterous to deny the 
originality of Shakspere because his plays derived their plots 
from histories, poems, and novels, as to suppose that Plato 
thought and wrote only at second-hand. We have only to com- 
pare the dialogues of Plato with the tame appearances of 
Socrates in the Memoirs of Xenophon, if we wish to see how 
much is due to the dramatic power, poetic fancy, analytical 
skill, and exhaustive learning of the former. Fully conceding 
the postulate, that Socrates first awakened the idea of science, 
and laid the foundations of dialectics, on which a main part of 
the philosophy of Plato was built up,’ and recognizing the im- 
portance of the great ideas which Plato had learned from the 
Eleatics, the Heracleiteans, and the Pythagoreans, we must still 
claim for him the master-mind which extracted from all these 
systems their common truths, rejected their specific errors, and 
from the whole elaborated and expounded, in the finest language 
ever spoken by man, the great theory of the opposition between 
the law and the facts, between the general and the particular, 
between the objects of reflexion and the objects of the senses, 





1 Arstne Houssaye has well remarked: ‘le plus souvent le génie n’est qu'un 
écho bien disposé.’ 
2 See this distinctly stated by Aristotle, Metaph. XII. 4, § 5. 


THE DIALOGUES. _ 217 


between the world of abstract thought and the world of visible 
phenomena. 

§ 5. With the exception of the epistles, if any of these are 
genuine, and the philosophical definitions, which are undoubt- 
edly spurious, all the extant writings of Plato are in the form 
of dialogues, and in all these dialogues, with the exception of 
the Laws, Socrates is either an interlocutor, or in some way 
interested in the conversation. In this species of composition 
Plato was preceded by Alexamenus of Teos, and perhaps by 
Epicharmus, Zeno of Elea, and others.’ Aristotle says:’ ‘ We 
cannot deny the name of discourses and imitations to the 
mimes of Sophron and the dialogues of Alexamenus of Teos, 
which were the first written of the Socratic dialogues.’ With 
regard to Zeno, we have the more doubtful statement of Dio- 
genes:* ‘they say that Zeno of Elea was the first to write 
dialogues ; and a mere inference from Aristotle’s description of 
‘the answering and questioning Zeno.’* Whatever may have 
been the force of precedent, there can be no doubt that Plato 
was led to employ the form of dialogues from the nature of the 
case. The mere fact that he adopted the dialectics of Socrates 
and the Eleatics is sufficient to account for his exhibiting his 
reasonings in accordance with that method of questioning by 
which his great teacher and the school of Parmenides had 
tested the doctrines and opinions of those with whom they came 
into contact. A professor of dialectics was, by the nature of the 
case, a professor of conversation ; the verb διαλέγεσθαι means 
simply ‘ to converse,’ and the common word to denote conversa- 
tion, namely, διάλεξις, is used by Aristophanes to denote 





1 The following writers of dialogues were contemporary with Plato: Aischines, 
Antisthenes, Eucleides, and Phedo. 

3 Athenzus XI. p. 505 B.: αὐτὸς (Πλάτων) τοὺς διαλόγους μιμητικῶς γράψας, ὧν 
τῆς ἰδέας οὐδ᾽ αὐτὸς εὑρετής ἐστιν. πρὸ γὰρ αὐτοῦ τοῦθ᾽ εὗρε τὸ εἶδος ὁ ΤΤήϊος ᾿Αλεξα- 
μενός, ὡς Νικίας ὁ Νικαεὺς ἱστορεῖ περὶ Σωτίων. ᾿Αριστοτέλης δὲ ἐν τῷ περὶ ποιητῶν 
οὕτως γράφει" “ οὐκοῦν οὐδὲ ἐμμέτρους τοὺς καλουμένους Σ ώφρονος Μίμους μὴ φῶμεν 
εἶναι λόγους καὶ μιμήσεις, ἢ τοὺς ᾿Αλεξαμενοῦ τοῦ Τηΐου τοὺς πρώτους γραφέντας 
τῶν Σωκρατικῶν διαλόγων.᾽ Where Bergk reads τοὺς πρότερον. On the general sub- 
ject see Brandis, in Niebuhr’s Rhein Mus. I. 120. 

8 TIL. 47, p. 215 A. Casaub. : διαλόγους τοίνυν φασὶ πρῶτον γράψαι Ζήνωνα τὸν 
᾿Ελεάτην. 

4 Sophist. Elench. c. 20, § 2: ὁ ἀποκρινόμενος καὶ ὁ ἐρωτῶν Ζήνων. 


218 PLATO. 


‘dialectics’ or ‘logic’! The definition by -which Socrates, 
according to Xenophon, reduces διαλέγεσθαι to its active form, 
and supposes it to mean the apa or subdivision of things 
according to their genera and species,’ is, of course, one of those 
plays upon words which merely indicate the non-existence of 
philological criticism among the Greeks. To examine and 
cross-examine appeared to Socrates the only means of arriving 
at the truth or confuting error, and to keep close to the ques- 
tion was in the strictest sense of the term ‘ to argue διαλεκτικῶς.᾽3 
The convenience of this method for an object such as that 
which Plato proposed to himself is obvious.’ Wishing to review 
and criticize the various systems of philosophy then current in 
Greece, and also to test various opinions of political or social 
import, no better plan could have occurred to him than that of 
supposing their authors and advocates to meet with Socrates in 
the course of his daily life at Athens, and submit their views, 
with the best arguments which had been advanced in support of 
them, to his searching elenchus. In this way, Plato, as the 
anonymous reviewer, was enabled to substitute the well-known 
person of Socrates for the conventional ‘we’ of our modern 
critics, and instead of extracts from the works under review, 
with inverted commas and other marks of quotation, which, in 
this age of writing and printing, are expedients as convenient as 
they are universal, he produced the living forms of the authors 
themselves, or of some friendly Theodorus,’ who had said, or 
was likely to say, a good word on their behalf. In this way, 





1 Nub. 317: αἵπερ γνώμην καὶ διάλεξιν καὶ νοῦν ἡμῖν παρέχουσιν. 
2 Mem. IV. 5, § 12: ἔφη δὲ καὶ τὸ διαλέγεσθαι ὀνομασθῆναι ἐκ τοῦ συνιόντας — 
κοινῇ βουλεύεσθαι διαλέγοντας κατὰ γένη τὰ πράγματα. 
3 The words of Hudibras (I. 3, 1255 544.} accurately describe the dialecticprocess 
‘ The quirks and cavils thou dost make 
Are false and built upon mistake. 
And I shall bring you with your pack 
Of fallacies to elenchi back ; 
And put your arguments in mood 
And figure to be understood. 
ΤΊ] force you: by right ratiocination 
To leave your vitilitigation, 
And make you keep to the question close, 
And argue dialecticws.’ 
4 There is a modern justification of Plato’s method in Mr. Kingsley’s Phaethon, 
2nd Edition, Cambridge, 1854. 
5 Who undertakes the defence of Protagoras in the Theetet us. 


ORDER OF PLATO’S WORKS. 219 


too, Plato was able to gratify his own dramatic genius, and his 
almost unrivalled power of keeping up an assumed character, 
a power in which Shakspere alone can claim to be his equal. 
The natural bent of a man, who transcribed Epicharmus' and 
kept Sophron under his pillow,’ must have been strongly 
towards this habit of impersonation, to say nothing of the 
pleasure of doing that which we do easily and well; and if this 
had not been the case, it would be difficult to show what other 
method of controversy and literary or philosophical criticism 
would have been available to him in an age when he stood 
almost alone as a collector and possessor of books written by 
his contemporaries. 

§ 6. The chronological order of Plato’s works, and their 
arrangement according to the subject matter, have occasioned a 
good deal of discussion. There is another question connected 
with this, namely, whether any and how many of the dialogues 
attributed to him are not genuine. With regard to this latter 
question, which must precede any inquiry as to the order of the 
dialogues which really proceeded from Plato, we feel disposed 
to agree with those who grant the critical passport to all but 
certain of the minor works. The following will be either 
received with doubt or rejected without hesitation ; the Axiochus 
and Eryxias (sometimes attributed to the Socratic philosopher, 
Aischines), the Epinomis (probably written by Philip of Opus), 
the first and second Alcibiades (the latter attributed to Xeno- 
phon), the first and second Hippias, the Theages, Ion, Anteraste, 
Hipparchus, Minos, Cleitopho. On the other hand, we must 
maintain, against Ast, the genuineness of the Laws, the Meno, 
Euthydemus, Charmides, Lysis, Laches, Menexenus, Euthyphro, 
Apology, and Crito. And we cannot consent even to enter 
upon an argument with Socher as to the genuineness of the Par- 
menides, Sophistes, and Politicus, which seem to us as undoubt- 
edly Platonic as the Theetetus, or the Philebus.6 The earliest 





1 Alcimus quoted by Diogenes (III. 18) says that Plato transcribed most of the 
writings of Epicharmus. 2 Quintil. Znst. Orat. I. 10, § 17. 

3 Socher, iiber Platon’s Schriften, Miinchen, 1820. These views have been partly 
adopted or supported by Dr. Whewell in some interesting papers read before the 
Cambridge Philosophical Society (Transactions, vol. IX. pt. 4, vol. X.p. 1). As 
far as the Sophistes and Politicus are concerned, the question has been set at rest 
by Professor Thompson in the elaborate is Sel to which we have already referred : 
above, p. 175. 


220 PLATO. 


methodical arrangement of Plato’s dialectics is that of the 
Tetralogies drawn up by Thrasyllus, a grammarian, who flou- 
rished in the time of Tiberius.’ Of these nine Tetralogies there 
are only three which are partially accurate in classification. 
Thrasyllus could not avoid putting together the Theetetus, 
Sophistes, and Politicus, but he spoils the connexion by prefix- 
ing the Cratylus, instead of appending the Parmenides. With 
similar want of judgment he makes the Cleitopho a preface to 
the Republic, Timeus, and Critias, which are really connected. 
There is a possible coherence in the Parmenides, Philebus, 
Symposium, and Phedrus, which constitute his third class; but 
this arrangement will not bear examination. In modern times 
the most important classification of the dialogues is that which 
was drawn up by the great philosophical theologian Schleier- 
macher, who was the first to submit the whole of Plato’s works 
to an acute and careful examination in regard to their coherency 
and the connexion of thought which runs through them. He 
divides them into three classes: (A) the elementary dialogues, 
or those which contain the germs of all that follows, of logic as 
the instrument of philosophy, and of ideas as its proper object ; 
these are the Phedrus, Lysis, Protagoras, Laches, Charmides, 
Euthyphro, and Parmenides ; to which Schleiermacher subjoins, 
as an appendix, the Apology, Crito, Io, Hippias minor, Hip- 
parchus, Minos, and Alcibiades II. (B) Progressive dialogues, 
which treat of the distinction between philosophical and common 
knowledge in their united application to the proposed and real 
sciences, ethics, and physics; these are the Gorgias, Theetetus, 
Meno, Euthydemus, Cratylus, Sophistes, Politicus, Symposium, 
Phedo, and Philebus ; with an appendix containing the Theages, 
Eraste, Alcibiades I., Menexenus, Hippias major, and Cleitopho. 
(C) Constructive dialogues, in which the practical is completely 
united with the speculative; these are the Republic, Timeus, 
and Critias, with an appendix containing the Laws, the Epistles, 





1 The following are the Tetralogies of Thrasyllus as given by Diogenes Laértius, 
II. 56, p.221, Casaubon. I. Luthyphro, Apologia, Crito, Phedo. Τ1, Cratylus, 
Thectetus, Sophista, Politicus. III. Parmenides, Philebus, Symposium, Phedrus. 
IV. Alcibiades prior, Alcibiades alter, Hipparchus, Anteraste. V. Theages, 
Charmides, Laches, Lysis. Vi. Euthydemus, Protagoras, Gorgias, Meno. VII. 
Hippias major, Hippias minor, Io, Menexenus. VIII. Cleitopho, Respublica, 
Timeus, Critias. IX. Minos, Leges, Epinomis, Epistole. 


ORDER OF PLATO’S WORKS. 221 


&c. Without entering upon a criticism of this arrangement, 
which is, as we conceive, in accordance neither with the chrono- 
logical order of the dialogues, nor with the main divisions of 
the subjects discussed in them; we will endeavour briefly to 
ascertain the periods in Plato’s life at which the principal 
dialogues were written, and the literary connexion of the more 
important treatises with one another.’ 

It seems to us extremely unlikely that many works were 
published by Plato during the lifetime of Socrates, or that he 
composed at this time any of the more elaborate dialogues. It 
has indeed been very generally assumed that the Phedrus ap- 
peared at this epoch, and was in fact the first of his works. 
We are much more disposed to accept the conclusion of 
C. F. Hermann,’ that this dialogue belongs to the final period 
in Plato’s literary career. Some of the reasons for this view 
have been briefly summed up by an English scholar. They are 
—(1) its Pythagorism ; (2) the multifarious learning displayed 
in it—a learning of which there are few traces in his youthful 





1 The most recent hypothesis with regard to the arrangement of Plato’s dialogues 
is that of E. Munk (Die natiirliche ordnung der Platon. Schriften, Berlin, 1857), 
who conceives that their natural order is that which is indicated by the age of 
Socrates at the time when each conversation is supposed to have taken place: 
thus the Parmenides is the first, because it introduces Socrates as a boy, and the 
Phedo is the last, because it represents the closing scene in the philosopher’s life! 
The following are his subdivisions :— 

A. Socratic Cycle I. Socrates’ initiation as a philosopher, and his contests with 
false wisdom (time of composition, 389—384). 

1. Parmenides (time of action, 446). 2. Protagoras (434). 3. Charmides (432), 
and Laches (421). 4. Gorgias (420). 5. lon, Hippias I., Cratylus, Euthydemus, 
(420). 6. Symposium (417). 

II. Socrates teaches the true wisdom (time of composition, 383—370). 

1. Phedrus ; 2. Philebus; 3. Republic, Timeus and Critias (410). 

III. Socrates proves the truth of his doctrines by a criticism of the antagonistic 
opinions and by his death as a martyr (composed after 370). 

1. Meno (405); 2. Thecetetus (on the day of Meletus’s accusation) ; 3. Sophis- 
tes and Politicus (one day after the Thectetus) ; 4. Huthyphro (on the same day as 
the Theetetus) ; 5. Apology (at the trial) ; 6. Crito (two days before the death of 
Socrates) ; 7. Phedo (on the day of his death). 

B. Platonic writings which do not belong to the Cycle. I. Juvenile Writings 
(composed before the death of Socrates). 1. Alcibiades J.; 2. Lysis; 3. Hip- 
pias II. 

Il. Later Writings. 1. Menexenus (after 387) ; 2. Laws (begun about 367). 

3 Platon. Philosophie, pp. 373 564. 

8 Professor Thompson, note on Butler’s Lectwres, II. p. 44. 


222 PLATO. 


works ; (3) the maturity of its ethical views, contrasted with 
the Socratic crudity of the Lysis, Protagoras, &c.; (4) the 
clear exposition of the principles of philosophical method, and 
the advanced views of the nature of ideas implied in the great 
mythus; (5) the exquisite perfection of the Phedrus as a work 
of literary art. The tradition, which assigns an early date to 
the Phedrus, is possibly due to the fact that it was the first 
book published by Plato, when he finally established himself as 
a teacher in the Academy. The favourable notice of Isocrates," 
and the criticisms on Lysias,’ need occasion no difficulty. He 
-may have entertained a higher opinion of the former than he 
did when he wrote the Euthydemus, if the description of the 
conceited rhetorician in that dialogue really refers to Isocrates ; * 
and the importance attached to Lysias would be most appli- 
cable to the time, when that orator enjoyed the Panhellenic 
reputation consequent on his Olympiac speech. Now this was 
in B.c. 388, just about the time when Plato, being ransomed 
from his bondage, set up his school at Athens, and when Iso- 
crates was in great repute. If any one of the extant dialogues 
can claim to be really the first written, the Lysis is perhaps 
the best entitled to this primogeniture. For there is not only 
a distinct tradition to this effect,’ but the style and subject- 
matter bear a stamp of juvenility and unpractised authorship. 
Closely connected with this we have the Charmides and the 
Laches ; and other short dialogues, if they are genuine, belong 
to the same epoch ; such are the Hippias major, the Alcibiades I., 
and the Jo. After these, and perhaps shortly before the time 
of the death of Socrates, we have two transition dialogues, in 
which the Sophists are so fully exhibited, namely, the Proéa- 





1 Phedrus, p. 279 A. 2 Thid. p. 234 D. sqq. 

3 Euthydemus, p. 304 D.: ἀνὴρ οἰόμενος πάνυ εἶναι σοφός, τούτων Tis τῶν περὶ τοὺς 
λόγους τοὺς εἰς τὰ δικαστήρια δεινῶν. When Plato wrote the Protagoras and 
Euthydemus, it seems to have been his wish to contrast Socrates with those sophists, 
and he might therefore take a less favourable view of Isocrates on that account, for 
this rhetorician was a pupil of Protagoras. 

4 Clinton, Fasti Hellenici, II. p. τοι. Mr. Grote (vol. X. p. ror) supposes that 
the Olympiacus of Lysias and the Panegyricus of Isocrates were delivered at suc- 
cessive Olympic festivals in B.c. 384 and 380 respectively. 

5 Diog. Laért. ITT. 35: φασὶ δὲ καὶ Σωκράτην ἀκούσαντα τὸν Λύσιν ἀναγιγνώσκοντος 
Πλάτωνος, Ἡρακλεῖς, εἰπεῖν, ὡς πολλά μου καταψεύδεται ὁ νεανίσκος. 


ORDER OF PLATO’S WORKS. 223 


goras and Euthydemus.' While he was at Megara, and very 
soon after the death of Socrates, he probably published and 
sent to Athens the Apology and the Crifo.2 When he returned 
to Athens in B.c. 395, we conceive, for the reasons which we 
have quoted from Professor Thompson, that he wrote the 
Gorgias, and the first edition of the Republic. Being also fresh 
from his instructive intercourse with Eucleides at Megara, he 
most probably published at this time also the trilogy of 
dialogues which are supposed to be narrated at that philosopher’s 
‘house—namely, the Theetetus, the Sophistes, and the Politicus— 
and are stated to have taken place at the time when Socrates 
was indicted by Meletus.* The battle of Corinth, mentioned at 
the beginning of the Theetetus, must have been that in which 
Plato took a part, in the year of his return to Athens, B.c. 395 ;* 





1 Stallbaum seems to have shown satisfactorily that the Zuthydemus must have 
been written about the beginning of Ol. 94, 1.6. about B.0. 404. Its object is 
evidently the same as that of the Protagoras, namely, to mark the essential dis- 
tinction between the principles and conduct of Socrates and those of the Sophists, 
with whom he was so often confounded. To the assumption of a corresponding 
date for the Protagoras the chief objection, which occurs to the reader, is the 
resemblance between this dialogue and the Symposiwm, which all are agreed in 
regarding as one of Plato’s most matured works. Both of these dialogues introduce 
Eryximachus and his friend Phedrus, Agatho and his admirer Pausanias, Alcibiades 
and his relations to Socrates, with remarks of a very similar kind, and there are 
unmistakeable resemblances of style_and allusion, as, for instance, in the reference 
to the same line of Homer (Protagoras, 348 D., Symp. 174 D.). But the purport 
of the two dialogues and the indications of a more mature and thoroughly Platonic 
philosophy in the latter, must lead us to seek for the natural explanation of these 
resemblances in that tendency to reproduction which is common to all authors. 
The introduction of Critias in the Protagoras and Charmides need create no dif- 
ficulty. If they were composed after the death of the tyrannical oligarch, the 
amnesty was so faithfully observed by the democratical party that no mischief could 
aecrue to Plato from such an allusion to his relatives. 

2 This may be inferred from the natural wish of Plato, who was prevented from 
defending Socrates at his trial, to send to Athens a written vindication of his 
master, and an account of his noble unwillingness to evade the sentence of the 
court. 

3 In the introduction to the Theetetus, Eucleides is led by the mention of that 
brave young philosopher, who had been wounded in the battle of Corinth, to read 
to his friend Terpsion a written report of the imaginary conversations in which 
Theetetus took a part, and at the end of the first dialogue Socrates says that 
Meletus had indicted him. 

4 For the battle of Corinth see Grote, IX. p. 425. We know nothing about the 
battles of Tanagra and Delium at which Plato fought ; probably, as Clinton suggests, 
they took place in the Corinthian or Theban war. 


224 PLATO. 


and there can be little doubt that these dialogues were written 
shortly after that event. A fourth dialogue, which is unmis- 
takeably referred to' in the three supposed to have been detailed 
at Megara, and which is manifestly connected with them in 
subject, is the Parmenides, which is supposed to have been held 
in the younger days of Socrates, but is reallya Platonic review of 
the Eleatic system considered in its connexion with the Megaric. 
In this class, too, we must include the dialogue which gets its 
name from his first teacher, the Heracleitean Cratylus. When 
Plato returned from his first peregrmation and the bondage 
which. concluded it, and established himself as a public teacher 
in the neighbourhood of Colonus, he seems to have published 
the Phedrus, as an introductory treatise, followed by the — 
Menexenus, in direct rivalry of Lysias, whom he had criticized 
in that previous dialogue ; and at intervals after this he must 
have given to the world his Symposium, which treats, like the 
Phedrus, of love, his Phedo, which discusses the immortality of 
the soul, not without reference to the doctrine of transmigration, 
so clearly stated in the Phedrus, the Philebus, which argues the 
moral question in a Pythagorean spirit, perhaps the Meno, with 
its theory of reminiscences,’ and certainly the second or com- 
plete edition of the Republic, with its full development of all 
these ideas, and its substitution of the three classes in the State 
for the charioteer and horses of the Phedrus, as a representa- 
tion of the tripartite division of the soul. This last was followed, 





1 The Parmenides is distinctly alluded to in the Thectetus, p. 180 E., and it is 
inferred from the Sophistes, p. 217 C., 253 E., 254 B., and from the Politicus, p. 
257.A.B., that the Parmenides was the sequel of the two latter under the title of 
the Philosophus. 

2 Both C. F. Hermann and Stallbaum are inclined to class the Meno with the 
earlier dialogues. The latter, adopting the views of Socher, thinks that Plato 
would not have dealt so gently with Anytus, if he had written this dialogue after 
his teacher’s death, but sees in it indications of ill-will between Anytus and Socrates. 
Accordingly he places the dialogue about the middle of the 94th Olympiad. But 
this argument would only apply to the supposition that the Meno was written 
while the Socratic school entertained a fresh recollection of the part which Anytus 
had played, and there would be no more difficulty in a calm exposure of Anytus 
many years afterwards than in making Aristophanes and Socrates hoon companions 
at the same feast. The reference to Ismenias, p. go A., places the dialogue after 
Ol. 96, 1., B.c. 396 (Cf. Xen. Hell. III. 5, § 1.); and the doctrine of reminiscences 
is too Pythagorean to allow us to separate the Meno from the Phedrus, 


ORDER OF.PLATO’S WORKS. 225 


probably after an interval, by the Timeus and Critias. And 
the Laws were undoubtedly written after his last return from 
Sicily, and when he had changed the general method of his 
teaching and writing. Notwithstanding the differences of style 
and the anacolutha or grammatical inconsequences which are found 
in the Laws, to an extent of which we have no example in the 
other works of Plato, the non-introduction of Socrates, and the 
discrepancies in detail between the Laws and the Republic, we 
entertain a perfect conviction that we have here a genuine work 
of Plato. The faults of the style may be explained by the fact 
that the Laws had not received the last touches of the author’s 
pen; for Philippus of Opus is said to have transcribed the work 
from the waxen tablets (ἐν κήροις)" and to have copied it out. 
With regard to the non-introduction of Socrates, this is surely 
a peculiarity which the author was at liberty to adopt if he 
pleased. What would have been said if it had not been in the 
form of a dialogue at all? The discrepancies in details between 
the Laws and the Republic are explained by the different 
purport of the two treatises. The author himself tells us that 
the former is not intended to represent a perfect state, but 
merely one that is relatively perfect ; and the discrepancies do 
not affect any leading principles in Plato’s ethical system. But 
even if the objections were of much more weight than they 
seem to be, they would be overthrown by Aristotle’s direct and 
positive testimony to the genuineness of the work.’ 

It does not appear that Plato made any formal division of his 
writings according to their subject-matter. Generally it may be 
said that they represent the dialectics and ethics, to which So- 
crates confined his attention, and in a less elaborate form, the 
physical philosophy of the older speculators, This tripartition 
of philosophy was recognized in Plato’s time, and is said to have 
been expressly adopted by Aristotle, Xenocrates, and the Stoics,° 





_ 1 Diog. Laert. ITI. 25, who also mentions that this Opuntian disciple of Plato 
was the author of the Zpinomis attributed to his great master. 

2 Polit. 11. 6, ὃ τ. 

3 Sextus Empiricus, adv. Mathem. VII. 16: ἐντελέστερον δὲ παρὰ τούτους οἱ 
εἰπόντες τῆς φιλοσοφίας τὸ μέν τι εἶναι φυσικόν, τὸ δὲ ἠθικόν, τὸ δὲ λογικόν. ὧν δυνάμει 
μὲν Πλάτων ἐστὶν ἀρχηγός, περὶ πολλῶν μὲν φυσικῶν, περὶ πολλῶν δὲ ἠθικῶν, οὐκ ὀλίγων 
δὲ λογικῶν διαλεχθείς᾽ ῥητότατα δὲ οἱ περὶ τὸν Revoxpdry καὶ οἱ ἀπὸ τοῦ Περιπάτου, ἔτι 
δὲ οἱ ἀπὸ τῆς Στοᾶς ἔχονται τῆσδε τῆς διαιρέσεως. 


Voz. II. Q 


226 PLATO. 


but Cicero tells us that it was contemplated also by Plato,’ and 
it may be discerned in his dialogues as we have them. In 
accepting, however, this formally-scientific classification of 
Plato’s dialogues, we shall be obliged to exclude all those which 
were written before his return to Athens in B.c. 395, for none 
of these can be considered as contributing directly to the de- 
velopment of Plato’s system. They are rather examples of his 
dramatic genius and dialectic skill applied to the exhibition of the 
views peculiar to Socrates, or they are intended as justifications 
of that philosopher, giving a favourable representation both of 
his method and of the ethical principles which he adopted, and 
contrasting him, in both respects, with the Sophists, in opposition 
to the common prejudice at Athens, that he was only a Sophist 
himself? If we take even the most elaborate of these early 
dialogues, the Protagoras, and compare it with any one of those 
which he published after his return from Megara, even the 
Gorgias, which is the least scientific of that group, we shall see 
that the former is entirely Socratic, while the latter uses the 
person of Socrates merely to justify the opinions of Plato. It has 
been well remarked by an English scholar, who is an authority 
in all that relates to this subject,’ that ‘the speech of Callicles in 
the Gorgias is throughout more applicable to the circumstances 
of a comparatively young man, who, like Plato, on his first re- 
turn to Athens, had his profession to choose, than to an elderly 
and inveterate dialectician, such as Socrates must have been 
considered at the time,.when this conversation is supposed to 
take place ; that no reader of Plato need be at a loss for parallel 
instances, in which the contemporaries of Plato would recognize 
the author under the mask of his hero, or in which the opinions 
of the parties and personages of his own time are antedated by 
some twenty or thirty years; and that certainly no Callicles, 
however well-intentioned, or however sanguine, could have 
hoped to win over Socrates to a profession for which he was so 
ludicrously disqualified by the absence of every one of those 
gifts of nature which are commonly regarded as essential to 





1 Acad. Post. I. 5, ὃ το. 

2 Above, Chapter XXXVII., § 1. Ken. Mem. I. 6, § 15, I. 2, § 49, qq. 

3 We quote from Professor RE MS. Lecture on the Gorgias, to which 
we have been permitted to refer. 


ORDER OF PLATO’S WORKS. 227 


success in public life, whereas Plato had already given indi- 
cations of an intention of taking that part in the public de- 
liberations which he declined to assume, for reasons adequately 
explained in the Gorgias and Republic’ In the Protagoras, on 
the other hand, we have Socrates, as he was, opposed to a group 
of the most eminent Sophists, who are drawn from the life, with 
all the accuracy of a photograph, and exhibiting not only a most 
favourable specimen of his peculiar dialectics, but also arguing 
for that identification of virtue with knowledge which we have 
seen’ was the special characteristic of his moral philosophy. 
_The compliment to Socrates, and the prediction of his future 
eminence, with which Protagoras concludes the dialogue, seem 
to us to intimate very clearly that in this dialogue it was the 
object of the zealous disciple to meet a growing prejudice 
against his master, and to induce the Athenians to recognize 
his present usefulness and future eminence. Protagoras is 
made to say:? ‘For my part, Socrates, 1 commend your zeal, 
and your skill in developing an argument; and I have often 
said of you, that of all who fall in my way, I admire you most, 
certainly by far the most of those of your standing, and that I 
should not be surprised if you were to gain a place among dis- 
tinguished philosophers.’ 

Omitting then, for these and the like reasons, all the dia- 
logues, which were probably written before B.c. 395, we shall 
get the following general results for a scientific classification and 
subdivision of the genuine works of Plato. We may fairly con- 
clude that Plato’s first object, in developing his own peculiar 
views, would be to vindicate the principles of moral and political 
speculation, which led him to the conclusion that no state could 
really succeed until the rulers became philosophical, or philoso- 
phers were placed in the seats of power. In thus maintaining 
the importance of philosophy, he prepared the way for a dis- 

cussion of those theories on which, as he thought, mental and 
moral philosophy depend. Accordingly, we infer that he began 
his systematic works by publishing the Gorgias and the first 
sketch of the Republic? These works were not only his prope- 





1 Above, Chapter XXXVII. ὃ 3. 2 Protagoras, p. 361 D. 
3 It is too generally forgotten, in histories of ancient literature, that, in the case 
of long-lived and prolific authors, the works which we have are very often trans- 


Q2 


228 PLATO. 


deutic, or inaugural discourses, but also his means of setting him- 
self right’ with those of his fellow-citizens who claimed from him 
a more direct participation in their own every-day affairs. After 
these he would naturally publish the dialectical reviews from 
the Theetetus to the Parmenides, in which the principles of 
abstract reasoning are controversially established. These are 
emphatically the dialectical treatises, though the results appear 
also in the later dialogues. Making a new start with the Phe- 
drus, on opening his school after his release from bondage, he 
reverts to the moral principles urged in the Gorgias and Re- 
public, and discusses the philosophy of rhetoric with direct 
reference to his most eminent contemporaries, Lysias and 
Isocrates ;? and in a series of dialogues, terminating with a 
revised and completed edition of the Republic, he blends together 
his dialectical and moral principles, and gives us adaptations of 
that Pythagorism with which he had made more accurate ac- 
quaintance at Tarentum. These dialogues then, with the later 
treatise on the Laws, represent generally the ethical system of 
Plato. In the Phedo he had glanced at the bearing of these 
questions on natural philosophy, and the play with numbers in 
the Republic had reference as much to the physical as to the 
political theories of the Pythagoreans ; but he has given a formal 
development of his views on these matters in the Timeus, which 
may therefore be regarded as a sample of Plato’s physical phi- 
losophy. According to this subdivision, we will now examine 
the general results of his system. 

§ 7. The dialogues, in which Plato discusses more particularly 
the science of dialectics, are a series of reviews representing, 
partly by way of example, the faults of the counter-systems of 





mitted to us in a revised or improved form, even if they are not entirely remodelled. 
Among Plato’s dialogues, we see this most clearly in the Republic and the Parme- 
nides, the latter of which is probably a new and separate edition of the treatise ‘on 
the philosopher,’ which is the promised sequel to the Sophéstes and the Politicus. 

1 In the German phrase, Plato orientirte sich in the Gorgias and the first sketch 
of the Republic ; See Classical Schol. and Learning, p. 215. 

2 Leonard Spengel, in an elaborate paper on Aristotle’s Rhetoric (Munich Trans- 
actions VI., 1852, pp. 465, sqq.), shows that the Phedrus gives Plato’s views on 
scientific rhetoric; that Aristotle was immediately indebted to Plato’s exposition. 
on this subject; and that in his Rhet. 11, 1—17, his πάθη καὶ ἤθη are a direct refe- 
rence to Plato’s ψυχαγωγία, 


DIALECTICS. 229 


Parmenides, as developed in the Megaric school, and of Hera- 
cleitus, as Plato had learned these opinions from Cratylus, and 
perhaps also studied them at Ephesus.’ The opposition between 
these two systems consisted, as is well known, in their anta- 
gonistic theories respecting the law and the facts, the in- 
telligible and the sensible, the form and the matter, the idea 
and the phenomenon, the one and the many, the permanent and 
the variable, that which is (ἔστι), and that which becomes, is 
produced, or comes into being (γίγνεται. The Eleatics of the 
school of Parmenides, and after them the Megarics of the school 
of Eucleides, rested on the formule (1) that all is one, and that 
there is no multiplicity or multeity of things; (2) that all is 
one immutable being, and that there is no becoming (γένεσις), 
no change, no alteration, augmentation and decay. According 
to the Eleatics, the outward world of sense only seemed to be— 
it had-no real existence. Parmenides himself declared in his 
high-sounding verses : ‘ Nothing except Being either is or will 
be ; for fate has fixed this at least—that the name ¢o Be belongs, 
alone and unchangeable, to the All, in regard to whatever mor- 
tals, in their confidence that such things are true, have set down 
as coming into existence and perishing, as being and yet not being, 
as undergoing change of place or change of aspect.’ To this 
Unitarian doctrine of Being was directly opposed that of the 
Ionian school of Heracleitus, which asserted that there is no 
unity, no being, no permanence; that all is plurality, coming 
into being (γένεσις), and fluctuation. This doctrine, modified 
into the dogma of Protagoras, that ‘the individual man is the 
standard of all things’ (πάντων μέτρον ἄνθρωπος), amounted to 
an assertion that all knowledge is sensation, that there are no 
realities in the world except those which meet us in the changing 
objects around us, and that even the names of things are as ab- 
solutely true as the objects which they are supposed to denote.’ 





1 See the expressions in Theetetus, p. 179 E. 
3 Simplicius, ad Aristot. Phys. I. p. 31. 
ἐπεὶ τό γε Moip’ ἐπέδησεν 

οἷον ἀκίνητόν τ᾽ ἐμέναι τῷ ΤΠάντ᾽ ὄνομ᾽ ᾿Εστί 
ὅσσα βροτοὶ κατέθεντο πεποιθότες εἶναι ἀληθῆ, 
γιγνεσθαΐ τε καὶ ὄλλυσθαι, εἶναί τε καὶ οὐχί, 
καὶ τόπον ἀλλάσσειν διά τε χρόα φανὸν ἀμείβειν. 

3 Plato, Theetet. p. 151 E. 544. 


230 PLATO. 


Briefly stated, the Eleatic doctrine was that the formula for the 
universal is one only; that of the Heracleiteans was that the 
universe can be regarded only as many. 

Plato, perceiving that neither of these propositions was €X- 
clusively true, but that there was truth in each of them; that 
the Eleatics were wrong in annihilating the sensible world, and 
so depriving science of its materials, and the Heracleiteans 
equally wrong in denying the intelligible world, and so depriving 
science of its form; that philosophy was neither confined with 
the former to a problem of logic, nor with the latter to a regis- 
tration of phenomena ;—Plato, being convinced of this, adopted 
as the symbol of his own system the following comprehensive 
proposition—that the formula for the universal is neither one 
only, nor many only, but one and many (ἕν καὶ πολλά), ὃ. é., the 
subject of which many predicates may be asserted, and which 
therefore appears as manifold.’ According to this view, the one 
and the many are terms which do not exclude, but rather pre- 
suppose one another ; the one is many and the many one, for 
the general idea may be analyzed and divided into its sub- 
ordinate ideas, the genus into its species, the one into the 
many; and conversely, we may ascend from the individual to 
the species, and the species to the genus, from the many to the 
one.” Thus we see that Plato’s system, as distinguished from 
‘that of the two schools which he undertook to criticize, rests 
upon a proper conception of that which Leibnitz called ‘ the 
definition real.”* The definition, as Socrates too had seen, con- 
sists in generalization and division, i. ¢., it is made per genus et 
differentiam ;* and to reason scientifically, it is necessary that we 
should be able to generalize and classify (κατ᾽ εἴδη σκοπεῖν and 
κατὰ γένος διακρίνειν). Science then depends on dialectics, 
dialectics on the definition real, and the definition real on this 





1 See Phileb. p. 14 C. sqq., and Sydenham’s note 51, pp. 86, sqq. Cf. Republ. V. 
p- 476 A. Sophist. p. 251 A. Parmenid. p. 129 E. 

2 This is what is meant by the συναγωγὴ and διαίρεσις mentioned in the 
Phedrus, p. 265. 

3 Nowveauc Essais sur V Entendement humain, Liv. III. Chap, III. pp. 252, sqq. 

4 Phedrus, p. 249 Β. : δεῖ yap ἄνθρωπον ξυνιέναι κατ᾽ εἶδος λεγόμενον ἐκ πολλῶν 
lov αἰσθήσεων εἰς Ev λογισμῷ ξυναιρούμενον. Cf. ibid, 273 E., where the phrase is 
κατ᾽ εἴδη τε διαιρεῖσθαι τὰ ὄντα καὶ μιᾷ ἰδεᾷ καθ᾽ ἕν ἕκαστον περιλαμβάνειν. 


ὅ Sophist. p. 253, 3 D.E. Phileb. p. 25 Β. βᾳᾳ. Phedr. p. 265 Ὁ. 


DIALECTICS. 231 


power of synthesis and analysis. So that Plato’s ideas are, 
strictly speaking, nothing more than general terms, and Plato’s 
dialectics necessarily rest on his examinations—the first that 
had been attempted—of the syntax of the Greek language. 
His procedure is as follows. He perceived that every pro- 
position or enunciation necessarily consisted of a subject or 
name of a thing (ὄνομα), which assumes its being or entity 
(οὐσία), and of a predicate or assertion (ῥῆμα), which affirmed 
or denied something of the subject. He says, however, that 
words, whether subjects or predicates, express neither entity 
nor action, neither being nor becoming, unless they are joined 
together in a sentence; and then some tense of becoming is 
predicated of some state of being—or the many are predicated 
of the one—for then it is that we have a declaration concerning 
existing things (subjects) as becoming, or having become, or 
being about to become, and then we have not merely names 
or subjects, but conclusions derived from the connexion of the 
subject with the predicate.’ But how do we get the assumption 
of entity in the subject or name? Because the act of naming 
or affixing a general name, the name of the genus, is the first 
step in classification, and in itself gives a fixity to things, which 
is opposed to generation or becoming. The name is true and 
accurate in proportion as it rests upon the definition real, of 
which the main part is some general term including a multi- 
plicity of objects, and the secondary part is an explanation of 
the difference between this object and others which belong to 
the same genus. This secondary process, or the per diffe- 
rentiam, is subordinate to the per genus, and the dialectician’s 





1 Phedr. p. 266 B.: τούτων δὴ ἔγωγε αὐτὸς ἐραστής, τῶν διαιρέσεων καὶ 
συναγωγῶν. 

2 See New Cratylus, § 59, where we have given reasons for believing that Plato 
was, strictly speaking, a nominalist. This is shown incidentally by a comparison be- 
tween the gentle reproach to the youthful Socrates in the Parmenides, p. 130 A.-C., 
for supposing that the science of names'is not independent of any want of dignity 
in the objects which the names denote, and the distinct statement which we have 
quoted below from Sophistes, p. 227 A. 

3 Sophist. p. 262: ὅταν εἴπῃ τις ‘dvOpwros μανθάνει" λόγον εἶναι φὴς τοῦτον 
ἐλάχιστόν τε καὶ πρωτον ; ἔγωγε. δηλοῖ γὰρ ἤδη που τότε περὶ τῶν ὄντων ἢ γεγονότων 
ἤ μελλόντων καὶ οὐκ ὀνομάζει μόνον, ἀλλά τι περαίνει, συμπλέκων τὰ ῥήματα τοῖς 
ὀνόμασιν, διὸ λέγειν τε αὐτὸν ἀλλ᾽ οὐ μόνον ὀνομάζειν εἴπομεν. καὶ δὴ καὶ τῷ πλέγ- 
pare τούτῳ τὸ ὄνομα ἐφθεγξάμεν ἃ ὁ γ ον. 


232 PLATO. 


great object is to ascertain what are those general terms which — 
are the objects of thought. They cannot belong to the objects 
of sense—the phenomena—which are in a constant state of 
transition, but must of necessity be included among those things 
which we know by means of reflexion (διάνοια), through the un- 
derstanding (λογισμός, νοῦς, νόησις) ; for these things, being 
fixed, may be referred to entity (οὐσία), and made the objects 
of science (ἐπιστήμη), or certain knowledge.’ _ 

This, then, is Plato’s theory of ideas, considered as a recon- 
ciliation of the counter-propositions of the Eleatics and Hera- 
cleiteans. Asserting against the former that the sensible is true, 
he conceded. that it is so only by partaking of the intelligible 
(κατὰ μέθεξιν τοῦ ὄντος) ; and while this is expressed dialec- 
tically by a system of scientific classification, it is metaphy- 
sically an .effort to ascend to the supreme idea, which has in it 
nothing that.is:capable of being comprehended by the senses ; 
for the subordinate ideas are but hypothetical notions from 
which we reach the true elevation by means of continually 
higher assumptions ;? . until at last we come to God, as the 
supreme idea;.and thus the common standard of all things 
is not man, as Protagoras asserted, but God-alone.’ 

In order. to.understand fully the manner in which Plato 
works, out controversially this dialectical theory, it is necessary 
to read carefully the series of dialogues, which he seems to have 
written at brief intervals after his military service at Corinth, 
aidj,in which he has immortalized. the young philosopher and 
geometrician,* who was wounded, by his side, when the Lace- 
dsemonians outflanked and crushed the left wing of the Athe-. 
nian’ hoplites.. We must content ourselves with a general 
sketch of this ingenious collection of criticisms in the form of 
dialogues. The first three, a report of which Eucleides reads to 





1 See Parmen. p..129 E., Phed. 65 C., Resp.. VII. p. 532 A. According to 
Plato (Theetetus, p.. 187. A.).science must. be sought. ἐν ἐκείνῳ τῷ ὀνόματι ὅτι ποτ᾽ 
ἔχει ἡ ψυχή, ὅταν αὐτὴ. καθ᾽ αὑτὴν πραγματεύηται περὶ τὰ ὄντα. 

2 Resp. VI. p. 511 B., comp. Pheedo, p. 100 A. Philebus, p.20-D. Resp. p. 
610 C. 

3 Leges, IV. p. 716 Ο. 

4 Theetetus was the founder of the geometrical school, in which the great Euclid 
was formed ; see below, ch. XLVI. § 6. 

5 Theetet. p. 142. See Grote, History of Greece, IX. p. 427. 


DIALECTICS. 233 


his friend Terpsion, are represented as consecutive parts of a con- 
ference commenced between Socrates and Theodorus, the mathe- 
matician of Cyrene. The latter having spoken in high terms of a 
young Athenian named Thezetetus, of Sunium, who resembled So- 
crates in person, and who had probably been Plato’s friend and 
fellow-exile at Megara, introduces him to Socrates, who at once 
engages him in a discussion on science (ἐπιστήμη). The object 
of the dialogue called Theetetus' is to refute three definitions of 
this term, which are put into the mouth of the young student 
of philosophy : (I.) that science is sensation (αἴσθησις), which, as 
Socrates says, is much the same as the dogma of Protagoras, 
‘the individual man is the standard of all things ;’ (II.) that 
science is right conception (ἡ ἀληθὴς δόξα), from which we get 
a most subtle disquisition on the nature of false conception, 
with particular reference to the fallacies of the Megarics and 
Cynics, and with the celebrated illustration of memory as a waxen 
tablet ;? (III.) that science is right conception combined with 
accurate definition or reasonable explanation (ἡ μετὰ λόγου 
ἀληθὴς δόξα). The result of the dialogue is purely negative ; 
it consists in showing that no one of these definitions of science 





1 We have given an analysis of this dialogue in our article on Plato in the Penny 
Cyclopedia, and we recommend the dialogue itself to the careful consideration of 
any young student, who wishes really to comprehend the dialectics of Plato, or the 
effects of his philosophy on the theories of his successors and the rival schools of 
philosophy. There can be little doubt, for example, that the speculations of Car- 
neades have a direct reference to the Theetetus of Plato; see below, chap. XLVII. 
§ 8. 

3 Professor Thompson remarks (Butler’s Lectwres, vol. II. p. 103 note, ὃ 25) 
that ‘to this part of the dialogue Locke’s celebrated chapter on memory presents 
a striking parallel (Essay, B. II. chap. X. 88 4, 5).’ 

3 There is some difficulty as to the interpretation of λόγος in this third descrip- 
tion of ἐπιστήμη. The elucidation added by Theztetus, where he gives this des- 
cription at second-hand (201 D), ὧν μή ἐστι λόγος, οὐκ ἐπιστητὰ εἶναι, and the whole 
course of the argument which follows, show that λόγος must mean, as we have 
rendered it in the text, definition or explanation. So Stallbaum translates μετὰ 
λόγου, cwm explicatione verbis expressd (Proleg. p. 27), Schleiermacher ‘ die mit ihrer 
Erklirung verbundene richtige Vorstellung,’ and Mr. Butler (Lectures, II. p. 104) 
says, ‘Science is pronounced to be opinion μετὰ λόγου---ἃ qualification, which 
seems from the subsequent tenor of the discussion, to signify judgment with expli- 
cation.’ The subdivisions carried on in the Sophistes are probably illustrations of 
that explication, which Plato meant by λόγος, as distinguished from the definition 
real. The locus classicus for the distinction between the οὐσία, the λόγος, and the 
ὄνομα, is in the Laws, X. pp. 895—6. 


234 PLATO. 


is capable of being sustained ; but the author more than suggests 
in the course of the disquisition the positive result which he 
would substitute for these exploded hypotheses, namely, the 
method of true classification and real definition as the basis of 
dialectics. The abrupt termination of the Theetetus is excused 
by Socrates on the ground that he is obliged to attend at the 
porch of the king archon, and meet the indictment of Meletus ; 
but he appoints the following morning for the adjourned dis- 
cussion with Theodorus and his pupils. In accordance with 
this arrangement the mathematician of Cyrene comes to the 
rendezyous, bringing with him a foreign philosopher of the 
Eleatic school, and the second dialogue in this series, which is 
called the Sophistes, from the general subject of the definitions 
which it attempts, is mainly carried on between this Eleatic 
stranger and Theztetus, Socrates sitting by rather to watch 
and preside over the dialogue than to take any active part in 
it. The stranger, who is represented as a man of conspicuous 
moderation and courtesy, does not go to any great length in 
maintaining the principles of his school, but he is allowed to 
exhibit some of the trifling, in which the Eleatics, and, after 
them, the Megarics, were wont to indulge ; and it was, no doubt, 
Plato’s object to show that all the hair-splitting of these subtle 
analytical disputants,'’ with their perpetual bisection of the suc- 
cessive subdivisions, was, after all, only a play with words, which 
did not necessarily issue in a real definition, that, in fact, the 
ideal theory required the use of reflexion (διάνοια) and under- 
standing (λογισμός), and was not attained merely by definition 
in words (λόγος), which led only to a sort of primd facie clas- 
sification. On the whole, then, we may say, that, as the Thee- 
tetus was designed to confute more especially the opinions of 
Protagoras and Heracleitus, so the Sophistes was intended, less 
directly but quite as intelligibly, to exhibit the deficiencies of 
the Eleatic and Megaric schools, into which Plato had passed 





1 Another Butler, not the Professor at Dublin, has very happily described the 
kind of explication by way of subdivision, which is exhibited in the Sophistes 
(Hudibras, I. 1, 65): 

‘He was in logic a great critic 
Profoundly skilled in analytic ; 
He could distinguish and divide, 
A hair ’twixt south and south-west side.’ 


DIALECTICS. 235 


from that of the Heracleitean Cratylus;' to show, in fact, that if the 
Heracleiteans were wrong in their annihilation of the intelligible 
world, neither were the Eleatics right in confining all truth to the 
predication of entityand unity. That his dissent from the philoso- 
pher, whose hospitality he had so recently enjoyed, was less marked 
than that which separated him from his first teacher, Cratylus, 
is shown by the general tone of the dialogue and by the manner 
in which he occasionally allows the Eleatic stranger to express 
his own thoughts and opinions. For example, he would not have 
repeated in the Politicus, his assertion ‘ that in scientific classi- 
fication we have nothing to do with the dignity or meanness of 
the subject-matter,’ unless he had attached some importance on 
its own account to the statement in the Sophistes* that ‘the 
science of definitions does not pay more or less attention to the 
art of purgation externally by the sponge than to that of pur- 
gation internally by medicine, because the benefits of the latter 
are more important ; for, as its object is to understand the affi- 
nity or dissimilitude of all arts, in regard to their definition, 
this science attaches equal value to them all in this respect, and 
does not regard one art as more ridiculous than another in 
regard to that which they have in common ; for example, it does 
not consider the man who illustrates the art of capturing by 
means of generalship more dignified, but only more ostentatious 
and pretentious, than the man who illustrates the same art by 
catching vermin. That in the midst of all his persiflage he 
intended to define the Sophist as contrasted with the true States- 
man, whom he depicts in the Politicus, and the true Philo- 
sopher, whom he indirectly exhibits in the Parmenides, must be 
clear to all attentive readers. In the Politicus, Thetetus, 
who resembles Socrates in person, makes way for a younger 





1 There is a direct comparison of the two schools in the Sophistes, p. 242 C. 

2 p. 266 Ὁ. 3 p. 227 A. 

4 The connexion in thought between this passage and that in the Parmenides 
(p. 130 C.), when the question is raised, whether there is such a thing as the abstract 
idea of a hair, or mud, or filth, or any other of the vilest and most contemptible 
objects, appears to us to indicate not only the genuineness of the Parmenides, but 
also its connexion with the Politicus and the Sophistes. Aristotle’s reference to 
- the Politicus, which we haye quoted below, is sufficient to establish the authen- 
ticity of that dialogue, and the connected works, must, as we think, stand or fall 
together, 


236 PLATO. 


Socrates, a namesake of the great philosopher, who, as in the 
former dialogue, takes no active part in the discussion. Al- 
though we have here also a sample of the same Eleatico-Megaric 
subtleties of successive subdivision, it is clear enough that the 
writer seriously intends to define the true—that is, the philoso- 
phical—Statesman, such as he or his imitator describes in’ 
the 7th epistle, such as he indirectly adumbrates in the 
Gorgias, such as he elaborately exhibits in his ideal Republic, 
such as he presents, in relation to the universal frame of 
nature, in the Timeus. Developing what Plato had already 
written in the almost contemporary dialogue of Gorgias, 
and in the first edition of the Republic—if they pre- 
ceded, as seems most probable, the publication of the Politicus, 
—and anticipating the views of the Timeus, which is manifestly 
one of the latest of Plato’s works, this dialogue is a glimpse 
of Plato’s ethical philosophy in the midst of his dialectical 
criticiams. Out of the fifty-four pages of which this dialogue con- 
sists, about one-half are purely dialectical,’ the rest being either 
on the politico-ethical subject, or having reference to the ori- 
ginal condition of man and his relations to the divine theocracy. - 
That the author does not regard his dialectical minutiz as un- 
instructive trifling is clear from the apology which he puts into 
the mouth of the Eleatic disputant:? ‘ Our discourse bids us 
regard, not in the first, but in the second place, in point of im- 
portance, that length of the investigation which is suitable to 
the subject under discussion, namely, that we may find the 
object of our search as early and as speedily as possible ; but in 
the highest degree and in the first place it recommends us to 
honour on its own account the scientific procedure (μέθοδος), 
namely, the being able to divide the genus into its species 
(kar εἴδη διαιρεῖν) ; and with regard to the discourse, if, on the 
one hand, by being spoken at great length it shall make the hearer 
more inventive, we are enjoined to pursue it zealously, and not 





1 The dialectical part is from p. 258 C., to p. 268E., andfrom p. 274 E., top. 291 C. 

2 Politicus, p. 286 D. We must compare with this passage, Plato’s candid ad- 
missions of his voluntary and intentional discursiveness in the Republic, VI. p. 487 
B, and Theetetus, p. 173 B, and the recommendation to the youthful Socrates which 
puts into the mouth of the venerable Parmenides: ἕλκυσον σαυτὸν καὶ γύμνασαι 
μᾶλλον διὰ THs δοκούσης ἀχρήστου εἶναι καὶ καλουμένης ὑπὸ THY πολλῶν ἀδολεσχίας, 
ἕως ἔτι νέος εἶ (Parmen. p. 135 C.). 


DIALECTICS. 237 


be annoyed by its prolixity; and similarly if it be more con- 
cise. Moreover, the person, who complains of prolixity in 
discussions of this kind, and disapproves of round-about argu- 
mentation, must not so very quickly and at once dismiss the 
argument with the complaint that it is lengthy, but must show 
besides that, if it were shorter, it would render the disputants 
better dialecticians (διαλεκτικωτέρους), and more inventive in 
the art of explaining realities by means of language.’ This 
passage should be in the recollection of modern réaders when 
they find fault with what appears to them sometimes the pur- 
poseless and tedious perplexity of discussions which the ancient 
logicians valued on that very account and for their own sake. 
Plato’s definition of the statesman’s art is very plainly given in 
the Politicus. The faculty of the statesman (ἡ τοῦ πολιτικοῦ 
δύναμις) is, he tells us, that which rules and presides over all 
laws and public deliberations and guides them to their proper 
end,’ and the best of all governments is that form of monarchy 
in which the state is ruled by a really wise and virtuous man. 
If all states were equally bad, it would be best to live under a 
democracy; if all were equally good, the monarchical form of 
government would be most eligible. But the ideal state, in 
which the virtuous philosopher is the living interpretation of 
the law, is far better than any actual monarchy in the world. 
It is only an inference,* but we believe it to be a well-founded 
inference, that the Parmenides is the dialogue to which the So- 
phistes and Politicus refer as the coming discourses on ‘the philo- 
sopher.’ The passages,on which this conclusion depends, are those 
in the Theetetus and Sophistes, in which distinct reference is 
made to the fact that Socrates, when very young, held such a 
conversation with Parmenides as is represented in the dialogue 
so named,’ those in the Sophistes,° in which the character of the 
philosopher is described, just as that character is fully exhibited 
in the Parmenides, and those in the Sophistes and Politicus, in 





1 p. 304 D. The direct reference to this dialogue at the very beginning of Ari- 
stotle’s Politics (I. 1, §2, comp. with Plato, Politicus, p. 258 E.) shows the importance 
of the work in those days. 2 p. 301 Ὁ. 3 p. 303 A. 

4 This inference is due to Stallbaum, Prolegom. ad Parmen. (Lips. 1839), p. 334; 
Proleg. ad Sophist. (Gothe, 1840), p. 52 ; Proleg. ad Politic. (Gothx, 1841), p. 33, 
and to Zeller, Platonische Studien, p. 236. 

5 Theetet. p. 183 E. Sophist. p..217 Ο, § Sophist. p. 253 Ὁ, E, 


238 PLATO. 


which a discourse on the philosopher is promised as a neces- 
sary sequel.’ The chief difficulty in accepting this conclusion 
is occasioned by the fact that in the Parmenides, as we have it, 
there is no mention of Thextetus, Theodorus, the Eleatic 
stranger, and the other persons present in the three connected 
dialogues. In the Parmenides, as it stands, Cephalus, the 
Clazomenian,’ begins at once, without a word of preface, and 
without any intimation of the persons whom he is addressing, 
to narrate how, on his arrival at Athens from his house at Cla- 
zomens, he fell in with Adeimantus and Glauco, and was by 
them taken to Antipho’s house, who told them, on the autho- 
rity of Pythodorus, the details of the conversation between 
Socrates and Parmenides, when the former was quite a young 
man,’ and the latter sixty-five years old. The other parties to the 
dialogue, thus reported at third hand—for Pythodorus tells 
Antipho, Antipho relates it to Cephalus and his two com- 
panions,,and Cephalus recounts it to his unknown auditors— 
are Zeno, the philosopher, and Aristoteles, who was afterwards 
one of the thirty tyrants. To the difficulty occasioned by 
the independent preface to the Parmenides it has been 
thought a sufficient answer that, as we are not told to whom 
Cephalus recounted the dialogue, there is nothing to prevent us 
from supposing that his hearers were the persons who had 
taken a part in the three connected dialogues. And to this 
solution there is no chronological objection ; for the Theetetus 
and its associated dialogues are represented as taking place in 
B.c. 399, and Cephalus, the Clazomenian, is made to speak of 
the conversation, which he relates, as having happened very 
long before the time when he repeats it.“ Our conclusion is 





1 Sophist. p. 216 E. sq., 254 B. Polit. p. 257 A. 

2 The mention of Glauco and Adeimantus, who appear in conjunction with 
Cephalus, the father of Lysias, in the Republic, might lead us to conclude that the 
Cephalus of the Parmenides was the same person. But the latter was a Clazo- 
menian, probably one of the school of Anaxagoras, like his companions who are 
described as μάλα φιλόσοφοι (Parmen. p. 126 B.), and the former was a Syracusan, 
who had lived 30 years at Athens (above, ch. XXXV. § 1), whereas the Clazo- 
menian had not been at Athens since he was a boy. 

3 Synesius (Calv. Enc. 17) says, he was then 25 years old. 

4 He says he was a boy when he first came to Athens, πολὺς δὲ ἤδη χρόνος ἀπ᾽ 
ἐκείνου, and he speaks of the λόγους obs ποτε Σ. καὶ Ζ. καὶ ΤΙ. διελέχθησαν, and 
implies that Antipho recollected them (ἀπομνημονεύει) from frequent repetitions. 


DIALECTICS. 239 


this: as the Eleatic stranger is indicated as the person from 
whom we are to expect the description of the philosopher, and 
as the philosopher introduced is one of his own school, we 
must suppose that he reads the report of Cephalus from some 
manuscript left in his possession by that respectable old man, 
and the loss of the connecting prefatory matter must be ex- 
plained in the same way as the similar omission in the Re- 
public, where we are left to conclude from the Timeus and 
Critias, who are the persons favoured with this narrative of a 
conversation in ten books. We have mentioned above’ some of 
the reasons for supposing that the Republic, as we have it, in 
its lengthened form, but without any introduction, was the 
revised and enlarged edition of a work originally written about 
the same time as the Gorgias ; and we are convinced that the 
Parmenides, also, in its present state, was the result of the re- 
casting and almost re-writing of a dialogue, which had been pub- 
lished long before, as the Philosopher, and as a connected sequel 
to the Theetetus, Sophistes, and Politicus ; and that the loss of 
the introductory matter, in this as in the Republic, is due to the 
fact that Plato was still at work about them both at the time 
of his death. If we had the preface to the Parmenides, it 
would probably tell us that Socrates left to the Eleatic stranger 
the task of narrating the conversation, because he professed to 
forget what he had heard and said so many years before. It 
would be impossible to give any idea, to a person who has not 
read the dialogue, of the subtle and elaborate reasonings of the 
Parmenides, which is perhaps the most remarkable specimen of 
dialectical power to be found in the whole range of philosophical 
literature. We must be satisfied with saying’ that the Par- 
menides discusses at length the various forms and consequences 
of the hypothetical propositions which rest on the suppositions : 
(1.) ‘If the One is; (2.) ‘ If the One is not ;’ the apodosis or 
conclusion being an answer to the question—‘ what are we to 
understand by the One and by the things other than One ?’ 
There are nine forms, according to this dialogue, of the apodosis, 
five for the positive, and four for the negative assumption ; or 





1 See above, § 6. 
2 Tn the text we have followed Renouvier’s account of the Parmenides, which 
gives perhaps the simplest analysis of this subtle dialogue ; see Manuel de Philo- 


240 PLATO. 


if we regard the third as merely a natural consequence of the 
second, we shall have four of each. Now the last four, or the 
results of the negative hypothesis, are a reductio ad absurdum 
of those who maintain the theory of multiplicity without the 
real unity, the πολλὰ without the &—of the Heracleiteans, in 
fact; for the 7th and gth propositions compel them to deny the 
existence of plurality, while they reject even the name of 
unity, and the 6th and 8th propositions oblige them to recognize — 
in the One and in other things the same properties con- 
trary to those which they would have if the One existed really. 
And the first four (or, if we prefer it, five) propositions are di- 
vided between the Megarics and Plato. The first and last of 
this set (propositions 1st and 5th) reduce the Megarics to a 
profession of nihilism, because assuming the ἕν without the 
πολλά, they place each of the ideas by itself and deny their 
participation in one another. The intervening propositions (2, 
3 and 4) contain the system of Plato. The One exists and 
partakes of being, and the other ideas partake of it, so that 
Unity as well as Plurality—the ἕν καὶ roAAa—both belong to 
existence or entity, which thus combines the apparent contra- 
dictions. Considered then as an exhibition of the ideal philo- 
sopher, the Parmenides shows that this ideal is not to be found 
either in the Eleatico-Megaric or in the Heracleiteo-Cratylean 





sophie Anciénne, II. pp. 24, 25. The following is his statement of the nine hypo- 
thetical propositions: 


PosITIVE ASSUMPTIONS. NEGATIVE ASSUMPTIONS. 
If the one is: If the one is not: 
1. There is no science, sensation or 6. There must be contradictory pre- 
opinion of this one, when it is absolute. dications. 
2. There is science, sensation, &c., of 4. There can be no science, &c. 
the one, if it admits of logical predica- 8. Other things must exist, because 


tions or may be distributed in predicates; we speak of them; and therefore they 
so that the one is combined with the both exist and do not exist. 
many. 9. Nothing exists. 
3. There is a co-ordinate possibility of 
similitude and dissimilitude, &c., in the 
latter case. 
4. Also a compatibility of contraries. 
5. But when the many and the one 
are absolutely contrasted and opposed, 
there is no possibility of logical predica- 
tions, 


DIALECTICS. 241 


school, but might be manifested by one, who, like himself, 
brought to a review of these systems the dialectical method of 
Socrates and the abstract speculations of the Pythagoreans. 
It seems to us that Plato had a special object in giving this 
development of his philosophical principles in a dialogue which 
represents his teacher Socrates, while still a young man, in 
direct intercourse with Parmenides, from whose school, com- 
bined with that of Socrates, the Megaric philosophers derived 
their doctrines. The compliments paid to Socrates by the 
veteran philosopher, the warning to him to avoid the influences 
of current opinions, and the recommendation to examine the 
negative as well as the positive assumption in his hypothetical 
reasonings, all seem to show that Plato wished to represent 
Socrates as the true founder of his own school, no less than of 
the Megaric, and to indicate the importance of the rules which 
Socrates had not applied, which the Megarics had deliberately 
set aside, and which he adopted as the clue to the solution of 
the problem respecting the One and the Many. The sequel 
and supplement to this series of four dialogues is the Cratylus. 
Although it was the natural tendency of Plato’s system to 
make general terms the proper objects of reasoning and the 
materials of science, although he was, like his predecessor So- 
crates, a nominalist rather than a realist, he was not the less 
on this account opposed to the extravagances of ultra-nomi- 
nalism. And when he found the two schools, which he made 
the chief objects of his criticisms, the Eleatics as well as the 
Heracleiteans, engaged in etymological researches, which pre- 
sumed that truth and science were to be discovered in sounds 
and signs, the spoken elements of a living language, especially 
when he saw that Aristippus had given a still more pernicious 
extension to these theories,’ he felt himself obliged to add to 
his general review of the two counter-systems an exposure of the 
absurdities which had resulted from an attempt to deal pre- 
maturely with the great problem of language.’ As the Eleatics, 
in this and in other matters, were much less opposed to Plato’s 
views than the Heracleiteans, we find that Cratylus, the original 





1 Above, chapter XX XVII. ὃ 6. 2 See New Cratylus, ὃ 60, 
Vou, II, R 


242 PLATO. 


instructor of Plato, who gives his name to the dialogue, is made 
to bear the chief brunt of the irony and ridicule ; while Her- 
mogenes, the brother of Callias, who appears as a supporter of 
the Eleatic doctrines, is allowed to speak contemptuously of 
Protagoras’ book called ‘Truth’ The general result of the 
dialogue is that, as words are merely the images of things, it 
would be much better, even if we could learn the nature of 
things from their names, to make the truth a criterion as well 
of itself as of its image.’ 

§ 8. The moral and political philosophy of Plato rests entirely 
on his dialectics. Indeed the ethical and political dialogues are so 
interspersed with logical and metaphysical disquisition that it 
would be impossible to separate the method of language and 
thought from its practical applications.” It may be said, how- 
ever, that if we add the Gorgias, the Republic and the Laws to 
those works which Plato published after opening his school in 
the Academia, we shall have the bulk of what he wrote respecting 
the nature of virtue, the objects of life, and the duties of man 
as an individual and a citizen. Our limits will not permit to 
give a lengthened analysis of this long series of elaborate essays, 
but it will not be difficult to indicate the general views which 
they develope, and the many details m which they contribute 
respectively to the ethical theory of Plato. 

The main principles, which form the basis of these speculations 
are,—that the soul is independent of the body,—that it is tri- 
partite,—and that its three divisions, with their due combination, 





1 Cratylus p. 439 A.: εἰ οὖν ἔστι μὲν ὅτι μάλιστα δι᾽ ὀνομάτων τὰ πράγματα μαν- 
θάνειν, ἔστι δὲ καὶ δι’ αὐτῶν, ποτέρα ἂν εἴη καλλίων καὶ σαφεστέρα ἡ μάθησις ; ἐκ τῆς 
εἰκόνος μανθάνειν αὐτήν τε αὐτήν, εἰ καλῶς εἴκασται, καὶ τὴν ἀλήθειαν ἧς ἣν ἡ εἰκών, 
ἢ ἐκ τῆς ἀληθείας αὐτήν τε αὐτὴν καὶ τὴν εἱκόνα αὐτῆς, εἰ πρεπόντως εἴργασται; 

2 There are in fact many passages in which Plato recognizes a subordination of 
virtue in general to wisdom, on the true Socratic principle ; see especially Phado 
p. 69 A, where even the other three cardinal virtues ἀνδρεία, σωφροσύνη, δικαιοσύνη, 
are to be purchased by the fourth φρόνησις as the only true coin—ddN Ff ἐκεῖνο 
μόνον τὸ νόμισμα ὀρθόν, ἀνθ᾽ οὗ δεῖ ἅπαντα ταῦτα καταλλάττεσθαι, φρόνησις, Kat 
τούτου μὲν πάντα καὶ μετὰ τούτου ὠνούμενά τε καὶ πιπρασκόμενα τῷ ὄντι ἣ, καὶ ἀνδρεία 
Καὶ δικαιοσύνη καὶ ξυλλήβδην ἀληθὴς ἀρετὴ ἢ μετὰ φρονήσεως. So that this one 
virtue plays the part of virtue in general in the lines of Euripides (@dipus fr. TX. 
Dind.), attributed to Sophocles by Clem. Alex. Strom. IV. p. 574, Potter : 

οὔτοι νόμισμα λευκὸς dpyupos μόνον 
καὶ χρυσός ἐστιν, ἀλλὰ χἠρετὴ βροτοῖς 
γόμισμα κεῖται πᾶσιν ἣ χρῆσθαι χρεών. 


MORAL AND POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY. 243 


are indicated by the relations of the four cardinal virtues. This 
view, which is supported throughout by suggestions derived 
from the Pythagoreans, is opposed, like his dialectics, to the 
counter systems of the Heracleiteans and Eleatics, and in many 
respects also to that of Socrates. While he at once discards 
the notion that pleasure resulting from sensible impressions can 
be the highest good—for this would be to admit morally what 
he had denied scientifically in the Theetetus, namely, the para- 
mount influence of the senses,—he also rejects the claim of 
knowledge alone to be considered as the chief good, which 
would have brought him back to the views of the Eleatics, the 
Megarics, and some other Socratic schools. 

The allegory or mythus in the Phedrus opens the way to a 
comprehension of the principles which Plato wished to enforce.’ 
The soul, we are told, is immortal, because it is self-moved ; it 
not only does not perish with the body, but it existed before it 
was enveloped in any bodily frame. It is god-like also; but 
the human soul differs from that which belongs to the deities 
in one of its three parts. For the soul may be compared to a 
charioteer driving a pair of winged steeds. Now the horses 
and drivers of the gods are all both good themselves and of good 
extraction ; but, in the case of men, the charioteer, the Reason, 
has to drive two horses of opposite descent and opposite cha- 
racter ; one of them is well-bred and well-trained, and the other 
quite the reverse :? the quiet horse,—the Will—is obedient to 
the rein and strives to draw its wilder yoke-fellow,—the Appe- 
tite—along with it, and to induce it to listen to the voice of 
the charioteer, the Reason: but they have much pain and 
trouble with it, and the whole object of the charioteering is lost 
if it contrives to get the better of them. In this allegory it is 
intimated that the Reason exacts obedience from the lower 
faculties, not merely for the sake of that subordination which 
constitutes the moral goodness of man, but also because it is 
thus enabled to take a calm view of abstract truth, and to gaze 
on the eternal realities, which in this world are clothed in the 
garb of space and time. According to the allegory, the soul in 





1 Phedrus, p. 245 sqq. 
2 Τῇ the elaborate description of the unruly steed (Phedr. p. 253 E), we should 
adopt Porson’s unpublished emendation περὶ τὰ ὦτα λασιόκωφος for λάσιος, κωφός. 
R 2 


244 : PLATO. 


its previous state of existence, traverses the circuit of the uni- 
verse, in the train of the gods, with Zeus at their head, and if 
the Reason can control his restive steed so far as to be able to 
raise his own head above the heavenly vault, he is borne round 
by the revolution of the celestial sphere, and though sore en- 
cumbered with his horses, sees, however faintly and imperfectly, 
the essences of things, which are there disclosed to his gaze ; 
for ‘real existence, colourless, formless, and intangible, visible 
only to the intelligence which guides the helm of the soul, and 
with which the family of true science is conversant, finds its 
abode in that region.’ And it is the remembrance of this gaze 
which furnishes the soul of man with its ideas of the true and 
the beautiful after it has descended to this lower world and 
become united with a body. This figurative picture contains the 
germs of the thoughts which are developed in the connected 
dialogues. The doctrine of the soul’s reminiscences in a pre- 
vious state, becomes the argument for its immortality in the 
Phedo, and it helps to solve the question as to the teachableness 
of virtue in the Meno. The same Phzdrus, who evokes the 
discourse about love in the dialogue called by his name, is 
declared to be the father and founder of the argument’ in the 
Symposium, where the guests at Agatho’s table make a series 
of panegyrics on love, which are finished off by the discourse put 
into the mouth of Socrates, but attributed to the Arcadian 
prophetess Diotima; and here we have the same doctrine as in 
the Phedrus, that virtue and science spring from that true love 
which is produced by the contemplation of ideal beauty. ‘ What 
effect, says Diotima,’ ‘would the sight of beauty itself have 
upon a-man were he to see it pure and genuine, not corrupted 
and stained all over with the mixture of flesh and colour, and 
suchlike perishing and fading trash, but were able to view that 
divine essence, the beautiful itself, in its’ own simplicity of 
form? Do you not perceive, that in beholding the beautiful 
with that eye with which alone it is discernible,‘ thus and thus 
only could a man generate not the images or semblances of 
virtue, but virtue itself, true, real, and substantial, by conversing 





1 Phedr. p. 247 C: ἡ γὰρ ἀχρώματός τε καὶ ἀσχημάτιστος καὶ ἀναφὴς οὐσία ὄντως 
οὖσα ψυχῆς κυβερνήτῃ μόνῳ θεατὴ νῷ, περὶ ἣν τὸ τῆς ἀληθοῦς ἐπιστήμης γένος, τοῦτον 
ἔχει τὸν τόπον. : 2 Sympos. p. 177 D. 3 Jbid. p. 211 D. 

4 ὁρῶντι ᾧ ὁρατὸν τὸ καλόν t.€. νῷ. Phedr. p. 247 C. 


MORAL AND POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY. 245 


with and embracing that which is real and true. Thus, be- 
getting true virtue and bringing her up to maturity, he would 
become a favourite with the gods, and at length he would be, if 
man ever was so, himself one of the immortals.’ 

But the practical development of these lofty and Gianneet. 
dental views of morality is to be found most fully in the 
Republic, and their metaphysical elaboration is reserved for the 
Philebus. The criticisms on the rhetorical school of Lysias, 
Thrasymachus, and Gorgias, bring the Phedrus into one contact 
with the Gorgias and the Republic, which are connected also 
by the general objects referred to above, and by their eschatology 
or doctrine of retribution in a future state.’ But we think that 
the Republic, most probably in a later edition,? was intended 
especially to develope the connexion between the tripartite 
division of the soul, and the four cardinal virtues, to which so 
much importance was attached. According to Plato,’ moral 
virtue is the due subordination of man’s lower faculties to his 
reason ; in other words, man is virtuous when the Will acts as 
the servant of Reason in controlling the Appetite. Considered 
as an individual, man is righteous and just, or generally 
virtuous and good, in proportion as this subordination is com- 
plete. In his social capacity, as a state or republic, man 
attains to this perfection in proportion as the guards, or military 





-1 Among the striking similarities of the Republic and the Gorgias, we may men- 
‘tion particularly the refutation of Polus in the latter as compared with the Republic, 
p- 445, where at B we ought to read ἐπείπερ ἐνταῦθα ἐληλύθαμεν ὅπου for ὅσον. 

2 One of the most decisive proofs that the Republic, as we have it, is a second 
and enlarged edition of a work originally published some years previously, is fur- 
nished by the manner in which the discussion in the 5th book is introduced. 
Socrates there says that he would have been satisfied with a brief statement of his 
views respecting the community of women and children, and it would appear as if 
some criticisms had compelled him to elaborate this part of his theory. It seems 
probable that the sixth beok was the conclusion of the Republic in its original form ; 
at least there is a trace of this in p. 506 ἢ, where Glaucon says to Socrates, μὴ 
πρὸς Διός, ὥσπερ ἐπὶ τέλει ὧν ἀποστῇς. * 3 Respublica, IV. pp. 427 sqq. 

4 Plato’s phrases are τὸ λογιστικόν, τὸ θυμοειδές, τὸ ἐπιθυμητικόν (p. 439 D). The 
second of these, representing the better steed in the Phedrus, is sometimes ren- 
dered the ‘irascible principle,’ and Cicero translates it by tracwndia (de Republ. I. 
38): but Hooker and Hemsterhuis the younger more properly render it ‘ the will,’ 
la velleité ; for it is the natural auxiliary of the reason (τὸ θυμοειδὲς ἐπίκουρον TY 
λογιστικῷ φύσει Resp. IV. p. 441 A), and the idea of spirit and courage implied in 
the word θυμὸς is well illustrated by the figurative statement that when a sedition 
arises in the soul, the will draws itself up in battle array by the side of the reason 
(ὦ τῇ τῆς ψυχῆς στάσει τίθεσθαι τὰ ὅπλα πρὸς τοῦ λογιστικοῦ, Resp. LV. p. 440 E). 


246 PLATO. 


caste, representing the Will, subserve the philosophical rulers, 
representing the reason, in controlling the turbulent populace, 
representing the Appetite. Now, the four cardinal virtues, by 
which, according to the ancients, the whole province of morality 
was exhausted, were—(1.) Prudence or Wisdom, (φρόνησις) ; 
(2.) Courage or Fortitude, (ἀνδρεία) ; (3.) Temperance, or Self- 
control, (σωφροσύνη); (4.) Justice or Righteousness, (δικαιοσύνη). 
In the imdividual the first is the virtue of the Reason, the 
second of the Will, and the third of the Appetite, while the 
fourth represents the state or condition resulting from the 
harmony of the whole. In the republic or society, the first is 
the virtue of the rulers, the second of the valiant standing- 
army, the third of the well-conducted populace; and the re- 
maining virtue is the virtue of the whole, the principle and 
cause of the existence of the three others, compelling each por- 
tion of the commonwealth to keep to its own business, and to 
abstain from all interference with the affairs of the other depart- 
ments, (that is, in the Greek sense, to avoid πολυπραγμοσύνη)." 
So then in the virtuous man and in the righteous republic, the 
Reason is full of wisdom, the Will is strong in fortitude, and 
the Appetite under the healthy influence of self-control; and 
all these are kept together in one concert or harmony by justice, 
just as the musical harmony combines the highest, the lowest, 
and the middle sound.” This due subordination and harmony 





1 IV. p. 434 B, 443 Ὁ, 444 B. 

2 IV. p. 443 D: ξυναρμόσαντα τρία ὄντα ὥσπερ ὅρους τρεῖς ἁρμονίας ἀτεχνῶς 
νεάτης καὶ ὑπάτης καὶ μέσης. Τῦ is now admitted that Shakspere must have been 
acquainted, by means of some translation, with this passage, and that he was not 
merely following Cicero’s imitation when he wrote (Henry V., Act I., se. II.): 

Exeter, While that the armed hand doth fight abroad 
The advised head defends itself at home: 
For government through high, and low, and lower, 
Put into parts, doth keep in one concent, 
Co-greeing in a full and natural close 
Like music. 
Canterbury. Therefore doth heaven divide 
The state of man in divers functions, 
Setting endeavour in continual motion, 
To which is fixed, as an aim or butt, 
Obedience. 
See the note in Knight’s Pictorial Shakspere, p. 328. There is also something 
more than fortuitous in the correspondence between the praise of love in the 
Sympos. p. τοῦ B, and that in Love's Labour's Lost, Act IV. se. 111. 


MORAL AND POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY. 247 


are necessary to the proper contemplation of the idea of the good, 
which, with Plato, is the essence of true religion.’ On this 
subject, Plato has expressed his meaning in a remarkable pas- 
sage of the Republic. The sun, he says, is a visible image of 
the idea of the good. For while the other senses, such as the 
hearing, need nothing intermediate or additional, in order to 
the perception of objects, the sight, on the other hand, does need 
the intervention or mediation of light, otherwise the colour and 
the form will uot be visible. Now this light is derived from 
the sun ; and the benefit, which our sight derives from the sun, 
is analogous to the benefit which our reason derives from the 
idea of the good; for, as the eye cannot see without the inter- 
veution of light, so the reason cannot discern the things of the 
ideal world without the light of truth. Consequently, the idea 
of the good is that which imparts truth to the objects of our 
reason, and the power of discerning truth to the reason itself. 
The idea of the good, therefore, is far above truth and the 
knowledge of truth; and as light and the faculty of vision are 
akin to the sun, but not identical with it, so truth, and the 
knowledge of truth, are related to the idea of the good, but are 
not identical with this idea, The sun is also an image of the 
idea of the good in another way. As the sun not merely enables 
the eye to see, but likewise supplies nourishment and growth 
to the visible objects, so the idea of the good not merely enables 
the reason to discern and know, but likewise gives to the ideas 
of the reason their being and reality. Accordingly as the sun, 
in Milton’s phraseology, ‘looks from his sole dominion like the 
god’ of this lower world of sense, so the idea of the good, the 
sovereign good, even God himself, reigns supreme in the higher 
world of ideas, which is cognizable only by the reason. 

It does not fall within our province, in writing a history of 
Greek literature, to discuss the visionary proposal for the 
arrangement of a commonwealth, which forms a distinct feature 
in the treatises on the Republic and the Laws. We are willing 
to admit that the former at least is a genuine Utopia—a place 
which is no place,—and that some of its provisions amount to 





1 Resp. VI. p. 507 B. 
2 The word Utopia, Οὐτοπία, is formed like Οὐκαλέγων and similar negative 
words, and signifies a Weissnichtwo or Kennaguhair; see New Cratylus, § 189. 


248 PLATO. 


heartless socialism, inconsistent alike with morality and civili- 
zation.’ And it is much to be regretted that Plato should have 
added these details to a general view of the constitution of man 
which approves itself to our best instincts, and is confirmed by 
the teaching of Christianity. Leaving these fruitless dreams of 
a dissatisfied politician, we have to examine the machinery by 
means of which Plato had intended to connect his Republic 
with three other dialogues—the Timeus, which is complete, the 
Critias, which is a mere fragment, and the Hermocrates, which 
is lost. Socrates is supposed to narrate to the interlocutors, 
who were to give their names to the other three treatises, a 
long conversation which took place at the house of old Cephalus, 
the father of Lysias, on the preceding day, when he had gone 
down with Glauco to see the Bendideia at the Peirzeus; and, 
in return for this, Timeus undertakes to explain how men such 
as they ought to be came into being; Critias is to show that 
such men really existed, and to describe, on the strength of an 
old family record derived from Egypt, the golden age of prime- 
val Athens, and the overthrow of the wonderful island of Atlan- 
tis; and Hermocrates is to finish with an essay on nature and 
nourishment.? We cannot see our way to any explanation, 
which will remove the anachronisms and impossibilities from 
this dramatic framework. We have already mentioned the 
reasons which render it probable that the Republic in its first 
form was written or published along with the Gorgias, i.e. soon 
after B.c. 395. That it did not then reach its present form, 
and was not connected with the other dialogues of the tetralogy, 
is shown not only by the story that the beginning was found in 





1 The socialism of Plato’s Republic is severely, but by no means fairly or ade- 
quately criticized in the first five chapters of Aristotle’s second book of Politics. 
A modern writer, Mr. Mitchell, in the preliminary discourse to his translation of 
Aristophanes denounces Plato’s fifth book as ‘lying,’ ‘absurd,’ ‘unfeeling,’ and 
‘ guilty, —lying, because it makes the useful the measure of the honourable; ab- 
surd, because it stifles the natural instincts of humanity; unfeeling, because it 
obliterates the domestic affections ; and guilty, because it makes lying a statutable 
virtue in the governors. Many of the criticisms on the Republic would be obviated 
if we could believe with Morgenstern (Commentat. de Plat. Republica), that it 
had no political reference, but was merely an allegory of the human soul, like 
Bunyan’s. 

5 Timaus, p. 20 A. 


MORAL AND POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY. 249 


the author’s tablets, with various transpositions of the words,' 
and by the fact that the third dialogue is an unfinished fragment, 
and the fourth non-existent, but also by many internal evidences, 
such as the Pythagorism, the unmistakeable references to 
Dionysius, and the like. There is also a distinct tradition, 
preserved by Aulus Gellius, that the Republic originally appeared 
in two books only, and in that form was controverted by Xeno- 
phon.* But no conclusions respecting the date of the work will 
remove the objections to the machinery, otherwise than by the 
supposition that at the end of his life Plato’s historical recollec- 
tions had become somewhat hazy and indistinct. It has been 
mentioned above that the imaginary conversation recorded in 
the Republic has been referred by Bockh to the year 411 B.c.;? 
and intercourse between Socrates and Critias at this time was 
possible enough. But Timzeus, whom Plato had to seek in 
Italy, was not very likely to have been at Athens at the time 
when the Athenians were in the midst of their difficulties after 
the Sicilian disaster ; and it is, of course, quite impossible that 
Hermocrates should have been there, when we know he was 
commanding a fleet against Athens in the Aigean. C. F. Her- 
mann would place the fictitious date of the supposed discourses 
about the time of Plato’s birth, in B.c. 429, ὁ.6. in Ol. 87, 2 
or 3. But the appearance of Hermocrates at Athens at any 
time after the breaking out of the Peloponnesian war involves 
the utmost improbability, and an earlier date would not be con- 
sistent with the extreme old age of Cephalus,* to say nothing of 
the statement of the scholiast on Thucydides, that Hermocrates 
was a young man B.c. 415. We can only conclude that Plato 
was either very oblivious or very careless of historical verisimi- 
litude. His selection of Hermocrates as his mouthpiece is even 





1 Quintilian VIII. 6, ὃ 63. Dionys. Halicarnass. De Compositione Verborum, 
Ρ. 208, Reiske. 

2 Noctes Attice XIV. 3: ‘Xenophon incluto illi operi Platonis, quod de optimo 
statu reipublice civitatisque administrande scriptum est, lectis ex eo duobus fere 
libris, qui primi in volgus exierant, opposuit contra scripsitque diversum regize 
administrationis genus, quod παιδείας Kvpov inscriptum est.’ 

3 See chapter XXXYV. ὃ 1. 

4 Resp. I. p. 328 Εἰ: ἐπειδὴ ἐνταῦθα ἤδη εἶ τῆς ἡλικίας ὃ δὴ ἐπὶ γήραος οὐδῷ φασι 
εἶναι οἱ ποιηταί. 


ὅ ad Thucyd, VI. 38. 


250 PLATO. 


less patriotic than his choice of Critias in the character of Jau- 
dator temporis acti. But it is very explicable on the supposition 
that his frequent visits to Sicily, in spite of the misconduct of 
Dionysius, who represented the party of this valiant oligarch, 
and had married his daughter, had enabled Plato to form a very 
high opinion of his character, and, perhaps, induced him to be- 
lieve that, if Hermocrates had succeeded in establishing himself 
at Syracuse, he would have introduced a form of government far 
superior to that of the Dionysii, and even of Dion. 

While the Republic gives us more directly Plato’s solution 
of the great problem of moral philosophy, the Philebus is one 
of Plato’s critical reviews of the systems of his contemporaries 
and predecessors in regard to the chief good of man, which was, 
with the ancients, essentially an ethical question. There can be 
no doubt that the Repudlic, in its present form, makes direct 
reference to the Philebus,’ and we should conclude that the latter 
was written expressly as an introduction both to the ethical spe- 
culations of the Republic, and to the psychological physics of 
the Timeus. The general purport of the Philebus is thus given 
by a modern writer :*-—‘ The Pytliagoreans, as interpreted by 
the rédacteur of their doctrines, Philolaus, looked upon the 
infinite (τὸ ἄπειρον) as the mere rude material element of the uni- 
verse, which, naturally devoid of all definite limits, measure, and 
rule, must receive its form, and so its positive existence, from the 
finite or limiting (τὸ πέρας ἔχον, τὸ περαῖνον, τὸ πεπερασμένον), 
which is likewise the natural element. The ideas of finite and 
infinite are also, and more commonly, represented by the terms 
“the one” and “ the many,” especially in the Platonic philosophy. 
Plato, who borrowed the Pythagorean doctrine, but extended 
and enlarged its sphere, in his elaborate inquiry into the nature 
of the summum bonum in the Philebus, in like manner places 
the infinite (or particulars as opposed to general notions), in 
which pleasure is found to consist, at the bottom of his gra- 
duated scale of moral perfection, the finite (τὸ πέρας ἔχον), 
including sciences, arts, and right opinions, occupying the place 





1 Resp. VI. p. 505 B, where the οἱ πολλοὶ are Aristippus and the general public to 
whose lower views of happiness he pandered, and the κομψότεροι are Eucleides and 
his school. 

2 Mr. E. M. Cope, in the Cambridge Essays for 1856, p. 146. 


MORAL AND POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY. 951 


next above them; the highest place of all being assigned to 
“measure, and that which is in-due measure and due season” 
(τὸ μέτριον Kai τὸ καίριον), by which Plato seems to mean the 
highest and universal moral law, which embraces all subordinate 
laws, regulates the entire system of things, and assigns to all 
their due place and order’ The doctrines,’ which Plato submits 
to his searching criticism in the Philebus, are those of the two 
Socratic schools, who took the most opposite views on the sub- 
ject of the highest good—the Cyrenaics, who held that it was 
pleasure, and the Megarics, who maintained that it was intelli- 
gence in its various manifestations. The former are represented 
in the dialogue by Philebus and his friend Protarchus, the latter 
by an unknown person, probably Eucleides himself. Plato, 
speaking in the person of Socrates, maintains that the highest 
good is not to be found in either of these states, but in one 
which he proceeds to investigate in a most elaborate and com- 
plicated argument. First of all he developes the meaning of 
‘the One’ and ‘ the Many,’ showing that this formula denotes 
the relation of monads (i.e., ideas or universals), to sensibles 
(τὰ γιγνόμενα καὶ ἄπειρα), and then argues that it is the dia- 
lectician’s first problem to find ‘the One’ in ‘the Many,’ his 
second task to find ‘the How Many, or definite quantity in 
“the One.’ For example: voice is one, but voices are innu- 
merable. And between this One and these innumerables 
intervenes a definite number of kinds of voice, which the gram- 
marian and musician ascertain and classify. Now the formula 
of the One and the Many is equally applicable to the ideas of 
pleasure and intelligence, the manifestations of both being 
unlimited, but their species limitable. Applying this to the case 
before him, Socrates maintains that, as the Good must be con- 
ceived as self-sufficing and perfect ; and as neither pleasure nor 
intelligence is by itself self-sufficing and perfect, we cannot find 
the good in either of them separately, but must seek it in a life 





1 For the etymology of καιρός, and its connexion in meaning with μέτρον see our 
note on Pindar, Ol. IX. 38, 39, and Varronianus, p. 392 note ; and for Plato’s identi- 
fication of μέτρον and καιρός, see Politicus p. 284 E: ὁπόσαι πρὸς τὸ μέτριον καὶ τὸ 
πρέπον καὶ τὸν καιρὸν καὶ τὸ δέον καὶ πανθ᾽ ὅποσα εἰς τὸ μέσον ἀπῳκίσθη τῶν ἐσχάτων. 

53 Here we have to acknowledge our obligations to Professor Thompson’s 
introductory lecture on the Philebus, delivered at Cambridge, in October, 1855. 


252 PLATO. 


which blends pleasure with intelligence. Consequently this 
mixed life is better than either of the other two. But if we 
wish to fix the relative places of pleasure and intelligence, we 
must start with a tetrad of forms or principles (εἴδη) ; namely : 
(1.) πέρας, limit; (2.) ἄπειρον, unlimited; (3.) τὸ ξυμμισγό- 
μενον (Ξε γένεσις εἰς οὐσίαν), the concrete, created being, or 
procession into being; (4.) αἴτιον, the cause, which makes up 
the third by mixing the former two. Now the mixed life is 
evidently referable to the third form—that of the genesis, or 
coming into being; as pleasure is unlimited in respect to less 
and more, the life of pleasure must belong to the second form, 
or that of the unlimited; and as intellect plans the order of 
the universe, the intellectual life must fall under the fourth 
form. ‘By these distinctions,’ says Sydenham,’ ‘ the phi- 
losopher leads Protarchus to recognize the superior excellence 
of the science of mind above all others—a science conversant in 
those subjects only, which are the same for ever. In the third 
and last argumentative part of this dialogue, those moral truths 
are shown, which it is the whole intent of it to show, in the 
following order: the first is, that neither pleasure alone, nor 
theoretical wisdom or knowledge alone, is sufficient for the 
happiness of any man ; the second is, that the best and happiest of 
all human lives is that life in which the best and highest science, 
the knowledge of true good, produces the moral virtues; the 
third is this, that in a life where pleasure and knowledge are 
thus amicably joined, and operate together for the good of the 
whole man, symmetry, harmony, and beauty appear throughout ; 
the last and highest truth, no less theological than moral, is this, 
that the cause of happiness found in such a life is the same with 
the cause of harmony, symmetry, and beauty through the uni- 
verse ; and the same with the principle and essence of moral 
virtue, namely, measure itself and truth itself, the idea of good, 
the great object of the divine mind, in which universal idea the 
true measures of all things are contained.’ 

§ 9. The physical speculations of Plato would have very little 
interest for us, if we were obliged to regard them as contri- 
butions to natural philosophy in the modern sense of the term. 





} Translation of the Philebus, London, 1779, pp. 27-29. 


PHYSICAL SPECULATIONS. 253 


Tt cannot be said, however, that Plato ever proposed to himself 
any such object. To him researches into the visible phenomena 
of nature had no special value except as enabling him to show 
how the idea of law and order and numerical symmetry is to be 
detected in the complex machinery of the outer world, so that 
here also, we discern the One in the Many, and may separate 
science from the province of opinion. 

We have some hints as to the manner in which Plato read 
the book of nature in the Phedo,’ some in the Republic; his 
general views are involved in the argumentation of the Phi- 
lebus ;* and he gives us a strangely fanciful theory respecting 
the counter revolution of the globe, and its effects on the 
inversion of human life, in the Politicus* But his book 
expressly written on this subject is the Timeus, which forms 
the second part in the intended tetralogy of dialogues begin- 
ning with the Repudlic. This work is professedly a fictitious 
κοσμοποιΐα, or history of the creation. The contemplation 
of mutable nature is taken up as a relaxation and amuse- 
ment by the abstract philosopher, and the results assumed 
merely pretend to be as probable as any others which have been 
stated.© And in freely indulging his fancy, Plato takes as 
the basis of his speculations the details which were well known 
to the students of natural science in his time. The numerical 
system of the Pythagoreans plays a prominent part in the 
Timeus ;° he makes direct reference to the theories of Hera- 
cleitus, Anaxagoras, and Empedocles; and here, as elsewhere, 
the unitarian hypothesis of the Eleatics is subjected to his cri- 
ticism.’ Plato, following Parmenides, supposes the existence 
of two worlds—the world of matter and the world of mind—the 
ὁρατὸς τόπος, or visible world, and the νοητὸς τόπος, or ideal 
world—the former being on the model of the latter.2 Now 
Plato argues that as the visible world is within the domain of 





1 Phedo, pp. 97 C, 98 B. 2 Respubl. X. pp. 614 A—62r A. 
3 Philebus, pp. 27 B sqq. 4 Politicus, pp. 269 D seqq. 
: 85. Timeus, p. 29 D: ὁ λέγων ἐγὼ ὑμεῖς τε οἱ κριταὶ φύσιν ἀνθρωπίνην ἔχομεν, ὥστε 
περὶ τούτων τὸν εἰκότα μῦθον ἀποδεχομένους πρέπει τούτου μηδὲν ἔτι πέρα ζητεῖν. 
6. Ibid. p. 34 C sqq. 
7 See Professor Thompson’s note on Butler’s Lectwres, II. p. 189. 
8 Timeus, p. 29 E sqq. : 


254 PLATO. 


the senses, it is for this reason one of the things which are 
liable to generation and decay. It must therefore have been 
created, i.e., it must have come into being. And its maker 
could be no other than the One, τὸ ἕν, of the Ionics, and this 
is the Entity, τὸ ov, of the Eleatics, which reduced to order the 
infinite plurality of visible substances, and so exhibited itself as 
the formative principle. From the symmetry and order dis- 
cernible in this lower world, it is clear, Plato says, that the 
Creator must have constructed it after the model or pattern of 
a perfect and eternal world, and in order that this might be 
done in the most perfect manner possible, he made it ‘ a living 
animal, gifted with intelligence, by enduing it with a living soul.’? 
The body of this animal was composed of the four elements (and 
here Plato combines and modifies the theories of Empedocles 
and Anaxagoras),’? and the soul of the world was not, as the 
Eleatic pantheism would have maintained, God himself, but an 
emanation and product of that intelligence which is the cause of 
' all things.’ 

Both in the Timeus and in the Philebus Plato speaks of in- 
telligence as very near akin to the causative principle. In the 
Philebus he says :* ‘ We find that fire, water, air, and earth must 
naturally be in the composition of all bodies. These elements, 
which we find in individual bodies, receive their being from the 
elements which we find in the universe, and this little body of 
ours owes its nourishment, and all that it has received or 
possesses, to the great body of the world. Now these bodies 
of ours are animated by souls; and from whence should they 
derive these souls, if the great body of the universe, which has 
all the same elements with them, only in far greater purity and 
perfection, did not possess a soul as our bodies do? Since then 
we admit in all bodies four sorts of being—the limit, the un- 
limited, the compound of these, and the cause—and since we 
find in the part of the universe to which we belong that there are 
causes which create souls, produce health of the body, and effect 
cures for diseases of the body, and causes, which put together 
other compositions and amend them when impaired, all of these 





1 Timeus, p. 30 B. 2 Ibid. pp. 31 B—32 C, 53 C—s56 OC. 
3 Jbid. p. 35 A. 4 Philebus, p. 29 A. 


DOCTRINE OF NUMBERS. 255 


causes having names which betoken some kind of wisdom or 
skill,—this being the case, we cannot but think that the whole 
heaven, possessing the same four sorts of beings, but possessing 
them pure and undepraved, has for its cause the nature of those 
things which are most beautiful and noble, a cause which may 
most justly be called wisdom and mind; and as wisdom and 
mind cannot be without soul, it follows that the world has a 
soul and mind from the power of the cause, and that mind is 
of the nature of the cause of all things.’ In thus allowing a 
cause and beginning to the world, Plato naturally maintained, 
in opposition to Parmenides, the reality of time.’ As the 
multiplicity of things (τὰ πολλά) presumes the universal (ro 
ἕν), and as the limit controls the infinite, so there must be 
time as the image and product, the limitation or bound of 
eternity. | 

The recognition of an analogy between the soul of man and 
the soul of the universe, and the perception of a harmony in 
each, is naturally connected in Plato’s speculations with the 
view of the Pythagoreans that numbers are the principles and 
essence of all things, and that the world subsists by a numerical 
harmony,’ a view which Heracleitus adopted under a modified 
form.’ ‘The system of the heavenly bodies is, according to this 
view, represented by the intervals of the musical scale, these 
intervals making what is called the Platonic tetractys, branching 
from unity on one side by doubling, and on the other side by 
trebling the preceding number; thus: 1, 2, 4, 8, and 1, 3, 9, 
2η. He estimates the durability of his Republic by a still 
more complicated numerical process, involving, however, the 
mean proportionals 12 and 18 between the last two terms in 
these series, and introducing the γαμήλιον διάγραμμα or right- 
angled triangle, of which the sides are 3, 4, and 5.° Even in his 
Laws we find that Plato limits his citizens to 5040 ‘ for the sake 





1 See Timeeus, pp. 37 A, 38 B, &c. 
2 Aristotle, Metaphys. A. I. c. 6, p. 987, Ὁ. 11] 


3 Plato, Sympos. p. 187 A. - ‘s 
4 See Stallbaum’s note on the Timeus, p. 35 B. The figure Z, 
presumed is δ: της “ἢ 


5 The writer of these pages has examined the celebrated passage (Respublica, 


256 PLATO. 


of a fitting number,’’ this number being the continued product 
of the first seven digits, a calculation having the same mystical — 
value as the discovery that 27, the last of the seven terms in the 
double tetractys, is both the sum of the other six terms, and 
also equal to the sum of the first six digits after unity. There 
is the same sort of arbitrary fancy in the astronomy of Plato, 
as exhibited in the Timeus ;? and, on the whole, we must admit, 
with a modern writer, that ‘the Timeus is a physical romance, 
with a mighty moral.’* At the same time, the speculations of 
Plato, wild and fanciful as they seem to us, have very often 
made nearer approximations to the truth than the more 
elaborate and serious investigations of his pupil Aristotle ; as, 
for example, ‘in his notions of a centripetal force, of the causes 
of gravity, of antipodes, and of the nullity of the popular dis- 
tinction of up and down.’* And if his separate conjectures had 
been entirely devoid of truth, or even plausibility, we could not 
fail to recognize, as quite worthy of a great philosopher, the 
general principles of his theory, and the grand truth with which 
he starts, that the moving cause of creation was the unenvying 
goodness of the Creator, and His wish that all things should as 
far as possible resemble Himself.’ 

δ το. The style of Plato is in every way worthy of his posi- 
tion in universal literature; and the critical taste of modern 
scholars has fully confirmed the general encomium of Aristotle, 
that ‘all his dialogues exhibit extraordinary acuteness, elabo- 
rate elegance, bold originality, and curious speculation.’® 





VII. p. 546), ina special essay ‘on Plato’s Number’ in the 7’ransactions of the Phi- 

lological Society, Vol. I. No. 8, and has shown that the number itself is 216= 6%, 

and that the calculations involved are the proportion 8:12::18:27, and the equa- 
3 3 8 8 

tions (3 x 8) ΞΞΊΟΟ Χ wand (4 x 5) = EES EAC _ 1000 55. 

1 Plato, Leges, V. p. 737: ἀριθμοῦ τινος ἕνεκα προσήκοντος., In the Republic, 
1X. p. 587 C, because the tyrant is nine times as wretched as the oligarch, 9° or 
729 represents his misery. 

2 Timeeus, p. 35 B. 

3 Butler’s Lectures on Ancient Philosophy, ΤΙ. 196. 

4 Professor Thompson’s note on Butler’s Lectwres, II. p. 171. 

5 Timeus, p. 29 D, E. 

6 Aristot. Pol. II. 6, 5: τὸ μὲν οὖν περιττὸν ἔχουσι πάντες οἱ τοῦ Σωκράτους λόγοι 
καὶ τὸ κομψὸν καὶ τὸ καινοτόμον καὶ τὸ ζητητικόν᾽ καλῶς δὲ πάντα ἴσως χαλεπόν. 
The last words show that these expressions are not ironical, Mr, Congreve says, 


STYLE AND DICTION. 257 


Paneetius used to call him the Homer ofphilosophers,’ and others 
declared that, if Jupiter himself had spoken Greek, he would 
have adopted the majestic dignity of the Platonic eloquence.’ 
The celebrated critic, Dionysius of Halicarnassus, though he 
reserves the highest stretch of his admiration for Demosthenes, 
is inclined to admit that no master of eloquence could success- 
fully compete for the second place with Plato.* He considers 
him, in fact, as the best example of the middle or mixed style 
of composition, which was initiated by Thrasymachus, and 
systematically taught and exemplified by Isocrates.* This inter- 
mediate or mixed style combined the simple diction of Lysias 
with the more ponderous eloquence of Thucydides and Gorgias, 
and the process in the case of Plato is thus described by 
Dionysius ἢ ‘ He was nurtured in the Socratic dialogues, meagre 
and exact as they are in the fullest sense, but did not abide 
in them, being enamoured of the language’ of Gorgias and 
Thucydides ; accordingly, it is not surprising that he acquired 
some of their characteristic faults as well as their excellences.’ 
The same critic classes the style of Plato with that of Herodotus 
and Demosthenes, as exhibiting in the highest degree those 
pauses and changes of rhythmical structure, and that variety of 
elegant figures, which he considers as the greatest perfections of - 
style ;’ and he places the philosopher below the great orator 





in his note on the passage: ‘This just and high compliment on his master’s 
writings is not easy to translate. It bears witness, if such were needed, to Aris- 
totle’s careful study and correct appreciation of their beauties, as well as their 
more solid merits. I venture the following translation: All the dialogues of Plato 
alike are characterized by brilliancy, grace, originality, and profound inquiry.’ 

1 Cic, Tuse. Disp. I. 32, ὃ 79. 

2 Cic. Brut. 31, § 121: ‘quis enim uberior in dicendo Platone? Jovem aiunt 
philosophi, si Greece loquatur, sic loqui.’ Dionys. Hal. de adm. vi dic. in Dem. 
xxiii. p. 1024, Reiske: ἤδη δέ τινων ἤκουσα ἐγώ λεγόντων, ws εἰ καὶ παρὰ θεοῖς 
διάλεκτός ἐστιν, ἣ τὸ τῶν ἀνθρώπων κέχρηται γένος, οὐκ ἄλλως ὁ βασιλεὺς ὧν αὐτῶν 
διαλέγεται θεὸς []. Ζεὺς] ἢ ὡς Πλάτων. 

3 De adm. vi Dem. p. 1043: Πλάτων γάρ ἐστιν ὁ ταῦτα γράφων᾽ ὃς εἰ μὴ καὶ τὰ 
πρωτεῖα οἴσεται τῆς λέξεως, περί γε τῶν δευτερείων πολὺν ἀγῶνα παρέξει τοῖς διαμιλ- 
λησομένοις. 

4 Id. ibid. pp. 958, 1083. 5 Td. ibid. p. 968. 

6 κατασκευή, i.e. the apparatus of words as distinguished from their arrangement, 
their copia verborum in fact; see above, chapter XXIV. § 3, note. 

7 De Compos. Verborum, p. 133. 

Vou, 11. 5 


258 PLATO. 


chiefly because the former departs occasionally from that 
judicious choice of words by which Demosthenes is dis- 
tinguished. ‘ Plato,’ he says,’ ‘was most admirable in per- 
ceiving the harmony and rhythm of style, and if he ‘had been 
as excellent in the selection as he was in the composition of his 
words, he might have outstripped Demosthenes, or made his 
superiority doubtful; as it is, he commits some faults in his 
choice of expressions, especially when he aims at ἃ lofty, 
elegant, and elaborate (ἐγκατάσκευον) phraseology.’ In comparing 
these two masters of Greek eloquence, Dionysius has given us 
a very felicitous analogy. ‘It seems to me,’ he says,’ ‘ that we 
should not err if we compared the diction of Plato to a meadow 
gay with flowers, and furnished with pleasant arbours and 
transient gratifications ; whereas, the language of Demosthenes 
might be likened to a fruitful field, rich in produce, and want- 
ing neither the necessaries of life nor the superfluities of enjoy- 
ment.’ Although these remarks of Dionysius will be endorsed 
by most of the critical readers of Plato in our days, it will be felt 
that in some respects he has not done full justice to the literary 
merits of the great philosopher. In Plato the powers of the 
imagination were just as conspicuous as those of reasoning and 
reflexion; he had all the chief characteristics of a poet, espe- 
cially of a dramatic poet; and if his rank as a philosopher had 
been lower than it is, he would still have stood unrivalled, 
except by Shakspere, in the power of exhibiting dramatically, 
and in the form of dialogue, a consistent development of cha- 
racter, and so giving to his interlocutors all that is required in 
a lifelike representation of the personages whose opinions he 
wishes to combat or defend. The slightest touch sometimes lends 
a finish to the picture, as when the equestrian Antipho is found 
in the act of ordering a bit,* or the bare-footed Socrates either 
in his ordinary* or his exceptional attire.» The more elaborate 
and fanciful pictures which he introduces are not less remark- 
able for their descriptive power, than the dramatic incidents are 
for their vivid reality. Nothing can be better told than the 





1 De Compos. Verborum, p. 117. ? De adm. vi dic. in Dem. p. 1056. 
3 Parmenides, p. 127 A. 4 Phedrus, p. 229 A. 
ὅ Sympos. p. 174 A. 


STYLE AND DICTION. 259 


strange story of the world’s inverted rotation in the Politicus,' 
or the allegory of the cavern,’ and the tale of Er, the Armenian, 
in the Republic? or the fable about the soul’s state after 
death in the Gorgias.* The periodical structure of the sentence 
in Plato is principally distinguished by an intentional laxity, and 
by the frequent introduction of explanatory circumstances, 
which, either following or preceding the main predication, give 
to the whole an appearance of grammatical irregularity... Many 
of the peculiarities of Plato’s style are due to his adoption 
of the language of ordinary conversation, with its conventional. 
words and phrases, and its abrupt transitions.. He has few 
technical words, and none of any importance, except the terms 
by which he designates the typical forms of things and the 
general conceptions by which they are represented in the mind.’ 





1 Polit. p. 269 D sqq. 2 Resp. VII. pp. 514—517 B. 

3 Thid. X. pp. 614 A—6ar A. 4. Gorg. pp. 523 A—526 C. 

5 See Dissen’s Essay de structwrd periodorum oratorid prefixed to his edition of 
Demosthenes De Corond, pp. LXX. sqq. 

6 As for example his use of αὐτίκα, πολλάκις for lows, κινδυνεύω for ἔοικα, ἄλλοτι 
for ἄλλο τι ἤ, his asyndeton in the adverb πάντως, &e. 

7 In Plato’s language εἶδος is the mental apprehension, and ἰδέα its counterpart 
in nature, but the words are often used as synonyms. See Professor Thompson’s 
note on Butler’s Lectures, vol. II., p. 127. 


s 2 


260 


CHAPTER XL. 


ARISTOTLE. 


§ 1. Life of Aristotle. § 2. General view of his writings. § 3. His metaphysics 
and psychology. § 4. Logic. § 5. Rhetoric and criticism. § 6. Moral philo- 
sophy. § 7. Politics. § 8. Natural history and general physics. ὃ 9. Mis- 
cellanies, ὃ 10, Form and style of his writings. 


δι. ‘TP\HE Master of them that know,’ as Dante calls Aris- 

totle,’ occupies a position among the leaders of human 
thought, scarcely inferior to that which we have claimed for his 
teacher Plato. Indeed, one modern writer has not hesitated to 
say that every man is born either a Platonist or an Aristotelian,’ 
meaning by this that Plato and Aristotle represented the two 
modes in which men philosophize, if they philosophize at all. 
It would, however, be more true to say, historically, that the 
influence of Aristotle’s writings has been felt directly or in- 
directly, wherever it is not anticipated or superseded by a 
method of reasoning which may be traced back to his great 
teacher. To treat, therefore, of Aristotle in a manner suitable to 
his importance, would involve a distinct literary effort not less con- 
siderable than that which would be implied in a similar treatment 
of Plato’s writings ; and there are not a few works on the subject 
to which the student might be referred with great profit to him- 
self.2 For our present purpose it is sufficient to deal with the 





1 Inferno, IV. 131: 

Vidi "1 maestro di color che sanno 
Seder tra filosofica famiglia: 
Tutti ’ammiran, tutti onor gli fanno. 

2 Coleridge, Table Talk (July 2nd, 1830, I. p. 182): ‘ Every man is born an Aris- 
totelian or a Platonist. I do not think it possible that any one born an Aristotelian 
can become a Platonist ; and I am sure no born Platonist can ever change into an 
Aristotelian. They are the two classes of men, beside which it is next to impossible 
to conceive athird, The one considers reason a quality or attribute; the other con- 
siders it a power. I believe that Aristotle never could get to understand what 
Plato meant by an idea.’ 

3 As for example, the works of Stahr, Jourdain, and Brandis, 


LIFE OF ARISTOTLE. 261 


questions of literary history which are involved in a general 
survey of Aristotle’s life and labours. Ξ 
The materials for Aristotle’s life are very scanty, and all the 
ancient biographies of the philosopher are full of exaggerations 
and misstatements. Nevertheless the dates are tolerably accu- 
rate, and we can form to ourselves a general picture of his 
career which is sufficient for all the purposes of literary history.’ 
Aristotle’s life may be divided into five epochs; the first in- 
cludes the period of his boyhood and youth; the second, his 
residence at Athens, as a pupil of Plato; the third, his three 
years’ sojourn at Assos after Plato’s death ; the fourth, his esta- 
blishment in Macedonia, as tutor to Alexander; and the fifth, 
his final settlement at Athens, as a teacher, during the last 
thirteen years of his life. 
᾿ First Period—Anistotie was born at Stageirus, or Stageira, 
one of the Chalcidian cities on the Strymonian gulf. Originally 
an Andrian colony, it had received an accession of population 
from Chalcis, in Eubcea, and though not in itself a place of any 
importance, it was a member of the Olynthian league, and 
shared in the destruction of those Greek cities which resisted 
the ambition of Philip. Aristotle’s father, Nicomachus, be- 
longed to the clan or guild of the Asclepiads, and was therefore 
a member of a family in which the medical profession was here- 
ditary.? His skill as a practitioner and his reputation as a 
man of science had recommended him to Amyntas, the father 
of Philip, at whose court he lived as the king’s medical ad- 
viser and confidential friend. Phzestis, the mother of Aris- 
. totle, was descended from one of the Chalcidian colonists of 
Stageirus, and it is worthy of remark that Aristotle died at 





1 Tn the account of Aristotle’s career which is given in the text, the author feels 
that he is greatly indebted to the admirable lectures on the Hthics and Politics 
which Dr. Thirlwall delivered at Trinity College, Cambridge, in 1833, and which 
were prefaced by an elaborate discussion of Aristotle’s literary history. Mr. 
Blakesley, who probably enjoyed the advantage of hearing these lectures, published, 
in 1839, a very clear and able Life of Aristotle, including a critical discussion 
of some questions of literary history connected with his works. To this book the 
writer has occasionally referred with much profit. And he has had before him 
Stahr’s Aristotelia (Halle, 1830), which is quite a storehouse of materials. 

2 See below, chapter XLIV. ὃ 2. 

3 Diogenes says: cuvveBiw ᾿Αμύντᾳ τῷ Μακεδόνων βασιλεῖ ἰατροῦ καὶ φίλου χρείᾳ. 


262 ARISTOTLE. 


Chalcis, the metropolis of his maternal relatives. Aristotle was 
born in Ol. 99, 1. B.c. 384, two years before his great contem- 
porary Demosthenes,’ and he died in the same year with that 
orator and his rival Hypereides. We do not know when his 
parents died. It appears that they were dead when he went to 
Athens, at the age of eighteen, and it is also probable that he 
had lost both his father and mother at a much earlier period ; 

_ for we are told that he was for some little time under the guar- 
dianship of one Proxenus of Atarneus. That his education 
was at least partly undertaken by his father may be inferred 
from the fact that he had acquired some practical acquaintance 
with the hereditary art of medicine ; and the partiality, which 
he exhibited in his later years, for all subjects connected with 
natural history, may have been due to his early initiation into 
this branch of study. His estate must have been well managed, 
for we find him, as a young man, at Athens, living in perfect 
leisure, and not only so, but able to collect books, to dress well, 
and indulge in gaiety and luxury. He retained a deep sense 
of the obligations conferred upon him by his guardian, for he 
afterwards adopted Nicanor, the son of Proxenus, and appointed 
him joint guardian with Antipater of his own son Nicomachus. 
And his will gives directions for the setting up of a statue in 
honour of Proxenus and his wife. 

Second Period.—Without noticing the contradictory accounts 
that have been given of Aristotle’s early life——that he squan- 
dered his property, and became a soldier or a vender of medi- 
cines,*—we pass on to the first visit to Athens in B.c. 367, when 
Plato had just started on his second journey to Sicily. This. 
latter circumstance explains the statement of Ammonius that. 
Aristotle first studied under Socrates, a statement obviously 





1 This is the usual opinion, adopted by Clinton, Fasti Hellenici, p. 104. Other 
scholars have come to the conclusion that the great orator and the great philoso- 
pher were born in the same year. See Stahr, Avristotelia, p. 31 ; Thirlwall, ‘On the 
birth year of Demosthenes,’ Philol. Mus. II. pp. 389 qq. 

2 Atheneus VIII. p. 354; Allian, V.H. V. 9; Aristocles apud Euseb. Prep. 
£v. XV. 2, p. 791 A.: πῶς yap οἷόν τε νέον μὲν ὄντα καταφαγεῖν αὐτὸν Thy πατρῴαν 
οὐσίαν, ἔπειτα δὲ ἐπὶ τὸ στρατεύεσθαι συνῶσαι, κακῶς δὲ πράττοντα ἐν τούτοις ἐπὶ 
τὸ φαρμακοπωλεῖν ἐλθεῖν, ἔπειτα ἀναπεπταμένου τοῦ Πλάτωνος περιπάτου πᾶσι 
παραβαλεῖν αὐτόν ; ἤ πῶς ἄν τις ἀποδέξαιτο Τιμαίου τοῦ Ταυρομενείτου λέγοντος 
ἐν ταῖς ἱστορίαις ἀδόξου θύρας αὐτὸν ἰατρείου καὶ τὰς τυχούσας ὀψὲ τῆς ἡλικίας 
κλεῖσαι; 


LIFE OF ARISTOTLE. 263° 


inconsistent with chronology, but quite explicable on the sup- 
position that the story meant to inform us, that he studied in 
the school of Socrates, and not under Plato in the first instance. 
For in Plato’s absence his school was conducted by Hera- 
cleides of Pontus, and Aristotle may have received his first 
lessons from this Socratic philosopher.' There is no doubt, 
however, that on Plato’s return, Aristotle became his regular 
hearer, and indeed the chief ornament of his school. That the 
characters of the master and pupil were quite uncongenial, and 
their intellectual tendencies diametrically opposed, is sufficiently 
well known. But beyond this there is no foundation for the 
report that Plato and Aristotle were personally on bad terms, 
and that the latter was not only unfriendly but ungrateful to his 
teacher. On the one hand, it is clear that Plato used to 
express a very high opinion of Aristotle, whom he called ‘the 
soul of his school,’? and whose house he designated as ‘ the house 
of the reader.’* On the other hand, we are told that Aristotle 
erected an altar to Plato after his death, with an inscription 
describing him as ‘a man whom the bad could not even praise 
without sacrilege ;’* and in opposing the Platonic doctrine of 
ideas in a passage of the Nicomachean Ethics, which has 
become proverbial as an expression of the duty of preferring 
our conscience to our private predilections,’ Aristotle says ° that 
he feels himself obliged to enter on this discussion, ‘ although 





1 Mr. Blakesley (p. 18, note) supposes that Xenocrates was mentioned as Aris- 
totle’s first instructor, and that his name has been carelessly or officiously altered 
into that of Socrates. 

3 νρῦς τῆς SiarpiBfs(Philoponus, De eternitate mundi adversus Proclum). 

3 οἶκος ἀναγνώστου, Pseudo-Ammonius. 

4 Βωμὸν᾽ Ἀριστοτέλης ἐνιδρύσατο τόνδε Πλάτωνος 
ἀνδρὸς ὃν οὐδ᾽ αἰνεῖν τοῖσι κακοῖσι θέμις. 

5 The usual form of the proverb is ‘Amicus Plato, amicus Socrates, sed magis 
amica veritas.’ It is stated that Plato himself used to confess: gids μὲν 
Σωκράτης, ἀλλὰ φιλτάτη ἡ ἀλήθεια. He makes Socrates remark (in the Phedo, p. 
gt B): σμικρὸν φροντίσαντες Σωκράτους, τῆς δὲ ἀληθείας πολὺ μᾶλλον. And healso 
says, in the Republic, X. p. 595 B: καὶ τοι φιλέα γέ τίς με καὶ αἰδὼς ἐκ παιδὸς 
ἔχουσα περὶ Ὁμήρου ἀποκωλύει λέγειν---ἀλλ᾽ οὐ γὰρ πρό γε τῆς ἀληθείας τιμητέος͵ 
ἀνήρ, which is just the sentiment expressed by Aristotle. Probably this passage 
or that in the Phedo was the reference which Stahr could not recal (p. 59). 

6 Ethica Nicom. Τ. 6,8 τ. Mr. Blakesley suggests that the phrase τὰ οἰκεῖα 
ἀναιρεῖν is an allusion to such cases as that of Iphigenia (p. 27); others suppose 
that the philosopher is referring to opinions, not to persons. 


264 ARISTOTLE. 


the inquiry is repugnant to our feelings, because the doctrine 
of ideas was introduced by persons whom we regard with affee- 
tion (φίλους ἄνδρας) ; but it would seem to be better, and indeed 
our duty, to sacrifice even our own children for the vindication 
of truth, especially as we are philosophers; for between two 
friends it is a religious obligation to prefer the truth.’ There could 
have been no animosity in the mind of a man who approached 
a speculative discussion in such a spirit as this. The story that 
Xenocrates was mixed up in a quarrel between Plato and Aris- 
totle is sufficiently refuted by the circumstance that, after the 
death of the former, Aristotle and Xenocrates travelled together 
at Atarneus. 

During the period of nearly twenty years which Aristotle 
spent at Athens, he was not merely a hearer of Plato and a 
learner. ‘The house of the reader’ fully justified its name ; 
- Aristotle was engaged continually in the most profound and 
varied studies, and was laying the foundations of that encyclo- 
peedia of learning, which he considered it as his special vocation 
to elaborate. It was at this time, in all probability, that he 
drew up his lost work on the various systems of rhetoric which 
had appeared before his time.’ Perhaps, too, he now wrote his 
book on the principles of government adopted by different 
states,’ and commenced, at all events, his grand historico-political 
work on the Constitutions of 255 different Commonwealths.’ 
Anecdotes are preserved which tell of his intense application 
to his studies. But he was anything but a book-worm, and in 
his hours of relaxation he exhibited an attention to dress and 
a love of pleasure, which were not usually observed in pro- 
fessed philosophers. He was a public teacher, too, as well as a 
writer ; and it seems that he adopted the profession of a rhetori- 
cian, which was the ostensible avocation of the Sophists, and was 
then practised with eminent success by ‘ the old man eloquent,’ 
Isocrates. Indeed it is stated, and we see no reason to doubt 





1 Συναγωγὴ Τεχνῶν. Cic. de Oratore, 11, 38, de Inventione, II. 2. The nature 
of such a work is well exemplified by Spengel’s essay under the same title ; Stutt- 
gardt, 1828. 

2 Δικαιώματα πολέων, Diog. Laért. V. 26. 

3 See Neumann, Aristotelis Rerumpublicarum Reliquiw, reprinted in. the 
Oxford edition of Aristotle’s works, vol. X. pp. 233 sqq. 


LIFE OF ARISTOTLE. 265 


the truth of the story, that Aristotle set up his rhetorical school 
in direct opposition to that of Isocrates.' Cicero says distinctly’ 
that ‘when Aristotle saw Isocrates flourishing and surrounded 
by the most illustrious pupils, having-transferred his disputa- 
tions from forensic and popular subjects to the mere cultivation 
of an elegant style, he suddenly changed the whole form of his 
teaching, and by a slight alteration in a verse of the Philoctetes, 
where the poet said: “ it was disgraceful to hold one’s peace, 
and suffer barbarians,’—he said: “and suffer Isocrates to 
speak.” Accordingly, he adorned and embellished the whole 
science of rhetoric, and combined a knowledge of things with 
the practice of speaking.’ The celebrated quotation in refer- 
ence to Isocrates, thus put into the mouth of Aristotle, is taken 
from a scene in the Philoctetes of Euripides, in which an em- 
bassy from Troy offers that hero the throne; and when the 
foreign orator has concluded his speech, Ulysses begins his 
reply by saying, that, whatever may be his deficiencies, yet, on 
behalf of the Greek armament, it is disgraceful to leave all the 
speaking to a barbarian. And though the Stagirite, himself a 
resident alien at Athens, could not with propriety. class the 
native Athenian Isocrates with the un-Greek orator of the 
play, still he may have regarded the affected style of the veteran 
rhetorician as tending to corrupt the purity of the Hellenic 
idiom, and so he might say—combining in one sentence both 
the word which he omitted and the proper name which he 


substituted :— 
When Greece at large demands a bold reply, 
*Tis great disgrace to sit in silence by, 
᾿ And leave Isocrates unchecked to teach 
The outlandish jargon of his fulsome speech. 





1 See Spengel, Συναγωγὴ Τεχνῶν, p. 167 544. 

2 De Oratore, III. 35, ὃ 141 (ef. Orator. c. 13. Quintil. Znst. Or. TIT. 1, 14). 
Cicero’s words are: ‘Itaque ipse Aristoteles, quum florere Isocratem nobilitate 
discipulorum videret, quod ipse suas disputationes a caussis forensibus et civilibus 
ad inanem sermonis elegantiam transtulisset, mutavit repente totam formam 
prope disciplinz sux, versumque quendam Philoctetze paullo secus dixit. Tle 
enim twrpe sibi ait esse tacere, quum barbaros ; hic autem quum Jsocratem pateretur 
dicere. Itaque ornavit et illustravit doctrinam illam omnem rerumque cogni- 
tionem cum orationis exercitatione conjunxit.’ 

3 Plutarch, Moral. p. 1108 B, Diog. Laért. V. 3. The words are: 

ὑπέρ ye μέντοι παντὸς Ελλήνων στρατοῦ 
αἰσχρὸν σιωπᾶν, βαρβάρους δ᾽ ἐὰν λέγειν, 


266. ARISTOTLE. 


For he may have considered the rhetoric of Isocrates as de- 
praved by some of the florid ornaments of the Sophistie schools, 
and it must be admitted that even the language of this pupil of 
Gorgias and Tisias is not always free from a taint of foreign 
idiom, which is shown in the occasional adoption of unusual 
forms and inflexions. The other story, that it was Xenocrates, 
and not Isocrates, whom he introduced into this sarcastic 
parody, is set aside by the friendly relations between him and 
that teacher, and by the inapplicability of the verse to any but 
an orator. It seems, too, that in his treatise on rhetorical 
systems he handled Isocrates very severely, insomuch that the 
rhetorician’s scholar, Cephisodorus, or Cephisodotus, thought it 
necessary to come forward in his defence with a treatise in four 
books, which not only met the criticisms but attacked the 
moral character of the assailant... Why, with all this, Aristotle 
so often quotes from Isocrates in his later treatise on rhetoric, 
we shall see when we come to speak of that work. 

Third Period.—On the death of Plato, in .c. 347, but not 
necessarily in consequence of that event, Aristotle accepted an 
invitation from Hermias, the tyrant of Atarneus and Assos, to 
visit him in one of those Mysian cities. Hermias, who had 
been the eunuch, and probably chief minister, of Eubulus, a 
Bithynian banker who had established an independent mo- 
narchy in Mysia, had spent some time at Athens, and had 
studied there under Plato and Aristotle ;? and his invitation to 
Aristotle, in which Xenocrates was no doubt included, probably 
originated in a wish for literary society and a renewed acquain- 
tance with his two fellow-students. Their residence at the 
court of Hermias was of short duration. In .Β.0. 345 the 
Persians, under a Rhodian captain of mercenaries, named 
Mentor, advanced against Atarneus; Hermias was decoyed by 
the treacherous promises of this leader, sent up to Susa and 
strangled there; and his cities fell into the hands of the 
Persians.*? The two philosophers made their escape to Myti- 
lene, taking with them Pythias, the sister and adopted daughter 





1 Aristocles apud Euseb. Pr. Zv. II. p. 792 A; Athenzus, II. p. 60 E. 
3 Strabo, XIII. p. 126. 
3 Strabo, οὐδὲ supra ; Diodor. XVI. 52-54. 


LIFE OF ARISTOTLE. 267 


of Hermias, whom Aristotle married in gratitude and friendship, 
and in order to protect her under the destitution in which the 
death of Hermias had left her.’ This connexion. exposed 
Aristotle to the most virulent calumny, and he was obliged to 
explain and defend his marriage in a letter to Antipater, which 
is still extant; and does him the greatest credit. Pythias died 
not long after, leaving Aristotle one daughter, and it is a touching 
circumstance that, in his will, he directs the bones of his wife to 
be taken up and laid in his grave, wherever he might be buried, 
according, as. he says, to her injunctions. He honoured ~the 
memory of Hermias in a scoliwm, or drinking-song in praise of 
virtue, which is still extant,? and also erected a statue to his 
memory. at Delphi, with an inscription stating how he had been 
slain, not in open fight, ‘ but because he had trusted to the 
honour of a perfidious villain.’* 

Fourth Period.—While residing at Mytilene, in B.c. 343, 
Aristotle received from Philip of Macedon, with whom he had 
some previous acquaintance, and to whom he was at all events 
recommended by the intimacy between Amyntas and Nico- 
machus, an invitation to go to Pella, and undertake the literary 
education of Alexander, who was at that time thirteen years 
old. This charge lasted about three years. The previous 
teachers of the young prince had been Lysimachus, an Acar- 
nanian, and Leonidas, a relation of his mother Olympias; the 
latter a. rough soldier, and the former. a dexterous_ flatterer. 
Under the discipline of the one he gained the contempt of 
danger and luxury which always distinguished him; under the 
management of the other he became intolerant of the truth, 





1 Aristocles apud Eusebium, ubi supra. In the letter to Antipater, the per- 
sonal qualities of Pythias are mentioned as an additional reason for the marriage ; 
Aristotle says she was σώφρων καὶ ἀγαθή, and the circumstance mentioned in the 
text shows that her husband was really attached to her. 

2 Athenzus, p. 696; Stobeus, Serm. I. -p..2; Diog. Laért. V. 2. He com- 
pares his hero to Hercules, the Dioscori, Achilles, and Ajax: ‘they died for thee, 
O virtue, and for the sake of thy dear form he, too, who_was reared in the lap of 
Atarneus, renounced the bright beams of the sun.’ 

3 The inscription runs thus (Anthol. Pal. appendix 8) :— 

Τόνδε ποτ᾽, οὐχ ὁσίως παραβὰς μακάρων θέμιν ἁγνήν, 
ἔκτείνεν ἹΤερσῶν τοξοφόρων βασιλεύς, 

οὐ φανερῶς λόγχῃ φονίοις ἐν ἀγῶσι κρατήσας 
ἀλλ᾽ ἀνδρὸς πίστει χρησάμενος δολίου. 


268 ARISTOTLE. 


and eager for servile compliances, even to the extent of deifi- 
cation. From neither of them could he get much of literature 
or philosophy. All his love of books and science was due to 
the better tastes with which Aristotle inspired him. He might 
have got to the Punjab without the education which he had re- 
ceived from Leonidas and Lysimachus, for he had all the ele- 
ments of a conqueror in his nature. But it was Aristotle who 
made him what Plutarch describes him as being—a lover of 
language, learning, and literature. It was Aristotle’s corrected 
edition of the Iliad which was Alexander’s travelling companion, 
and was placed with his dagger under his pillow at night.2 The 
literary tastes which Aristotle instilled into him are exhibited 
in the letter to Harpalus, in which Alexander, at that time in 
the extremity of Asia, requests that a collection of historical, 
dramatic, and lyrical works should be sent to him.* That 
Aristotle had introduced. Alexander to the more abstruse parts 
of philosophy is shown by the celebrated letter in which the 
king complains of the publication of the esoteric works.‘ It is 
clear too that Aristotle took great pains to enlarge Alexander’s 
ideas of government. For this purpose he wrote for him a 
treatise on monarchy. Not that Alexander’s liberal policy is to 
be referred to the influence of the philosopher. On the contrary, 
Plutarch tells us that Alexander’s attempt to amalgamate the 
Greeks and barbarians was in spite of the advice of Aristotle, 
who recommended him to treat the Greeks like a general 
(ἡγεμονικῶς) and the barbarians like a master (δεσποτικῶς), 
and in his Politics Aristotle recognizes an essential distinction 
between the Hellenic world and all without it. In the in- 
structions which he gave to his illustrious pupil,’ Aristotle did 
not forget his hereditary profession of medicine, which the king 





1 Plutarch (Vita Alexandri, c. 8), attributes this to Alexander’s natural dis- 
position: ἣν δὲ καὶ pices φιλολόγος καὶ φιλομαθὴς καὶ φιλαναγνώστης. But these 
tastes are acquired and not inherent. 

2 Plutarch, c. 8, on the authority of Onesicritus. 

3 The books sent to him were the works of Philistus, many of the tragedies of 
Euripides, Sophocles, and Auschylus, and the dithyrambs of Telestes and 
Philoxenus (Plutarch, whi supra). 

4 Plutarch, Vita Alex. c. 7; Aulus Gellius, WV. A. XX. 5. 

5 Plutarch, De Vitd et Fort. Alexandri, p. 329. 

6 Plutarch, Vita Alex. c. 8: δοκεῖ δέ μοι καὶ τὸ φιλιατρεῖν ᾿Αλεξάνδρῳ προσ- 


LIFE OF ARISTOTLE. 269 


sometimes practised for the benefit of his friends; and it seems 
that Alexander had a decided predilection for natural history 
in general. 

Aristotle made use of his influence with Philip to induce 
him to rebuild his native city of Stageirus, and to restore it to 
more than its former splendour. Plutarch says that he built 
a temple to the Nymphs, which served for a Lyceum.’ Aris- 
totle drew up a constitution for the resuscitated community,’ 
and occasionally retired thither from Pella. There were some 
walks and seats at Stageirus called after Aristotle, and in after- 
times the inhabitants celebrated an annual festival called the 
Aristotelia.* 

It is not probable that the tuition of Alexander lasted more 
than two or three years. When about sixteen the young prince 
had sovereign power at court during the absence of Philip. He 
fought at Cheroneia in 338 B.c., and afterwards engaged in 
state intrigues till his father’s death in 336 B.c., so that the 
connexion between the tutor and pupil could not have been 
uninterrupted after the latter had attained his sixteenth year. 
Callisthenes, who accompanied Alexander to Asia, Marsyas, the 
brother of Antigonus, afterwards king of Lycia and Pamphylia, 
and Theophrastus, Aristotle’s successor at Athens, were either 
fellow-pupils of Alexander, or at least received some instruction 
from Aristotle at this time.‘ 

Fifth Period—When Alexander crossed the Hellespont, in 
B.c. 334, Aristotle returned to Athens. We are told that the 
Athenians invited him on the death of Speusippus, and as his 
friend Xenocrates was established at the Academy, Aristotle 
opened his school in a gymnasium called the Lyceum, from the 
neighbouring temple and grove of Apollo Lyceus; and here 
he used to deliver his lessons, not sitting down, but walking to 
and fro ;? and from these lounges or saunters (περίπατοι), his 
scholars were called the peripatetics, or saunterers.° Aulus 





τρίψασθαι μᾶλλον ἑτέρων ᾿Αριστοτέλης᾽ οὐ γὰρ μόνον τὴν θεωρίαν ἠγάπησεν ἀλλὰ Kal 
νοσοῦσιν ἐβοήθει τοῖς φίλοις, K.T.d. 

1 Vita Alex. ¢. 7. 2 Plut. adv. Colot. ad fin. 

3 Pseudo-Ammonius and Vita Latina. 

4 Suidas, s.v. Mapovas ; Diog. Vita Theophrasti, 39. 

5 Cicero, Academ. Post. I. 4. 

® Diogenes (V. p. 301 C, Casaubon), says that Aristotle got into the practice of 


270 ARISTOTLE. 


Gellius gives us some interesting particulars respecting the orga- 
nization of this school. There were two classes of pupils. The 
morning lounge (ἑωθινὸς περίπατος) was designed only for the 
higher and more advanced students, and at the evening saunter 
(δειλινὸς περίπατος) he used to give a more popular lecture for 
the benefit of those who had not passed through the preparatory 
discipline. The former of these were called acroamatic dis- 
courses, and comprised theological, physical, and dialectical in- 
vestigations ; the latter were termed the ewoleric discourses, and 
comprehended rhetoric, sophistic disputations, and politics." We 
do not know whether his lectures were formal, or merely con- 
versational ; but we may infer that he did not adopt the cate- 
chetical method to any great extent. To keep up a friendly 
and instructive imtercourse with his hearers, Aristotle had 
periodical entertainments after the manner of Xenocrates, and 
at these banquets of the wise there were rules for decency of 
dress and decorum of manner which contrasted favourably with 
the noisy vulgarity of the usual Greek symposium.’ He also 
imitated Xenocrates in the institution of scholastic disputations 
under the presidency of a moderator, who held office for ten 
days.’ This practice formed the basis of the teaching and 
examination in the universities of Europe during the middle 
ages, and it is not yet extinct at Cambridge. 

It was during this second residence at Athens that Aristotle 
composed most of his extant works. And his situation during 
the greater part of the time must have been very enviable. We 
are told by Athenzeus that Alexander placed at his disposal, prin- 
cipally with a view to his collections in natural history, a sum of 
no less than 800 talents, about £200,000 of our money ;* Pliny 
informs us that some thousands of mén were employed by 
Alexander to procure specimens for his museum, and the ma- 
terials for his great work, and that Aristotle wrote fifty volumes 





teaching while taking his exercise, from his habit of walking about with Alexander 
during his convalescence after some illness, ὅτε ἐκ νόσου περιπατοῦντι ᾿Αλεξάνδρῳ 
συμπαρὼν διελέγετο ἄττα. 

1 Aulus Gellius (Woctes Atticw, XX. 5), is our only authority for this statement. 

2 Atheneus, p. 186. 

3 Diog. Laért. V. 4, p. 302 C: ἐν τῇ σχολῇ νομοθετεῖν μιμούμενον Zevoxpdrny, 
ὥστε κατὰ δέκα ἡμέρας ἄρχοντα ποιεῖν. 

4 IX. p. 398 Ἐ, 


LIFE OF ARISTOTLE. 271 


on the subject.' That these inquiries in natural history had 
commenced at an earlier period is indicated by Ailian’s state- 
ment? that Philip had supplied Aristotle with money for the 
prosecution of these researches. But these happy days of sun- 
shine and tranquillity were destined to be speedily overcast. On 
the one hand it is clear that some estrangement of Alexander 
from Aristotle took place towards the end of the philosopher’s 
stay at Athens ;* and on the other hand, his residence in this 
city was suddenly terminated by the threat of a prosecution for 
impiety, which might have produced a second edition of the 
death of Socrates. The misunderstanding with Alexander 
seems to have been connected with the downfall of his pupil 
and relative Callisthenes, who had accompanied the king to 
Asia. This Callisthenes, who was a rhetorician of considerable 
ability, but sadly deficient in common sense,‘ had opposed him- 
self to Anaxarchus, and the other flatterers who followed in the 
train of the Macedonian conqueror, and gave expression to his 
opinions with an unreserved and offensive bluntness, which was, 
under the circumstances, eminently imprudent.’ He also 
allowed himself to talk very foolishly to Alexander’s pages, 
which led to his implication in their conspiracy against the 
king.’ According to some he was put to death by Alexander’s 
express orders.’ Others say that he was abandoned to his 
enemies, in whose hands he perished by violence or neglect.* 
Now it seems that for some reason Alexander connected Aris- 
totle with the unjustifiable language of his kinsman; perhaps 
because Callisthenes had hinted to Philotas, one of the pages, 
that Athens would furnish a safe refuge to tyrannicides ;? perhaps 
Alexander’s mind had been poisoned by Olympias, who was vio- 
lently opposed to Aristotle’s friend Antipater. Plutarch men- 
tions a letter from Alexander to Antipater, in which he alludes 





1 Hist. Nat. VIII. 17. 2 Var. Hist. TV. το. 

8 The words of Aristotle in the Nicom. Eth. VIII. 7, where he speaks of too 
great inequality as a bar to friendship, have been supposed to refer to the interrup- 
tion of his friendly relations with Alexander. 

4 Aristotle is reported to have said of him: ὅτε Καλλισθένης λόγῳ μὲν ἣν δυνατὸς 
καὶ μέγας, νοῦν δ᾽ οὐκ εἶχεν. (Hermippus apud Plut. vit. Alex. c. 54.) 

5 Plutarch, ὁ. 52. 6 Arrian, IV. 13, 14. 
7 Curtius, VIII. 8, ὃ 21. 8 Plutarch, c. 55. 
9. Idem, ibid. 


272 ARISTOTLE. 


to the conspiracy of the pages, and states that they had been 
stoned by the Macedonians, but that he intended to punish the 
Sophist, and those who had sent him out, and those in the cities 
who had harboured conspirators against him.’ The same bio- 
grapher tells us, on the authority of Chares, that Alexander in- 
tended to have Callisthenes re-tried in the presence of Aristotle. 
Be this as it may, Alexander took no steps against Aristotle, 
and the story that the philosopher availed himself of the fact 
that one of Antipater’s sons was Alexander’s cup-bearer, to 
poison him with the water of the Styx, is a silly fiction? On 
the contrary, it is obvious that the death of Alexander rendered 
Aristotle’s position at Athens less secure, and exposed him to 
risk of religious persecution. Eurymedon, the hierophant, aided 
by Demophilus, indicted him for blasphemy, on the pretext that he 
had paid divine honours to Hermias, and his own wife Pythias.* 
The charge was contemptible in itself, but Aristotle knew that 
the Macedonian party at Athens had lost the power to protect 
him, and that it would be easy enough to induce the Athenians 
to treat him as they had treated Socrates. ‘ Let us not give 
them,’ he said, ‘a second opportunity of committing sacrilege 
against philosophy.’ Accordingly, he retired betimes with all 
his property, not forgetting his batterie de cuisine,’ to Chalcis in 
Eubeea, the native place of his maternal ancestors, where, no 
doubt, he had some personal friends. In his absence the 
Athenians rescinded a decree which had been made in his 
honour, and added the insulting imputation that he had acted 
as a Macedonian spy.’ This derogatory treatment he received 
in a spirit worthy of a great philosopher. ‘My mind is so 
constituted,’ he said, ‘ that I neither care very much about these 
things, nor on the other hand do I altogether disregard them.’® 





1 Idem, ibid. : οἱ μὲν παῖδες ὑπὸ τῶν Μακεδόνων κατελεύσθησαν᾽ τὸν δὲ σοφιστὴν 
ἐγὼ κολάσω καὶ τοὺς ἐκπέμψαντας αὐτὸν καὶ τοὺς ὑποδεχομένους ταῖς πόλεσι τοὺς ἐμοὶ 
ἐπιβουλεύοντας. 

2 Diodorus, XTX. 11. Plutarch, οὐδὲ supra. 

3 Phavorinus apud Diog. 5, p. 303 Ὁ. Milian, Var. Hist. III, 36. Aristocles 
apud Euseb. Prep. Ev. XV. 2. Origen 6. Celswm I, p. 51. 

4 Tt is said that he took no less than 75 copper saucepans to Chalcis (Aristocles 
apud Eusebium, ubi supra). 5 Aristocles, u.s. 

_ 8. Mlian, Var. Hist. XIX. 1: οὕτως ἔχω ws μήτε μοι σφόδρα μέλειν ὑπὲρ αὐτῶν 
μήτε μηδὲν μέλειν. ᾿ 


GENERAL VIEW OF HIS WRITINGS. 273 


It was in B.c. 323 that Aristotle retired to Eubcea, and he lived 
there only a few months, for he died of some illness, probably 
a disease of the intestines,’ in the following year, shortly after 
his great contemporary Demosthenes, also an exile from Athens, 
was obliged to save himself from a worse fate by taking poison 
at Calauria. It is scarcely worth while to notice the absurd 
stories that Aristotle also committed suicide by drinking hemlock, 
or by throwing himself into the Euripus, because he could not 
discover the cause of the seven tides there. By his wife Pythias 
he left behind him a daughter named after her mother, who 
married (1.) Nicanor, son of Proxenus, and adopted son of 
Aristotle; (2.) Procles, a lineal descendant of the Spartan 
king Demaratus, by whom she had two sons, Procles and De- 
maratus, both scholars of Theophrastus; (3.) Metrodorus, a 
physician, by whom she had a son called Aristotle. Aristotle 
also left an infant son called Nicomachus, by his concubine 
Herpyllis; he became a scholar of Theophrastus, and died in 
battle at an early age. 

An abstract of Aristotle’s will, or a codicil to it, is preserved 
by Diogenes. It is a very interesting document. It makes no 
mention of his literary property and his valuable library, which 
Strabo tells us* were left to Theophrastus. Antipater, Theo- 
phrastus, and four others are designated as provisionary execu- 
tors, until Nicanor’s return to take possession. 

Aristotle’s person is described by Timotheus.* He had some 
bodily defects or deformities, and made the most of himself by 
a diligent attention to his dress. In fact, he was no Cynic. 
Tn his private character he was extremely amiable and exemplary. 
His worth as a philosopher will be best exhibited if we take a 
general survey of his writings. 

§ 2. In looking at a mere catalogue of the works of Aristotle, 
we must be struck at once with the vast range of his knowledge. 
He aimed at nothing less than the completion of a general 





1 Censorinus (De die natali, c. 14) speaks of his ‘ naturalem stomachi infirmita- 
tem crebrasque morbidi corporis offensiones’ as of long duration. 
2 XIIZ. p. 124. 
5 περὶ βίων apud Diog. V. p. 300 B, ‘He had a lisping utterance, thin legs, 
little eyes, but wore a handsome dress, and rings, and shaved carefully.’ 
Vou. IL. τ 


274. ARISTOTLE. 


encyclopedia of philosophy.’ He had divided the collective ac- 
quirements of his age into their several branches, and had formed 
his own opinion on every one of them. In all this mass of 
learning his originality is as remarkable as his powers of re- 
search. He was, in fact, the author of the first scientific 
cultivation of each science, and he digested all the materials 
that he found so as to reproduce them in a manner peculiar to 
himself. There was hardly any quality distinguishing a philo- 
‘ sopher as such, which he did not possess in an eminent degree. 
We cannot indeed compare him with Bacon and the experi- 
mental philosophers of modern Europe; and any such com- 
parison would be quite unfair. But he was undoubtedly a 
great observer, and in this respect he stands in favourable con- 
trast to all who preceded him, not excepting Plato. Above all, 
we must be struck with the great sobriety of his speculations, a 
sobriety which is found in none of the elder schools, and is set 
at nought by the poetical genius of the great founder of the 
Academy. This indeed is so marked a feature in Aristotle, 
that some have reckoned it among his defects, and have at- 
tributed to it the dryness of his style, and the jejuneness of his 
expositions. 

The interest which, from an early period, attached itself 
to the works of Aristotle, led to the adoption of a very strange 
story about their preservation. They are said to have been 
buried under ground, and not brought to light for some 200 
years after the writer’s death. This story rests mainly on a 
passage in Strabo,? which Plutarch partly confirms,’ though 
perhaps only on the authority of Strabo himself. This geo- 
grapher tells us that Aristotle’s works were sold by the de- 
scendants of Neleus of Scepsis, who had got them from Theo- 





1 Tt must be remarked that, though Aristotle has attempted the thing, the 
barbarous name encyclopedia is not due to him. The ἐγκύκλιος παιδεία, or orbis 
doctrine (Quintil. Jnst. Or. I. το, § 101), corresponding generally to the seven 
liberal arts of the middle ages, was first described in these terms by the later Greek 
writers. Aristotle uses ἐγκύκλιος in the sense of ‘trivial, vulgar, common-place, 
routine, ordinary’ (see Pol. I. 7, §2, Meteor. I. 1). The idea that Aristotle wrote 
a treatise ‘on the elements of general knowledge’ (περὶ τῆς ἐγκυκλίου παιδείας) 
seems to be a mere inference of Diogenes and the commentators from such passages 
as Eth. Nic. 1. 5.§ 6: ἱκανῶς γὰρ καὶ ἐν τοῖς ἐγκυκλίοις εἴρηται περὶ αὐτῶν, where 
the reference is to the λόγοι ἐξωτερικοί. 

_ % XIII. p. 124. 3 Vita Sulle, c. 26. 


GENERAL VIEW OF HIS WRITINGS. 275 


phrastus, to one Apellicon of Teos, a book collector, after they 
had been lying for many years in a cellar under ground ; that 
immediately after the death of Apellicon, Sulla, having taken 
Athens, got possession of Apellicon’s library, and sent it to 
Rome, where Aristotle’s books fell into the hands of Tyrannio 
the grammarian, who undertook an edition of them. Plutarch, 
who repeats the principal part of this story, adds that Andro- 
nicus the Rhodian published tables of the contents of Aris- 
totle’s works (πίνακες) from the edition of Tyrannio. This is 
the whole authority for the story, which is completely over- 
thrown both by direct testimony, and by valid inferences. In the 
first place, we have the statement of Athenzeus, a learned and 
diligent collector, who, as an Egyptian Greek, was well ac- 
quainted with Alexandrian bibliography, and who says’ that 
Ptolemy Philadelphus bought the whole of the works of Aris- 
totle from Neleus, who had preserved them, and carried them 
away to his beautiful Alexandria. This statement is con- 
firmed by the fact that Aristotle was included in the canon of 
classical writers. Then, again, the Scholia on Aristotle, which 
were compiled out of a variety of works of the Alexandrian 
school, often refer to the works of Aristotle, coupled with the 
name of an Alexandrian writer; and this amounts almost to a 
direct proof that Aristotle’s works were known at Alexandria. 
Then, again, the encyclopedic form of Aristotle’s writings 
shows that they would be published altogether, if published at 
all. Then, again, the polemics of Xenocrates, who defended 
Plato’s doctrine of ideas against Aristotle, and of Chrysippus, 
who attacked many of Aristotle’s doctrines, show that Aristotle’s 
works must have been extant and available. Lastly, Cicero - 
makes such frequent mention of Aristotle, and so directly 
refers to the degeneracy of the later Peripatetics,? that he 
could not have failed to allude to the recent appearance of 





1 Athen. I. p. 3 Ὁ. After mentioning a number of book collectors, including 
Aristotle, he adds: καὶ τὸν τὰ τούτων διατηρήσαντα βιβλία Νηλέα" rap’ ov πάντα 
πριάμενος ὁ ἡμεδαπὸς βασιλεὺς ἸΠτολεμαῖος, Φιλάδελῴφος δὲ ἐπίκλην, μετὰ τῶν 
᾿Αθήνηθεν καὶ τῶν ἀπὸ Ῥόδου εἰς τὴν καλὴν ᾿Αλεξάνδρειαν μετήγαγε. 

2 De Finibus, V. 5, 12, 13: ‘teneamus Aristotelem et ejus filium Nioomachum. 
Theophrastum tamen adhibeamus ad pleraque. Simus igitur contenti his; nam- 
que horum posteri, meliores illi quidem quam reliquarum philosophi disciplinarum, 
sed ita degenerant, ut ipsi ex se nati esse videantur.’ 

T 2 


276 ARISTOTLE. 


Aristotle’s works, if the want of this source of information had 
been the true explanation of the fact, that the successors of 
Theophrastus exhibited no family likeness to the founder of 
the school. Still there must have been some grounds for 
the story which finds a place in the pages of such an accurate 
writer as Strabo; and we may conclude with safety, that 
Apellicon of Teos really became possessed of an autograph of 
Aristotle’s works, and that the later Peripatetics knew but little 
of the works of their master, not because they were in a cellar 
at Scepsis, but because they were more common at Alexandria 
than at Athens, and because they were considered too abstruse 
and too voluminous for general use. 

In speaking of the arrangement of Aristotle’s works as they 
have come down to us, we are first led to the well known distine- 
tion of the esoteric and exoteric writings, by which we generally 
understand the more scientific and recondite, as opposed to the 
more popular and superficial treatises. It was in reference to 
this division of Aristotle’s works that Lucian, in his auction of 
lives, puts the philosopher up for sale as ‘a double man,’? 
and Cicero often refers? to the exoteric works of Aristotle. 
There is no use of the word esoferic in the writings of Aris- 
totle himself, and when he employs the word ewoteric, he 
does not refer to a special class of his writings, but to a dis- 
cussion which is extrinsic and foreign to the subject before him, 
so that the phrase, ‘this has been treated of in the exoteric 
discourses,’ merely means ‘ this has been discussed elsewhere.’* 
It is true that in the Eudemian Ethics, which were drawn up 
by his pupil Eudemus, the epithet exoteric is opposed to the 
definition, ‘ according to philosophy,’ 7.e. ‘ scientific.’* And there 
can be little doubt that, after the time of Andronicus of Rhodes, 





1 Vitarum Auctio, c. 26: Emtor. ποῖος δέ τις ἐστί; Merce. μέτριος, ἐπιεικής, 
ἁρμόδιος τῷ βίῳ, τὸ δὲ μέγιστον διπλοῦς. Emtor. πῶς λέγεις ; Mere. ἄλλος μὲν ὁ 
ἔκτοσθεν φαινόμενος, ἄλλος δὲ ὁ ἔντοσθεν εἶναι δοκεῖ" ὥστε ἣν πρίῃ αὐτὸν μέμνησο τὸν 
μὲν ἐσωτερικόν, τὸν δὲ ἐξωτερικὸν καλεῖν. 

2 De Finibus, V, 5, 8 12. ad Att. IV. τό, 8 2. e¢ alibi. 

8 Eth. Nic. I. 13, § 9. Met. M. p. 1076 a 28: τεθρύλληται γὰρ τὰ πολλὰ καὶ 
ὑπὸ τῶν ἐξωτερικῶν λόγων, 

4 Eth. Eudem. I. 8, ὃ 4: ἐπέσκεπται δὲ πολλοῖς περὶ αὐτῶν τρόποις καὶ ἐν τοῖς 
ἐξωτερικοῖς λόγοις καὶ ἐν τοῖς κατὰ φιλοσοφίαν. 


GENERAL VIEW OF HIS WRITINGS. 277. 


the works of Aristotle were technically distinguished into the 
acroamatic, or autoprosopic writings, which were systematic 
treatises, addressed to duly prepared hearers, and delivered in 
the writer’s own person, and the ewxoteric, or dialogical, which 
were occasional and desultory essays, in the form of dialogues. 
This division does not apply to the works as we now have 
them, for they are all in the writer’s proper person, and all 
more or less scientific and methodical. We have only one 
original specimen of the Aristotelian dialogue, in a quotation 
of about thirty lines, preserved by Plutarch.’ Cicero has given 
us translations of two other fragments.? We can see that in 
these light popular essays Aristotle adopted a style more like 
that of the Scolium on Virtue than that of the Nicomachean 
treatise on the same subject, and justified the expression of 
Cicero, who speaks of his ‘ pouring forth a golden stream of 
language.’* In seeking a proper arrangement of the acroamatic 
works which have come down to us entire, we may either 
adopt the classification of Ammonius or Simplicius, or make 
one for ourselves. These commentators, who agree in the 
main, the latter having been a pupil of the former, adopt a 
primary division of Aristotle’s works into ‘the particular’ 
(τὰ μερικά), ‘the general’ (ra καθόλου), and ‘the mixed’ (ra 
μέσα or τὰ μεταξύ) ; the first being confined to the Epistles, the 
third to the Natural History, and the second including most of 
the extant writings. In this second class, the hypomnematic 
works, or draughts and notes of books, which Cicero calls com- 
mentari,’ are distinguished from the syntagmatic, or com- 
plete and formal treatises; and these latter, again, are dis- 
criminated as evoteric or dialogues, and acroamatic, autoprosopic, 
or treatises delivered proprid persond ; then these latter, again, 
are theoretical, practical, and organical, i.e. referring to language 
as an instrument of thought. The theoretical are, physiological, 
mathematical, and theological. The practical include the trea- 
tises on ethics, politics, and econamics. The organical com. 





1 Consolatio ad Apollon. p. 115 B; cf. vita Dionis, c. 22. 
2 De Natwrd Deorum, II. 37. De Officiis, II. τό. 


® Acad. Prior. ΤΊ. 38: ‘ veniet flumen orationis aureum fundens Aristoteles,' 
* Cic. De Fin. V. 5. 


278 ARISTOTLE. 


prise the logical, rhetorical, and critical treatises.' It seems 
to us that the order most convenient, in a general review of this 
great and diversified contribution to Greek literature, will be 
one analogous to that which we have adopted in discussing the 
works of Plato. We shall first consider Aristotle’s treatises on 
the history of philosophy, and the books in which he directly 
exhibits his own views of metaphysics and psychology. This 
includes what he calls theologia, and ‘ the first philosophy.’ We 
then pass on to the logic, which he substituted for the dialectics 
of the Socratic School, and the rhetorical and critical discussions, 
which he considered as correlative to it. In the next place, as 
in Plato’s system, we shall consider his ethical and political 
writings. Then will follow his speculations in natural history 
and general physics; and the miscellaneous works may be 
considered in the light of an appendix. 

§ 3. The title of Metaphysics (μετὰ τὰ φυσικά) was con- 
ferred, long after Aristotle’s time, on a collection of treatises 
more or less connected, in which the philosopher had given a 
sketch of the views of his predecessors, and expounded his own, 
on some of the primary subjects of general speculation. The 
, name denoted merely the place ‘after the physical treatises,’ 





1 The following is the arrangement of Simplicius (Stahr, Aristotelia, II. p. 260) :— 
I, τὰ μερικά, ἯΙ, τὰ μέσα. 
(As the treatise on Monarchy,) (As the Natural History.) 
IIL. τὰ epee 











I. ὑπομνηματικά. ἃ. συνταγματικά. 
ὦ. μονοειδῆ. ὃ. ποικίλα. ὦ. αὐτοπρόσωπα. ὃ. διαλογικά. 
| | 
a, θεωρητικά. B. πρακτικά. Ύ. ὀργανικά. 
ά. θεολογικά. ά, ἠθικά. ἁ. περὶ τῆς ἀποδεικτικῆς 
β΄. φυσιολογικά. β΄. οἰκονομικά. μεθόδου. (Analyt. 
γ΄. μαθηματικά. γ΄. πολιτικά. Post.) 


β΄. περὶ τῶν πρὸ τῆς ἀπο- 
δεικτικῆς μεθόδου. 
(Analyt. pr. In- 
terpr. Categorie.) 

γ΄. περὶ τῶν τὴν ἀπό- 
δειξιν ὑποδυομένων. 
(Topica, Sophist. 
Elench. Rhet.) 


METAPHYSICS. 279 


assigned to this book in certain arrangements of the philosopher’s 
works,’ but has become a general designation for formal treatises 
on the subject of mental philosophy, and for that branch of 
study itself, If Aristotle had given a name to all these treatises 
he would perhaps have included them under the general head 
of ‘wisdom,’ (σοφία), by which he meant ‘the theory of the 
first elements and causes of things, including the good and the 
motives of action ;’* and this would be our definition of the 
modern term Metaphysics, namely, the ‘ investigation of the 
causes and principles of things, as far as reason can penetrate 
and arrange them.’* Considered as the first and highest of all 
branches of speculation, Aristotle would term this ‘the first or 
mother science,’ (ἡ πρώτη σοφία, φιλοσοφία, ἐπιστήμη), and with 
reference to its supremacy he would identify it with theology, 
(ἡ θεολογική)," though perhaps, in the order of study, he would 
place it, like his commentators, after the contemplation of visible 
nature.” That there is no inconsistency in thus viewing the 
question from two sides, he has fully explained in a remarkable 
passage. He says:® ‘ If there is no existence distinct from the 
concrete realities of nature, physics must be the first science. 
But if there is an immutable existence, it must take precedence 
of the former, and its science must be the first, and because it 
is the first it must also be the universal science. And it must 
pertain to this philosophy to contemplate existence as such, 
both in its proper definition and in its essential attributes.’ 
Accordingly, what we call the Metaphysics of Aristotle includes 
what Plato meant by his Dialectic and the theory of ideas to 
which it led. Aristotle, however, used Dialectic in a much 
narrower sense than Plato. In one passage, he says that ‘ dia- 
lectic is merely tentative, where philosophy is cognizant, and 





1 Especially in that of Andronicus the Rhodian. See Michelet, Zxzamen Cri- 
tique de 0 Quvrage d’ Aristote intitulé Metaphysique. Paris, 1836, p. 20. 

2 Met. I. 2, p. 982, bg; δεῖ yap ταύτην (σοφίαν) τῶν πρώτων ἀρχῶν καὶ αἰτιῶν 
εἶναι θεωρητικήν" καὶ yap τἀγαθὸν καὶ τὸ οὗ ἕνεκα ὃν τῶν αἰτίων ἐστίν. 

3. Butler's Lectures on Ancient Philosophy, I. p. 74. 

4 Met. XI. 5, p. 1061, b 5. 

5 He gives the three speculative sciences in this order: Mathematics, Physics, 
Theology (Met. VI. τ, p. 1026, a 19): ὥστε τρεῖς ἂν εἶεν φιλοσοφίαι θεωρητικαΐ, 
μαθηματική, φυσική, θεολογική. 

δ. Met. V. 1, p. 1026 a 29. 


280 ARISTOTLE. 


sophistic merely assumes an appearance while it abandons the 
reality.’ In another he defines the dialecticians as merely 
‘those who syllogistically develope the contradictions implied in 
popular notions,” and even makes dialectic one of the four 
methods of conversational discussion, (τὸ διαλέγεσθαι). The 
metaphysical speculationsof Aristotle reduce themselves in a great 
measure to a refined system of scientific terminology. Indeed, one 
of the fourteen books in our collection is confined to definitions, 
and may be even considered as a special tract on the subject.* 
In discussing the theories of others, he tests them by their 
views respecting the four principles of things, namely the formal, 
the material, the efficient, and the final. The four causes are 
thus described :* ‘One of these causes we call the substance, 
(οὐσία), and the what-it-was-to-be (τὸ ri ἦν εἶναι), for the where- 
fore (τὸ διὰ ri) is the last point in the definition, though it is 
really the cause and the first principle, because it is necessarily 
antecedent ;" the second cause we call the material (ὑλη), and 
the subject (ὑποκείμενον) ; the third, we call that whence is the 
beginning of the movement; the fourth, the opposite of this, 
namely, the motive (τὸ ov ἕνεκα) and the good,—for this is the 
end of all generation and change.’ We thus see that the formal 
or ideal cause is the ‘ definition real,’ which forms the basis of 
Plato’s theory of ideas. And the phrase ‘ the what-it-was-to-be,’ 
which Aristotle invented to describe the abstract or general 
term, which was antecedent to any particular or concrete exis- 





1 Me. IV. 2, p. 1004, Ὁ 25: ἐστὶ δὲ ἡ διαλεκτικὴ πειραστικὴ περὶ ὧν | φιλοσοφία 
γνωριστική, 4 δὲ σοφιστικὴ φαινομένη, οὖσα δ᾽ οὔ. 

2 Sophist, Elench. 2. : 

3 Aristotle seems to refer to Met. IV. [V.] under the title of τὰ περὶ τοῦ ποσαχῶς 
λέγεται, ef. Met. V. [VI.] 4, 1028, a4; VI. [VII.] 1, 1028, a το; ΙΧ. {X.] 1, 
1052, a 15. 

4 Met. I. 3, p. 983,226. Mr. R. L. Ellis observes in a note to Bacon, De Aug- 
mnentis Scientiarum, lib. III. cap. IV. p. 550: ‘ These four kinds of causes may be 
divided into twe classes, extrinsic and intrinsic, the efficient and final belonging to 
the first class, the material and formal to the second. It is obvious that these dis- 
tinctions involve the postulate of what has been called the theory of physical influ- 
ence, that is, that one substance really acts on another, and must at least be modi- 
fied, if we adopt any such theory on this subject as that of Leibnitz or of Herbart.’ 

5]. 28: ἀνάγεται yap τὸ διὰ τί els τὸν λόγον ἔσχατον, αἴτιον δὲ καὶ ἀρχὴ τὸ διὰ τί ~ 
πρῶτον. Here it is obvious that ἔσχατον is a secondary predicate and must be con- 
strued with ἀνάγεται, and that πρῶτον is to be similarly taken with τὸ διὰ τί, ‘ the 
wherefore, as being the first, is the cause and the first principle.’ 


METAPHYSICS. 281 


tence, merely indicates the πρώτη οὐσία or abstraction which 
belongs to all things capable of definition... By the use of the 
past tense in this phrase, Aristotle indicates that the formal 
cause has only an inferential existence,’ whereas by the phrase 
‘the what-it-is’ (τὸ ri ἐστι), he implies not only the formal 
cause or abstract idea, but all the particulars of the definition, 
all, in fact, that is included in the category of entity or quiddity® 
lt is also a special part of Aristotle’s business in these specula- 
tions, to establish the distinction between the virtual or potential 
and the actual state of things. The eighth book of the Meta- 
physics is mainly occupied with this discussion. <A thing exists 
potentially or virtually (δυνάμει), when it may be made to exist 
actually (ἐνεργείᾳ). Thus the statue is virtually in the wood 
before it is actually a representation of Hermes or any other 
god.* From this opposition of the virtual to the actual, com- 
bined with the view which Aristotle takes of the formal cause, 
we get his celebrated term Entelechy (ἐντελέχεια) or complete- 
ness, which is, to a certain extent, synonymous with substance 
(οὐσία), distinguished from actuality (ἐνέργεια), and opposed to 
matter (vn). The formal cause is an entelechy, the definition 
of that which exists potentially is an entelechy, and the soul is 
the primary entelechy of a natural body virtually alive.’ 

The proper arrangement and mutual relations of the books 
called the Metaphysics of Aristotle have formed the subject of 
much discussion among scholars. The following conclusions, 
adopted by the latest editor, seem, on the whole, to be quite 





1 Me. VI. [VII.] 4, p. 1030a6: τὸ τί ἣν εἶναι ἐστιν ὅσων ὁ λόγος ἐστὶν ὁρισμός. 
1030 Ὁ 4: ἐκεῖνο δὲ φανερὸν ὅτι ὁ πρώτως καὶ ἁπλῶς ὁρισμὸς καὶ τό τί ἣν 
εἶναι τῶν οὐσιῶν ἐστίν. 

2 See New Cratylus, §§ 192, 343, 344- 

3 Met. VI. [VII.] to, p. 1035 a 2: οὐσία ἥ re ὕλη, Kal τὸ εἶδος, καὶ τὸ ἐκ τούτων. 

4 Met. VIII. [IX.]6, p. 1048 a 30. See New Cratylus, ὃ 341. 

5 See the passages quoted in the Vew Cratylus, §§ 337—344. Perhaps the word 
‘completeness’ is the only single term which can be accepted as an equivalent for 
ἐντελέχεια. If we were not restricted to*a single term, we might call it ‘an orga- 
nizing force.’ Mr. Maurice says (Ancient Philosophy, p. 191): “ εἶδος expresses the 
substance ef each thing viewed in repose—its form or constitution ; ἐνέργεια, its 
substance considered as active and generative ; ἐντελέχεια seems to be the synthesis 
or harmony of these two ideas. The effectio of Cicero therefore represents the most 
important side of it, but not the whole.’ We fear that this explanation will not be 
very intelligible to an ordinary reader. 


282 ARISTOTLE. 


satisfactory.’ The fourteen books of the Metaphysics are gene- 
rally distinguished by the first thirteen letters of the Greek 
alphabet ; the first and second, however, being designated as “A 
μεῖζον and ἃ ἔλαττον. Now it appears that Books A, B, I, E, 
Z, H, 9, exhibit a continuous and connected development of one 
and the same argument. Book A treats of ‘ wisdom’ (σοφία), 
and of the principles which it involves, and criticizes the systems 
of the philosophers who preceded Aristotle. Book B discusses 
seventeen problems in ontology. Book I treats of the unity 
of science. Book E investigates substance or entity. Books 
Z, H, and 9, are occupied with concrete reality, the substantial 
form, the universal actuality and virtuality. The subject of 
Books B, I’, E, is briefly sketched in Book K, chapters 1—8. 
The same discussion is also the subject of Books I, M, and N, 
which treat of unity, ideas, and numbers. Book A, which 
treats of God or ‘the good,’ does not belong to the general 
question of the primary philosophy, but contains a special trea- 
tise. Book A is a genuine tract of Aristotle, but does not 
belong to the metaphysical works. It is inserted among these 
books, and immediately before Book E, which refers to the 
discussion περὶ τῶν ποσαχῶς λεγομένων, because it seemed to 
be a convenient appendix or supplement to them. It is by no 





1 Aristotelis Metaphysica recognovit et enarravit Hermannus Bonitz. Bonn. 
1848. The views maintained by Bonitz are, in the main, the same as those put 
forth by Brandis. 

2 The following table will show the different arrangements of the Metaphysica, and 
the different modes of citing the books; see Blakesley’s Life of Aristotle, p. 156. 


Greek MSS. Du Val. Petitus. Diogenes Laértius. 


A ay sine 5 περὶ ἀρχῶν d. 

α ΤΕ AOC ye art περὶ ἐπιστημῶν d. 

Β “LG 3 δ᾽" περὶ ἀρχῶν β'. 

Ἐπ EY: 4 Ax περὶ ἐπιστημῶν β'. 

Δ ὟΣ: 5 Ἐλο περὶ τῶν ποσαχῶς λεγομένων. 
ν mAs δ : at περὶ εἰδῶν Kal γενῶν. 

LE ig YA Sate 8 δι us περὶ ὕλης. not mentioned 
rs Wns ΚΙ a. 10 περὶ ἐνεργείας. § by Diogenes. 
I xX, to 2 ἡ ἐκλογὴ τῶν ἐναντίων, 
ΟῚ, 13 14 περὶ ἐπιστήμης. 

A ΠΡΟΣ 14 13 περὶ φιλοσοφίας d. 

Μ XIII. II 1 περὶ φιλοσοφίας β΄. 

Ν XIV 12 12 περὶ φιλοσοφίας γ΄. 


METAPHYSICS. 283 


means certain that Book a was written by Aristotle, and some 
have attributed it to his scholar Pasicles the Rhodian ; at any 
rate it is out of its place in this collection, and is merely a brief 
essay on truth. The latter half of Book K, chapters 9—12, 
is an extract carelessly made by some later writer from Aris- 
totle’s Physica Auscultatio. On the whole, then, it may be 
said, that we have seven continuous books, interpolated with a 
tract probably written by some scholar of Aristotle, and with 
a book of definitions by Aristotle himself; that these are 
followed by a book (I,) connected, but not immediately, with 
them, by a recapitulation (K, 1—8) of the three which foilow 
the first (B, [, E,) by a careless extract from the physical 
works (K, 9—12), by a special treatise on theology (A,) and 
by two books, (M, N,) whose place in the first seven cannot be 
accurately determined.’ 

Aristotle’s mental philosophy, in connexion with his physical 
science, forms the subject of a special treatise concerning the 
soul (περὶ ψυχῆς) in three books.? In this work, as in his Meta- 
physics, the philosopher begins with a criticism on the systems 
of his predecessors, which occupies the greater part of the first 
book. In the second book he enters on the distinction between 
soul and body, and all the principal questions connected with 
the theory of sensation. And here we are at once brought 
back to the phraseology on which he dwells so much in the 
metaphysical books. A body, from its conformation, has a 
potentiality or virtuality of existence.* Its entelechy or com- 
pleteness is the soul. But even when animated by the soul, 
and so, completely alive, it may have a dormant instead of an 
operating activity, it may have entelechy (ἐντελέχεια) without 
energy (ἐνέργεια), completeness without actuality. The soul 
then is the primary or antecedent completeness of the body, 
which is virtually alive ;* it is that which informs the material 





1 Mr. Maurice has drawn up an able review of the Metaphysica in his Ancient 
Philosophy, chapter VI. ὃ 5, pp. 178—198. 

3 There is a full analysis of this book in Butler’s Lectures on Ancient Philosophy, 
II. pp. 370 foll. 

3 All substance consists of matter and form, and the matter is a δύναμις or 
capacity, but the form is an entelechy or completeness (De Animd, II. 1, 2). 

4 διὸ ψυχή ἐστιν ἐντελέχεια ἡ πρώτη σώματος φυσικοῦ δυνάμει ζωὴν ἔχοντος, 


284 ARISTOTLE. 


(ὕλη), and makes the actuality of life inevitable, whenever there 
is the corresponding exertion. If the eye were an animal, the 
faculty of vision would be its soul, its entelechy, or completeness, 
and this would not be less real and complete if the eyelid were 
closed over it, though in that case it would not actually see. 
Without its entelechy, the eye could not be truly called by this 
name, but only homonymously so.’ The soul, then, is some- 
thing necessarily pertaining to the body, and ‘ each soul is in 
its own proper body ; for such is the nature of things, that the 
entelechy or completeness of each thing is in that particular 
thing which virtually exists;’? and thus the form (εἶδος) is 
always necessarily inherent in its own proper matter (ὕλη). 
These definitions at once connect themselves with Aristotle’s 
views respecting the gradations of organic beings, and his 
subdivisions of the human soul into the vegetable, the rational, 
and the partly rational.’ The intellect he regards as both 
passive and active (νοῦς ποιητικός, νοῦς παθητικός). The latter 
makes, the former becomes all things. Taken together, he 
regards it as recipient or susceptible of general impressions or 
forms. But the soul is so connected with the body that it 
cannot act without the aid of the senses, or of that imagination 
which retains the pictures of perception without the materials 
(vAn). As we are not writing a history of Greek philosophy, 
it is sufficient merely to indicate the tendency of these psycho- 
logical speculations, and to show how diametrically they are 
opposed to that doctrine of the soul’s independent existence 
which forms a key to the philosophy of Plato. 

§ 4. From a consideration of the soul and its functions, we 
pass on to language as the instrument of thought. By his labours 
in this field—his organic works, as they are ealled—<Aristotle has 
obtained the foremost place among those who have attempted 
the solution of the problem of logic; and though in the appli- 





τοιοῦτο δὲ ὃ ἂν ἢ ὀργανικόν (De Animd, II. τ, ὃ 5); and again: εἰ δή τι κοινὸν ἐπὶ" 
πάσης ψυχῆς δεῖ λέγειν εἴη ἂν ἐντελέχεια ἣ πρώτη σώματος φυσικοῦ ὀργανικοῦ (ibid. 
§ 6.). 

1 Thid. § 9: εἰ γὰρ ἣν ὁ ὀφθαλμὸς ζῷον ψυχὴ ἂν ἣν αὐτοῦ ἡ ὄψις K. τ. Ἃ. 

2 Jbid. II. 2, § 14,15: καὶ διὰ τοῦτο ἐν σώματι ὑπάρχει καὶ ἐν σώματι τοιούτῳ 
«νος ἑκάστου γὰρ ἡ ἐντελέχεια ἐν τῷ δυνάμει ὑπάρχοντι καὶ τῇ οἰκείᾳ ὅλη πέφυκεν 
ἐγγίνεσθαι. 

3 See below, ὃ 6. 4 De Anima, 111. 5. 


LOGIC. 285 


cation of his principles of reasoning to the discovery of truth 
by induction, Aristotle’s system was altogether defective, and his 
Organon was necessarily superseded by the Novum Organon of 
Francis Bacon,’ his regulation of the laws of speech is still ad- 
mitted to be sound and valid, and his analytical treatises are 
the basis, at all events, of all that modern science has attempted 
in the same field. We have seen* how Plato was led to his 
dialectical conclusions by an examination of the opposing 
systems of the Heracleiteans and Eleatics, and that his main 
object was to obtain a criterion of truth and science. Among 
those who admitted that there must be such a criterion, he 
found that some, like Heracleitus and Protagoras, maintained 
that every man was to himself the standard of truth ; others, 
like Parmenides, required a scientific cultivation before any man 
could come to a true judgment. Plato inclined to this class, 
and Aristotle would not accept the famous maxim of Protagoras 
except on ‘the condition that the sense and reason were in a 
perfect and healthy condition.* Still less could Aristotle adopt 
the Heracleitean hypothesis, that all things were in a state of 
perpetual flux or motion, so that nothing could be considered as 
in the same state for two successive moments. If this were so, 
the primary axiom of reasoning—the same thing cannot be and 
not be‘—would fail to establish itself, for we might connect con- 
tradictory predicates with the same subject at inappreciable 
intervals of time. Aristotle’s logic, then, like Plato’s dialectic, 
rested upon a previous examination of the general questions of © 
ontology, hypothesis, axioms, and causation. But while Plato 
considered dialectics as including metaphysics or philosophy as 
well as the principles of reasoning, Aristotle, as we have seen, 





1 The Novum Organon had an antagonistic reference to the Organon of Aristotle, 
just as the New Atlantis entered into professed rivalry with the Critias of Plato. 
On Bacon’s design in his great philosophical works, the English reader can now 
consult the admirable introductions of R, L. Ellis, and J. Spedding. 

2 Above, chapter XX XIX. § 7. 

3 Met. X. 1, p. 1053 ἃ 35. XI. 6, p. 1062 b 12. 

4 Met. III. 3, p. 1005, Ὁ. 23: ἀδύνατον ὁντινοῦν ταὐτὸν ὑπολαμβάνειν εἶναι καὶ 
μὴ εἶναι, Analyt. Pr. I. 40: φάσις καὶ ἀπόφασις οὐχ ὑπάρχουσιν ai ἀντικείμεναι 
ἅμα τῷ αὐτῷ... .. κατὰ παντὸς ἑνὸς ἢ φάσις ἢ ἀπόφασις ἀληθής. Analyt. Post, 
1. 25: διὰ γὰρ τὴν κατάφασιν ἡ ἀπόφασις γνώριμος καὶ προτέρα ἡ κατάφασις ὥσπερ 
καὶ τὸ εἶναι τοῦ μὴ εἶναι. 


286 ARISTOTLE. 


discussed the primary philosophy in a separate work, and 
examined the laws of reasoning by themselves. 

The logical works of Aristotle consist of the following 
treatises :—The Categories, the beok on Interpretation, the 
former and latter Analytics, the Topics, and the Sophistical 
Proofs. These five treatises, together with Porphyry’s intro- 
duction to the first of them, are generally called the Organon. 
The Categories are a list of the ten most general forms under 
which separate terms may serve as the subject or predicate of a 
proposition.’ This list seems to be founded chiefly on gram- 
matical considerations ; and the categories, according to the 
instances which Aristotle has given of them, are merely a 
syntactical arrangement of certain parts of speech. The first, 
or the category of substance or guiddity, includes nouns sub- 
stantive; the next three, quantity, quality, and relation, are 
different sorts of adjectives; the 5th and 6th are adverbs of 
place and time; and the last four are verbs considered as in- 
transitive (7th), perfect passive or the effect of action (8th), 
active (gth), and passive (10th). Adrastus wished to regard the 
Categories as an introduction to the Topics (τὰ πρὸ τῶν τοπικῶν), 
and the latter does contain an enumeration of the six categore- 
mata or predicables which are supplementary to the ten 
categories or predicaments ; but Porphyry rejected this appella- 
tion, and it seems better to consider the Categories as the 
treatise on separate terms, which precedes the Interpreta- 
tion or treatise on propositions, and forms a preface to the 
whole body of logical books. This essay on Interpretation is 
a discussion of nouns and verbs considered as the necessary 
parts of an enunciation or sentence. We have seen that this 





1 Ritter says that ‘the categories according to Aristotle are the most general 
forms of that which is denoted by the simple word ;’ Hegel defines them as ‘simple 
essences, universal designations’ (Bestimmungen); Biese as brief definite data 
(Angaben), which are to be considered in the investigation of the question ; Quin- 
tilian (II. 6. § 23) says: ‘ Aristoteles elementa decem constituit circa que versari 
videatur omnis questio.’ According to Waitz, the last editor of the Organon, 
κατηγορία in Aristotle means (1) quodeunque predicatur, (2) genera eorwm que 
predicantur, (3) ipsa predicandi ratio, (4) propositio simplex.. Karnyopia and 
κατηγόρημα are sometimes used as synonyms; Simplicius, fol. 36, distinguishes 
them as λέξις and πρᾶγμα. See also Plotinus, De categ. Ennead. 1V. 1. 

2 New Cratylus, § 125. Trendelenburg, Geschichte der Categorienlehre, Berlin, 
1846, pp. 384 foll. 


LOGIC. 287 


analysis of the sentence was adopted by Plato, and that ὄνομα, 
the ‘name’ or ‘noun, was the original designation of the 
subject, and ῥῆμα, the ‘ assertion’ or ‘ verb,’ was the original 
designation of the predicate. From the complete sentence he 
passes on, in ‘the former Analytics’ (Analytica Priora), to a 
discussion of the syllogism, which implies the combiation, by 
means of a middle term, of the three complete sentences, which 
involve the two premisses and their conclusion.’ Here he falls 
back on the first principles of his metaphysical reasoning ; for 
‘ the principle involved in all syllogism is the dictum de omni 
et nullo, which is identical with the axiom or the principle of 
contradiction”? The former Analytics, then, were well de- 
scribed in their old title, ‘On the Syllogism’ (περὶ συλλογισμοῦ). 
The latter Analytics are entitled ‘On Demonstration’ (περὶ 
ἀποδείξεως) ; and the whole work may be described, in the 
words of an English commentator, as falling into three divisions : 
(A) the generic branch, which treats of reasoning in general, 
whether the result is Opinion or Science; (B) the specific 
branch, which treats of reasoning, the result of which is Science, 
Inductive or Deductive; (C) the specific branch, which treats 
of Dialectical reasoning, the result of which is Opinion. Or, 
as Induction is not sufficiently confined to scientific reasoning 
by Aristotle, whose topics are lax, and whose observation of 
phenomena was scanty and careless, we may say that the 
Organon may be ‘ divided into four parts—General Logic, the 
Logie of Deduction, the Logic of Induction, and the Logic of 





1 Aristotle’s account of induction in the Prior Analytics was criticized by Dr. 
Whewell in 1850 (7 γαη8. of the Cambr. Phil. Soc. vol. TX. part 1), and the text 
and reasoning of the philosopher were defended by Mr. H. A. J. Munro, of Trinity 
College, in a very able paper, which has not, we believe, been published. Mr. 
Munro says (p. 9): ‘The object of Aristotle in his Prior Analytics is to give a 
technical exposition of the syllogism and its various moods and figures. In the 
concluding chapters of the work he maintains, in order to give his treatise a formal 
completeness, that any kind of proof may be put into the syllogistic form,’ and thus 
he ‘does not say that induction is a syllogism, but that any proof, and therefore 
induction, may be put into a syllogistic form.’ 

2 The Posterior Analytics of Aristotle, by Edward Poste, Oxford, 1850, p. 8. 
Mr. Poste adds: ‘ When Dugald Stewart observes that the whole of the science of 
syllogism is comprised or implied in the terms of one single axiom, his assertion is 
quite correct, the doctrine of syllogism merely determining, on the authority of the 
axiom itself, under what conditions the axiom is applicable.’ 


288 ARISTOTLE. 


Opinion ; the third not sufficiently articulated and disengaged 
from the fourth, and hence the necessity of a Novum Organon? 
The Topics, which Cicero had studied so carefully that he was 
able to make an epitome of the book from memory in the course 
of a voyage from Velia to Rhegium,’ is an examination of the 
different dialectical maxims or secondary axioms, from which we 
derive the middle terms of our syllogisms, and so frame the 
demonstrative argument ; and the treatise on Sophistical Proofs 
(περὶ σοφιστικῶν ἐλέγχων)" is an analysis of the different forms 
of fallacy, with a view to their detection and confutation. 

The Organon, as it has come down to us, does not include 
all or nearly all the books which Aristotle wrote on logic. The 
old commentators mention forty books attributed to the philo- 
sopher, many of which they rejected as not genuine.‘ Diogenes 
Laértius enumerates about twenty logical treatises besides those 
that we have; he says that there were eight, or, as one manu- 
script has, ten books of the former Analytics.” The Methodica, 
in eight books, which are quoted in the Rhetoric,’ may have 
been this very collection, and perhaps the same work is referred 
to in the Nicomachean Ethics. 

§ 5. The treatise on Rhetoric which has come down to us 
is apparently one of the latest of Aristotle’s extant writings. 
His earlier work on the subject—the Συναγωγὴ Teyvor—was 
rather a history of Rhetorical Literature, than a philosophical 
essay like that which we have, and was written probably during 
his first residence at Athens. Our present book refers to the 
Politics, which were a continuation of the Ethics, were written 
after the Poetics, and mention the death of Philip ;’ and it has 





1 Poste, Posterior Analytics, pp. 8, 32, 36. 

2 Cie. Topica, I. 5: ‘itaque hee, quam mecum libros non haba memoria& 
repetita, in ips& navigatione conscripsi.. Mr. Maurice remarks (Ancient Philo- 
sophy, p. 174): ‘To understand Aristotle rightly, the Zopics should be read together 
with the three books on rhetoric...... It (the Rhetorica) is closely connected 
with this work on probable arguments. The Topics are to it what the six books of 
Euclid are to a treatise on practical mechanics,’ 

8 ‘This work has a natural connexion with the Topics, as Aristotle himself re- 
marks in the beginning of the last chapter of the second book.” —Blakesley, Life of 
Aristotle, p. 144. 

4 Blakesley, u.s. 38/23; 6 I, 2, § to. 

7 That the Rhetoric was written after the Poetics appears from the latter, c. 19: 
ἐν τοῖς περὶ ῥητορικῆς κείσθω. That the Politics followed the Poetics appears from 


RHETORIC. 289 


therefore been inferred by.a modern critic that the Rhetoric 
must have been written about 330 B.c.' But although the 
existing treatise belongs to the last years of Aristotle’s literary 
activity, it is quite clear that its subject was one of the earliest 
which engaged his attention both as a teacher and as a writer. 
It is also certain that he regarded it as a necessary supplement 
to his dialectical treatises. The book begins by defining 
rhetoric as the correlative (ἀντίστροφος) of dialectic ;? and the 
author is at great pains to show how the rhetorical enthymeme 
(ἐνθύμημα) is related to the logical syllogism, the two modes 
of reasoning, though identical in their form, being different 
in their matter, because the topics or commonplaces of rhetoric 
do not admit of strictly scientific demonstration.’ Aristotle, 
however, justly claims to have raised rhetoric to the rank of an 
applied science, or at least of an art resting on scientific 
principles. ‘Those,’ he says,‘ ‘who have hitherto composed 
treatises on rhetoric (τὰς τέχνας τῶν λόγων) have introduced 
but little art into their systems. For the discussion of proofs 
(πίστεις) is the only part of their treatises that can be regarded 
as belonging to the art (ἔντεχνον) ; all the rest consists in 
merely accessory matter (προσθῆκαι). Besides, they say 
nothing about enthymemes, which are the substance of proofs, 
and busy themselves generally with extraneous discussions.’ As 
might be expected from a work on which Aristotle has bestowed 
the results of his mature knowledge and literary experience, 
and the subject of which had always occupied his attention, 
the Rhetoric is one of the most perfect of his compositions. 
Diogenes quotes only two books, and it is possible that the 
first two were originally a separate treatise, to which the third 





Pol. VIII. 7. B, 41. b, 39. The mention of the death of Philip in the Politics s 
in 8 (V.), το. § 16. 

1 L. Spengel, Munich Transactions, VI, for 1852, p. 496. 

5 Rhet. I, τ: ἡ ῥητορική ἐστιν ἀντίστροφος τῇ διαλεκτικῇ" ἀμφότεραι γὰρ περὶ 
τοιούτων τινῶν εἰσιν, ἃ κοινὰ τρόπον τινὰ ἁπάντων ἐστι γνωρίζειν καὶ οὐδεμιᾶς ἐπι- 
στήμης ἀφωρισμένης. He defines rhetoric (I. 2, ὃ 1) as: δύναμις περὶ ἕκαστον τοῦ 
θεωρῆσαι τὸ ἐνδεχόμενον πιθανόν, and says, 1.1, 814: οὐ τὸ πεῖσαι ἔργον αὐτῆς ἀλλὰ 
τὸ ἰδεῖν τὰ ὑπάρχοντα πιθανὰ περὶ ἕκαστον. 

3 T.2,§8. The relation of the enthymeme to the syllogism is well discussed in a 
paper on rhetoric in Blackwood’s Magazine for December, 1827, 

δ», $3: 

Vou. II. U 


250 ARISTOTLE. 


was subsequently added as an appendix. This view is borne 
out by the divisions of the work.' The first two books treat 
of the doctrine of proofs (πίστεις), which Aristotle regarded as 
the most scientific part of his subject; and the third discusses 
the rules of diction (λέξις) and arrangement (τάξις). So that 
the first two teach what the rhetorician ought to say; the third 
how he ought to say it; and the three together comprise the 
three departments “aig be to the Roman teachers of rhetoric 
as inventio, elocutio, and dispositio.2 According to Aristotle, 
rhetoric is an offshoot of dialectics and politics:* of the 
former, because the enthymeme or oratorical syllogism, which 
is intended only to persuade, rests upon its dialectical parent, 
which is caleulated to convince ;* of the latter, because a know- 
ledge of ethical philosophy is essential to the artificial prepara- 
tion of an argument. As the enthymeme is an application of 
the syllogism, so the example (παράδειγμα) is the oratorical 
form of logical induction.’ The inquiry about dispositions and 





1 The following is the general analysis of the Rhetoric of Aristotle. 


Books I. and II. (a) ἐκ τίνων ai πίστεις ἔσονται. 
I. 1, 2. Definitions. 
3. Three provinces of rhetoric—deliberative, forensic, epideictic. 
4-8. The deliberative. 
9. The epideictic. 
10-14. The forensic. 
15. (a) Formal and inartificial proofs (ἄτεχνοι mlorecs)—laws, witnesses, 
agreements, torture, oaths. 

II. τ. (8) Artificial proofs (ἔντεχνοι πίστεις) : dependent (I) on the character 
of the speaker and the state of the hearer, (II) on the speech 
itself. 

1-17. (I) Theory of the affections. 
18-26. (II) The common proofs (xowal-ricre:s). 
Book IIT. (6) περὶ τὴν λέξιν. 
III. 1-12. General remarks on oratorical style. 
(Ὁ πῶς χρὴ τάξαι τὰ μέρη τοῦ λόγου. 
13-19. On the parts of the oration. " 

2 Spengel, u.s. p. 477. 

3 T. 2, 8.7: ὥστε συμβαίνει τὴν ῥητορικὴν οἷον παραφυές τι τῆς διαλεκτικῆς εἶναι 
καὶ τῆς περὶ τὰ ἤθη πραγματείας, ἣν δίκαιόν ἐστι προσαγορεύειν πολιτικήν" διὸ καὶ 
ὑποδύεται ὑπὸ τὸ σχῆμα τὸ τῆς πολιτικῆς ἡ ῥητορική. 

4 ae tells us that the γνώμη, or general sentiment, is μέρος ἐνθυμήματος 
(II. 20, § 1); for the causal sentence with γάρ, added to the γνώμη, makes an 
enthymeme or rhetorical argument (II. 21, ὃ 2). 

5 T. 2,88: καλῷ δ᾽ ἐνθύμημα μὲν Siedutale συλλογισμόν' παράδειγμα δὲ ican 


RHETORIC. 291 


characters, which occupies the first seventeen chapters of the 
second book, is a valuable addition to Aristotle’s moral philo- 
sophy ; and it is a just tribute to the accurate observation of 
the Greek philosopher and the English dramatist, when attempts 
are made to exemplify the ee of Aristotle by examples 
taken from Shakspere.’ 

It is interesting to caine the relations between the rhe- 
torical system of Aristotle and those of Plato and Isocrates. 
Throughout the rhetoric there is a tacit reference both to the 
Gorgias and the Phedrus.’ The latter especially, which con- 
tains Plato’s views of scientific rhetoric, anticipates Aristotle’s 
views in so many respects, that it would be surprising that he 
does not directly refer to it, if this circumstance were not ex- 
plicable, according to the ancient rules of citation, by the fact - 
that Aristotle so completely agreed with its general scope. 
When Plato says* that, ‘as the power of speaking is just a sort 
of soul-leading (ψυχαγωγία), he who would be a rhetorician 
must know all the forms of the soul, he states generally what 
Aristotle discusses in detail in the second book of his rhetoric.* 
And throughout the latter work we see a general recognition of 
the principles laid down by Plato. The great discrepancy between 
the master and pupil on this subject is suggested by the oppo- 
sition between the favourable opinion respecting Isocrates, which 
is expressed in the Phedrus, and the well known antagonism 
between Aristotle and that orator. We have noticed above the 
reasons which have been advanced against the common opinion 
that the Phedrus was one of the earliest, if not the very earliest, 
of Plato’s dialogues, and that therefore the opinion about Iso- 
crates was really a prophecy, which he never fulfilled.” Plato 
and Aristotle might very well entertain different opinions 





ῥητορικήν. The different kinds of examples are discussed in II. 20, and the 
enthymemes are considered in IT. 21—26. 

1 We believe that a little book illustrating Aristotle’s Rhetoric by extracts from 
Shakspere appeared at Oxford some twenty years ago. 

5. See Spengel, whi supra, pp. 458 sqq. 

3 Phedrus, p.271 C: ἐπειδὴ λόγου δύναμις τυγχάνει Puxaywyla οὖσα, τὸν μέλλοντα 
ῥητορικὸν ἔσεσθαι ἀνάγκη εἰδέναι, ψυχὴ ὅσα εἴδη ἔχει. Cf. 261 A: Gp οὖν οὐ τὸ μὲν 
ὅλον ἡ ῥητορικὴ ἂν εἴη ψυχαγωγία τις διὰ λόγων ; 

4 Rhet. 11. :-17. Cf. Spengel, u.s. p. 466. 

5 Above, chapter XX XIX. § 6, pp. 221, 222 (61, 62]. 

U 2 


292 ARISTOTLE. 


respecting this orator, and their personal relations with him 
might have contributed to this discrepancy. There is no reason 
to doubt that Plato and Isocrates were on friendly terms; and 
it is distinctly stated that this was far from being the case with 
the latter and Aristotle. We have seen how Aristotle spoke of 
Isocrates,' and it has been inferred that the orator glanced at 
Aristotle in the passage of his Panathenaicus, where he speaks 
of ‘certain vulgar Sophists of the Lyceum that professed to 
know everything,” and in his fifth epistle, which is considered 
genuine, there is a direct attack on the philosopher.’ It will 
be remarked, however, that there are no symptoms of hostility 
in the many references to Isocrates which are found in the 
Rhetoric. This frequency of citation has been explained by the 
fact that Aristotle was not himself a professed orator, like 
Anaximenes, and did not make examples ;* so that he would 
naturally take his illustrations from the best known and most 
available specimens of the art.° 

Diogenes Laertius gives a list of six rhetorical treatises attri- 
buted to Aristotle ;° one is the collection (Συναγωγή) already 
referred to, another is a book called Gryllus, another is the 
Rhetoric to Theodectes, which is quoted as the Theodectea’ in the 
third book of the great work, and the remaining three are 
merely designated as ‘the art of rhetoric in two books, ‘the 
art in one book,’ and ‘another art in two books.” Diogenes 
does not mention the Rhetoric to Alexander, which is still 
preserved among Aristotle’s writings, and which has been proved 





1 Above, p. 265 [105]. Spengel considers that the reproach in Hth. Nic. X. το, 
1181, 12, refers to the Antidosis of Isocrates, § 83. 

2 Panathenaicus, § 20, p. 236 D: ἀπαντήσαντες γάρ τινές μοι τῶν ἐπιτηδείων 
ἔλεγον ws ἐν τῷ Λυκείῳ συγκαθεζομένων τρεῖς ἢ τέτταρες τῶν ἀγελαίων σοφιστῶν 
καὶ πάντα φασκόντων εἰδέναι καὶ τάχεως πανταχοῦ γιγνομένων. This speech was not 
finished till B.c. 340, when Aristotle was at the court of Philip, so that the reference 
to Aristotle and his friends must be quite general and perhaps retrospective. 

3 Spengel, οὐδὲ supra, pp. 472 866. 4 Spengel, p. 474. 

5 Demosthenes is quoted twice only, IT. 23, § 3; ITI. 4, § 3. Liysias is referred 
to only once (III. το, ὃ 7), and Aschines, Antiphon, Andocides, Iseus, Hypereides, 
and Lycurgus, are not mentioned at all. He refers to orators of inferior reputa- 
tion, like Cleophon, Meerocles, Autocles, &c. 

6 See I, T. Buhlii Argumentum librorum Aristotelis de Rhetoricd, prefixed to 
the Oxford edition, 1833; Spengel, u. s. p. 476. 

7 III. 9, $9: αἱ δ᾽ ἀρχαὶ τῶν περιόδων σχεδὸν ἐν τοῖς Θεοδεκτείοις ἐξηρίθμηνται. 


RHETORIC. 293 


to be the work of his contemporary Anaximenes of Lampsacus.' 
It has been inferred also that the Theodectea was not written 
by Aristotle, but by his friend and scholar Theodectes.? The 
Gryllus, which is entirely lost, is cited by Quintilian as fur- 
nishing examples of Aristotle’s subtlety.® 

Aristotle’s essay on the Poetic Art (περὶ ποιητικῆς) is a mere 
fragment, abounding in interpolations. Some have supposed 
that it is an excerpt carelessly made from the two books on 
Poets, quoted by Macrobius.? It seems, however, that in its 
complete and original form it must have been quite as methodical 
and scientific as the Rhetoric. And it is a remarkable fact that, 
imperfect and fragmentary as the work now is, the Poetic was 
accepted as a sort of critical gospel at the very time when 
Aristotle’s philosophical reputation was at its lowest point. His 
briefly expressed doctrine that poetry takes its rise in the 
tendency to imitation which is natural to man,’ his hint that 
the drama originated in the recitations of the dithyrambic 
leaders,’ and the laws of unity which he prescribed, were made 





1 This was first shown by Victorinus and Majoragius, and has been abundantly 
proved by Spengel (Artiwm Scriptores, p. 182 sqq.), who has edited the treatise, as 
‘ Anaximenis Ars Rhetorica, que vulgo fertur Aristotelis ad Alexandrum, Turici 
et Vitoduri, 1844.’ 

2 That Theodectes wrote a τέχνη is well known. It is referred to by his con- 
temporary Antiphanes, the comic poet (ap. Athen. IV. p. 134 B): 

ὁ τὴν Θεοδέκτου μόνος ἀνευρηκὼς τέχνην : 

and is said by Suidas to have been written in verse: ἔγραψε δὲ καὶ τέχνην ῥητορι- 
κὴν ἐν μέτρῳ. Cf. Steph. Byz. s.v. Φάσηλις. But the book was attributed to 
Aristotle at an early period ; Quintilian speaks doubtfully on the subject (II. 15, 
§ 10). The words in the spurious letter to Alexander (prefixed to the τέχνη of 
Anaximenes, p. 4, 1. 23, Spengel) are quite unintelligible: ‘aut ego stupidus,’ 
says Spengel, ‘ et talp&4 cecior sum, qui nullum horum sensum videam, aut inep- 
tus fuit auctor, qui que nemo intelligere posset scriberet.’ On Theodectes in 
general the reader may consult Marcher, De Theodectis Phaselite Vitd et Scriptis 
Commentatio, Vratislavie, 1835. 

3 ΤΙ, 17, § 14: ‘Aristoteles, ut solet, querendi gratié quedam subtilitatis suze 
argumenta excogitavit in Gryllo.’ 

4 See F. Ritter’s edition of this tract, Coloniw, 1839, and our reprint of Twining’s 
translation in the Theatre of the Greeks, ed. 6; and compare Spengel’s essay in the 
Munich Transactions, 1837, 11. pp. 209 sqq. 

5 Saturnalia, V. 18, ὃ 19, p. 460, Janus; and cf. Stahr, Aristot. ὃ. ὦ. Rémer, 
Pp. 190 sqq. 

6 I. §2; see Raumer, in the Berlin Transactions for 1828. 

7 IV. § 12; see Theatre of the Greeks, ed. 6, pp. 13 8qq. 


294 ARISTOTLE. 


the texts for long disquisitions and complete works on the 
subject, at the time when Bacon’s inductive philosophy had 
driven Aristotle’s Organon out of the field, and stigmatized him 
as the author of a false and erroneous method. In spite of its 
mutilated condition,’ this relic exhibits the genuine style of 
Aristotle, and justifies in a great measure even the exaggerated 
importance which has been attributed to it. 

§ 6. Three works on the subject of moral philosophy are in- 
cluded in the extant collection of Aristotle’s writings. They 
are generally distinguished as the Kthica Nicomachea, the 
Ethica Eudemia, and the Magna Moralia. Their comparative 
genuineness has formed the subject of a good deal of discussion. 
Cicero’s supposition that the Nicomachean Ethics were not 
written by Aristotle, but by his son Nicomachus,’? was probably 
occasioned merely by the title, which may be explained in many 
ways, and is, in itself, quite insignificant. Schleiermacher be- 
lieved* that the Magna Moralia were a genuine work, and that 
the Eudemian Ethics were a report of Aristotle’s lectures pub- 
lished by his pupils. All these treatises are noticed by Dio- 
genes, and it is clear that they are all three of great antiquity. 
The most probable conclusion‘ is that the Nicomachean Ethics 
contain the authentic and original system of the philosopher 
himself ; that the Eudemian Ethics’ were the work of his pupil 
Eudemus of Rhodes; and that the Magna Moralia were merely 
a later extract from this second work. 

Of all Aristotle’s writings there is no one which retains its 





1 If we compare the tract as it stands with the design as stated in the first 
section, we shall see that the book originally contained discussions on comic and 
lyric poetry, which are now lost. ‘fo the lost remarks on comedy, Aristotle him- 
self refers, in his Rhet. III. 18, § 7: εἴρηται πόσα εἴδη γελοίων ἐστιν ἐν τοῖς wept 
Ποιητικῆς. 2 De Finibus, V. 5, ὃ 12. 

8 Werke, III. Abth. zur Philos. vol. III. pp. 306 sqq. 

4 This is Spengel’s view (Munich Transactions, vol. V. pp. 458 544.) 

5 The genuineness of books V. VI. VII. of the Nicomachean- Ethics, which cor- 
respond to books IV. V. VI. of the Zudemian Ethics, has been well maintained by 
Bendixen in two articles on the seventh book of the former, in Schneidewin’s 
Philologus for 1855, pp. 199, 544.; 263, sqq. He has called attention, inter alia, to the 
perpetual reminiscences of the seventh book in the Politics of Aristotle (p. 290), and 
this applies particularly to the main stumbling-block, Hih. Nic. VII. ce. 14, 15, 
for there is a distinct reference to ὁ. 14, Ὁ. 1153 Ὁ 7—18 in the Politics 1V. 11, 
p- 1295 ἃ 35 (see Bendixen pp. 201, sqq.). 


MORAL PHILOSOPHY. 295 


value and importance more entirely than the Nicomachean 
Ethics, especially if we consider them in connexion with his 
Politics. Indeed, this branch of philosophy has been retro- 
grading rather than advancing. In point of systematic con- 
nexion the Ethics may hold a place by the side of any modern 
book on the subject, and the searching logic, with which it is 
sifted in the Summa of Thomas Aquinas, shows the exactness 
and coherency of its framework. The great distinction between 
Aristotle and his predecessors, in regard to the discussion of 
moral philosophy, consists in the thoroughly practical view 
which he takes of happiness and virtue. Altogether rejecting 
the doctrine of Socrates, a doctrine partly adopted by Plato, 
that virtue consisted in the knowledge of what was right, Aris- 
totle believed that a general knowledge of what was good: might 
perfectly well consist with doing what was wrong in particular 
instances, under the influence of passion or inclination. And 
herein consists the distinction, on which he lays so much stress 
in his seventh book, between the man who is incontinent 
(ἀκρατής), that is, habitually unable to control his inclinations, 
and the man who is intemperate (ἀκόλαστος), that is, inten- 
tionally devoted to self-indulgence ;' the former being much less 
vicious than the latter, more likely to regret a misdoing, and 
more open to correction and amendment.* 

The Nicomachean Ethics are divided into ten books. It has 
been supposed by a German critic that the eighth and ninth 
books, which treat of friendship, formed a separate work, and 
that the discussion about pleasure in the tenth book was an 
addition by Aristotle’s son, Nicomachus.* And an English 





1 In Eth. Nic. VII. 4, §6, he says: ‘some act from deliberate choice (προαι- 
podvrat), but others do not: so that the name of intemperate (ἀκόλαστος) should 
rather be given to him who, either without a passionate impulse, or with only a 
moderate one (ὅστις μηδ᾽ ἐπιθυμῶν ἢ ἤρεμα), pursues excessive pleasures, and eschews 
- moderate annoyances, than to him who does this under a strong inclination ; for 
what would the other do, if a violent impulse were superadded, and some over- 
powering feeling of uneasiness in regard to necessary wants ? 

2 Eth. Nic. VII. 8, § 1: ἔστι δὲ ὁ μὲν ἀκόλαστος, ὥσπερ ἐλέχθη, οὐ μεταμελητικός, 
ἐμμένει γὰρ τῇ προαιρέσει" ὁ δ᾽ ἀκρατὴς μεταμελητικὸς πᾶς διὸ οὐχ ὥσπερ ἠπορή- 
σαμεν, οὕτω καὶ ἔχει" ἀλλ᾽ ὁ μὲν ἀνίατος, ὁ δὲ ἰατός. 

3 Pansch, De Ethicis Nicomacheis, Bonn, 1833. The eighth and ninth books of 
the Fthics have been published separately, as: ᾿Αριστοτέλης περὶ φιλίας, by A. T. 
H. Fritzsch, Gisse, 1847. 


296 ARISTOTLE. 


scholar’ has quite recently advanced the theory that the fifth, 
sixth, and seventh books were borrowed from the Eudemian 
Ethics to supply a gap which was observed in the treatise which 
bears the name of its editor Nicomachus, and that the essay on 
friendship, though by Aristotle himself, is an unessential ad- 
junct, originally in the form of a special essay. 

But these are mere conjectures, and it is not difficult to see 
that the work, as we have it, is a continuous essay, in three 
main subdivisions. The first part, which comprises the first 
and second books, and five chapters of the third, treats of the 
chief good and virtue; the second part, which includes the re- 
mainder of the third book, and the fourth, fifth, and sixth, dis- 
cusses the different virtues; the third part, which contains the 
seventh, eighth, ninth, and tenth books, investigates the out- 
ward furniture of virtue, namely, continence, which belongs to 
the rational part of the soul, friendship, which pertains to the 
social appetite, and pleasure, which is referred to the instinct of 
self-preservation. And these points being discussed, the author 
returns to the subject of the first book, namely, happiness, and 
with an accurate recapitulation on this subject he passes on to 
the treatise on Politics. 

The Nicomachean Ethics begin with an inquiry respecting 
the ends of human action. The chief of these ends being ad- 
mitted to be happiness, it is of course the main point to de- 
termine wherein happiness consists. It cannot be limited to 
pleasure, honour, or intellect, for these, though desirable on 
their own account, are chiefly sought on account of the felicity 
to which they contribute. Admitting the importance of external 
adjuncts, as the necessary furniture of good fortune, Aristotle is 
content to define happiness as ‘ an activity, operation, or function 
of the soul, in accordance with perfect virtue’ (ἡ εὐδαιμονία 
ἐστι ψυχῆς ἐνέργειά τις κατ᾽ ἀρετὴν τελείαν). And hence it 
follows that the question respecting the ends of action resolves 





1 Sir Alexander Grant, in the introduction to his edition of the Zthics, London, 
1857, p. 43. See also Mr. Munro’s paper in the Jowrnal of Philology for 1855, 
pp. 68 sqq. 

2 The student will find a good analysis of the Nicomachean Ethics, especially 
with reference to Aristotle’s treatment of ustice and friendship, in Mr. Maurice’s 
Ancient Philosophy, pp. 200—208 3 Eth. Nic. I. 13, § 14. 


MORAL PHILOSOPHY. 297 


itself into an inquiry respecting the nature of virtue. As the 
seat of virtue is the soul, the moral philosopher is required to 
have some knowledge of mental philosophy. Aristotle indicates 
that the soul is bipartite... Considered as the vital principle, it 
is either rational or irrational. As far as it is merely irrational, 
it is common to men and brutes, and therefore does not enter 
into the question about human virtue and happiness. So far, 
however, as it partakes of, or is capable of listening to reason— 
that is, so far as it belongs to appetite and desire—the irra- 
tional part of the soul may be regarded as constituting the seat 
of a particular class of virtues. Accordingly Aristotle distin- 
guishes between the intellectual virtues (ἀρεταὶ διανοητικαί), such 
as wisdom, understanding, and prudence, which belong strictly 
to the rational part of the soul, and the moral virtues (aperat 
ἠθικαί), such as liberality and temperance, which are referred 
to the commendable habits (ἕξεις érawerai) of the irrational 
or merely appetitive branch of the soul. Passing on to the 
definition of virtue, Aristotle gives us an elaborate discussion in 
support of his view, that virtue is a mean between two extremes 
of vice; that it always stands half-way between the too much 
and the too little. Thus true courage is a mean between temerity 
and cowardice. The two opposites, and even the virtues them- 
selves, are not always recognized or indicated by names in 
ordinary language, and sometimes those who are guilty of one 





1 The following is the subdivision suggested in the Nicomachean Ethics I. 13; 
see Pol. 4 (VII.) 15. 


ΤΕ 

















| os 

ἄλογον ἄλογον μετέχον πη λόγον λόγον ἔχον 
(θρεπτικόν, (ἐπιθυμητικόν, « eed Ἔ 
φυτικόν) ὀρεκτικόν) ὩΣ ἢ ἀρεταί 

Pen τωι, ; ἴα. 

ἠθικαὶ ἀρεταί LOTLKOV, ἐπιστημονικόν 

αἀστικόν 
πε ες a | le ot | 
φυσικὴ ἀρετή ἡ κυρία φρόνησις | |. τέχνη 
| ! δεινότης δόξα | 


ἐπιστήμη, σοφία, ae 
2 Thus there is a nameless virtue, which bears the same relation to magnanimity 
that liberality does to magnificence, and which observes the proper mean between 
the excessive and defective pursuit of honour: Zth. Nic. IV. ο. 4. 


298 ARISTOTLE. 


or the other extreme consider their vicious opposite to be the 
man who adheres to the golden mean of virtue. Still this defi- 
nition is the necessary result of a scientific analysis of every 
moral virtue. This analysis Aristotle undertakes in the second 
part of his work, examining the moral virtues in general in the 
third and fourth books, and justice in particular in the fifth; 
because, as we have seen, Plato had made this the regulative 
principle of all morality, and, also, because justice is not, like 
the other virtues, a mean between two opposite extremes of vice, 
but rather belongs to that which is the mean between the too 
much and too little of a man’s rights, whereas injustice belongs 
to both extremes. in this respect.’ The sixth book is devoted 
to the intellectual virtues.. He then, as he says, makes another 
beginning in the seventh book, and treats here of continence 
and incontinence, the general result of his investigation being 
given in the words which Dante puts into the mouth of Virgil. 
‘ Do you not remember,’ says the poet,’ ‘those words in which 
your Ethics thoroughly discuss the three habits or dispositions 
which are offensive to heaven, incontinence (ἀκρασία), malice 
(κακία), and low brutality (θηριότης), and how it is that imeon- 
tinence incurs the least blame of the three?’ In fact, Aristotle 
regards incontinence rather as a weakness incident to the com- 
posite nature of man, than as a vice springing from a depravity 
of will or choice, and, therefore, makes great allowances for it. 
These three important discussions on justice, the intellectual 
virtues, and incontinence, which occupy the fifth, sixth, and 
seventh books of the Nicomachean Ethics, re-appear, in extenso, 
in the fourth, fifth, and sixth books of the Eudemian Ethics ; 
and there is no doubt that they were regarded by the followers 
of Aristotle as constituting one of the most characteristic and 
instructive portions of his morgl philosophy. The eighth and 





1 Eth. Nic. V.9: ἡ δὲ δικαιοσύνη μεσότης ob τὸν αὐτὸν τρόπον ταῖς πρότερον 
ἀρεταῖς, ἀλλ᾽ ὅτι μέσου ἐστίν" ἡ δ᾽ ἀδικία τῶν ἄκρων. 
2 Inferno ΧΙ. 79: 
Non ti rimembra di quelle parole 
Con le quai la tua Etica pertratta 
Le tre disposizion ch ’] ciel non vuole, 
Incontinenza, malizia, 6 la matta 
Bestialitade? 6. come incontinenza 
Men Dio offende 6 men biasimo accatta ? 


POLITICS. . 299 


ninth books contain an interesting inquiry respecting friend- 
ship, in which it is shown not only that virtue is essential to _ 
true friendship, but also that true friendship is essential to per- 
fect happiness. In the first part of the tenth book, we have 
an essay on pleasure, practically considered ; and, while it is 
admitted that pleasure is a good, it is proved that it cannot be 
regarded as the summum bonum. Aristotle defines pleasure as 
that which perfects the operation (τελειοῖ τὴν ἐνεργείαν ἡ 
ἡδονή), for, as pleasure is found by the side of every sensation, 
and in like manner may be produced by every exertion of the 
intellect and every speculation, that which is most perfect and 
complete is also most pleasurable. From pleasure he returns 
to happiness. As happiness is not a habit (ἕξις), but an ac- 
tivity or operation (ἐνέργεια) in itself desirable, and as the 
best of these operations is that of the intellect itself, he con- 
cludes that the highest of all happinesses is the contemplative 
(θεωρητική). This is superior to active happiness, for, while 
the latter is human, the former is divine. In the epilogue to 
the whole work he shows that, with a view to the practice of 
virtue, not only moral discipline, but civil government, are ne- 
cessary, and so paves the way for the political theory which is 
the proper supplement to his moral philosophy. 

The tract On Virtues and Vices, which is printed among Aris- 
totle’s writings, is obviously the work of some later Peripatetic. 

§ 7. It is now generally admitted that Aristotle’s important 
treatise on Politics, in which he carries out the views pro- 
pounded in his Nicomachean Ethics, has come down to us in a 
very confused arrangement of the eight books of which it con- 
sists. The following is the order which best preserves the 
sequence of thought in the work :’*—the first three books retain 
their original places; they are followed by the seventh and 
eighth ; the sixth place is assigned to the fourth book of the 
manuscripts ; and the work is concluded by the sixth and fifth 
books in this inverted position.® ‘The new arrangement,’ says 





1 Eth. Nic. X, 4, § 7. 

2 See Spengel, in the Munich Transactions for 1849, and the introductory matter 
to Mr. Congreve’s edition of the Politics, Oxford, 1855. 

® Marking the books of the older editions by Roman letters, and those of the 


900 ARISTOTLE. 


the latest editor of the Politics,’ “ brings into close juxtaposition 
two books, 6 and 7 (IV. VI.), whose separation is clearly the 
result of some accident, and whose re-arrangement is advocated 
even by the staunchest opponents of the change in general. 
Again, by placing 4 and 5 (VII. VIII.) immediately after 
3 (111.), the new order makes Aristotle’s aristocracy, or ideal 
state, the second of the two correct forms of government, follow 
directly on his treatment of monarchy or the first, and precede 
his treatment of Politeia or the third. Whereas, in the exist- 
ing arrangement, this third form is interposed between the first 
and second. Lastly, after the analysis of the two first ideal 
forms has been gone through, he proceeds, by a separate treat- 
ment of the elements of the third form, to prepare a way for 
the treatment of those elements in combination—in other words, 
for the treatment of that third form. Its discussion over, he 
goes through the problems connected with existing governments, 
their formation and their organization—he elaborates, that is, 
the statics of Greek Society. Then, in the absence of any 
theory or expectation of change, there is nothing left for him 
but to treat of the diseases to which that society was liable, its 
chronic state of dissension, its acute one of revolution.’ 

The first book of the Politics is a general introduction, con- 
necting this work with the Nicomachean Ethics. It is, in fact, 
a discussion on the principles of @iconomics, on which we have 
a separate treatise in our collection of Aristotle’s works. Aris- 
totle passes briefly over the relations of male and female, as the 
origin of social union, examines at great length the questions 
relating to slavery and property in general, and finishes with a 
summary review of the family relation, and the qualifications 
and duties of the governed. It is his theory that the female 
and the slave are essentially and naturally inferior to the male 
and the master. ‘ Nature,’ he says, ‘makes nothing in a 
niggardly manner, as the cutlers make the Delphic knife to 
serve a variety of purposes,’ but everything is made separately 





improved arrangement by Arabic numerals, they will stand thus: 1 (I), 2 (11), 3 
(IID), 4 (VID), 5 (VILD, 6 (IV), 7 (VD, 8 (V). 

1 Mr. Congreve, Preface, p. V. 

2 Pol. I. 2: οὔθεν yap ἡ φύσις ποιεῖ τοιοῦτον οἷον χαλκοτύποι τὴν Δελφικὴν μάχαι- 
ραν πενιχρῶς ἀλλ᾽ ἕν πρὸς ἕν. A good deal has been said by the commentators about 
this Δελφικὴ μάχαιρα. Gottling has a strange notion as to its being made of 


POLITICS. 301 


with a view to its special and proper work.’ One cannot read 
without astonishment the arguments by which Aristotle endea- 
yours to justify slavery. Considering that this relationship so 
often sprung from the accidents of war, and that the most cul- 
tivated Athenian might at any time become the slave of an 
uncivilized foreigner, it seems difficult to understand how Aris- 
totle’s acuteness and common sense could acquiesce in the sophis- 
tical and fallacious reasoning, that there was an analogous 
difference between the Greek and the barbarian, between the 
master and the slave, between the soul and the body, and his 
notion of government as presuming a regard for the interest of 
the governed is subverted by the fact that the state of slavery 
can never be beneficial to the slave. However, these opinions, 
strange as they seem to us, were really entertained by Aris- 
totle, and are involved in his famous recommendation to Alex- 
ander, to treat the Greeks as their general (ἡγεμονικῶς) and 
the barbarians as their master (Ssorortkwc). 

The second book is, in one sense, an episode, which might 
have been dropped without much injury to the general course 
of the reasoning. But Aristotle considered it necessary, per- 
haps, to prefix to the statement of his own theory on the sub- 
ject a review, not only of former speculations, but also of exist- 
ing polities. The first five chapters examine the Republic, the 
sixth the Laws of Plato; he then passes on to the proposed 
constitution of Phaleas the Chalcedonian, who argued for an 
equalization of property ; to that of Hippodamus of Miletus, 
with his minute and refined distinctions ; then to those of the 
Spartans, Cretans, and Carthaginians; and finishes the book 
with miscellaneous remarks on Solon and other lawgivers. 

In the third book, Aristotle undertakes a development of his 
own ideal. After a preamble, in five chapters, defining the citizen 





different materials. It was manifestly used for more than one purpose, and was, 
in all probability, a ξιφομάχαιρα, having a straight edge and point at the back, and 
a concave edge in front. The Romans had a complicated instrument of the same 
kind called the falx vinitoria, which was furnished with a variety of edges in order 
to meet the various operations required in vine-pruning. Platorefers to the specific 
use of the μάχαιρα as distinguished even from that of the δρέπανον in Resp. I. p. 
353 A. The story of the Delphic priest Machereus, who killed Neoptolemus with 
his μάχαιρα (see commentators on Pind. N. VII. 42), shows that this instrument 
had its special use in that temple. 1 Above, p. 268 [108]. 


302 ARISTOTLE. 


and the identity of the state, and discussing the questions 
whether the good man and the good citizen are one and the 
same, and whether the mean handicraftsman (βάναυσος) can 
be regarded as a citizen, Aristotle proceeds to consider the 
different kinds of government. According to the unity, plu- 
rality, or multeity of the governing body, the state is a 
monarchy, an aristocracy, or a commonwealth (πολιτεία), and if 
these act up to their true principles, they consider the interest 
of the governed ; otherwise, the monarchy becomes a tyranny, 
the aristocracy an oligarchy, and the commonwealth a demo- 
cracy. All these varieties are adequately examined, and the 
philosopher gives the preference to an aristocracy in which the 
ruling body is duly qualified by moral and intellectual edu- 
cation ; and this, as we have seen,’ is the established conclusion 
of the Socratic schools. 

As the third book concludes by referring the best form of 
government to the best and most desirable life (πρὸς τὴν 
αἱρετωτάτην Cw), the fourth book (4, VII.) in the improved 
arrangement begins with inquiring what this best life is. The 
discussion of this is expressly regarded as a preface ;* and then 
follows the detailed argument about the best form of the state, 
the number of its citizens, the geographical features of the 
country, the situation of the city, the character of the people, 
the castes and constitution, and, above all, the education of the 
burgesses. This last and most important question is pursued 
in the following book (5, VIII), which is unfortunately left 
in a fragmentary state, and it has been conjectured that this in- 
completeness has been one of the reasons why the fifth book 
has been placed at the end of the work in the old arrangement. 

In the last three books (6, IV., 7, VII., 8, V.), Aristotle applies 
his practical observations and philosophical theory to a considera- 
tion of the actual governments of Greece. © Tyranny being 
much less common than oligarchy and democracy, it is of 
these two that he chiefly speaks. Like the literary men of the 





1 Above, chapter XX XVII. 8 2. 

2 Pol. 111. 18: ἐπεὶ δὲ τρεῖς φαμὲν εἶναι τὰς ὀρθὰς πολιτείας, τούτων δ᾽ ἀναγκαῖον 
ἀρίστην εἶναι τὴν ὑπὸ ἀρίστων οἰκονομουμένην, τοιαύτη δ᾽ ἐστὶν ἐν ἧ συμβέβηκεν ἣ ἕνα 
συμπάντων ἢ γένος ὅλον ἢ πλῆθος ὑπέρεχον εἶναι κατ᾽ ἀρετήν, τῶν μὲν ἄρχεσθαι 
δυναμένων τῶν δ᾽ ἄρχειν πρὸς τὴν αἱρετωτάτην ζωήν. 

3 Pol. 4, VIL. 4: ἐπεὶ δὲ πεφροιμίασται τὰ νῦν εἰρημένα. 


NATURAL HISTORY. 808 


preceding century, he thought that the best average government 
was that in which the rulers were found in the middle class :} 
and between oligarchy and democracy, he gives the preference 
to the latter; showing, at length, that the tendency to faction 
(στάσις) and revolution (wera(30An) was less in democracy than 
in oligarchy, and therefore that the former was practically the 
most healthy and permanent of existing constitutions. The work 
terminates rather abruptly with some strictures on the Republic 
of Plato, in regard to the laws of revolutionary change laid 
down in that dialogue. 

The main points of the science of Ciconomics are discussed 
in the first book of the Politics, but we have a separate treatise 
on this subject in the collection of Aristotle's works”? <A 
quotation in the fragment of Philodemus found among the 
manuscripts at Herculaneum attributes the first book to 
Theophrastus ;* and Niebuhr has shown that the second book 
was probably written in Asia Minor after the death of Ophelas, 
in Ol. 118, 1, B.c. 308." 

§ 8. In comparing the literary remains of Aristotle with 
those of Plato, we cannot but be struck with the extent and 
importance of the physical speculations ‘in which the former 
engaged, and the very small and subordinate value assigned to 
natural philosophy by the latter. Whereas the Timeus is the 
only dialogue in which Plato enters professedly on a theory 
respecting the visible world, we find that Aristotle composed 
many elaborate works—some of the most important being no 
longer extant—on every detail of physical science; and even 
his work On the Soul, which we have considered with reference 
to his metaphysical speculations, was probably connected very 
intimately with this series of treatises. So that it has been 
said with justice by an ancient writer that while Aristotle 
physiologizes in his metaphysics, Plato’s physiology is but an 
application of his metaphysical reasonings.° 

The physical works of Aristotle may be considered as forming 





1 Pol, V.6, IV. 11. See above, chapter XXX VII. ὃ 2. 
2 Οἰκονομικῶν d, B’. 3 Herculanens, Volwmina, III. p. vii. and xxviii. 
4 Niebuhr’s Kleine Schriften, pp. 412—416. 


5 Schol. Aristot. 26,27: ᾿Αριστοτέλης μὲν ἀεὶ θεολογῶν φυσιολογεῖ, Πλάτων δὲ 
ἀεὶ φυσιολογῶν θεολογεῖ. 


804 ARISTOTLE. 


the integral parts of a regular and systematic series, and the 
following suggestions have been made for their arrangement :'— 

I. The introduction is formed by the eight books of ‘the 
physical lectures’ (φυσικὴ ἀκρόασις, naturalis auscultatio), which, 
as Hegel says, are ‘a metaphysic of physics.’ They treat of 
principles (ἀρχαί) and their number, of motion, of space and 
time, of the first unmoved moving power (πρῶτον κίνουν 
ἀκίνητον), the perpetually moved (ἀεικίνητον), which is neces- 
sarily circular, and according to the ancients realized in the 
heaven ; and here we have a transition to :— 

II. The four books ‘concerning heaven’ (περὶ οὐρανοῦ, de celo). 
According to Aristotle, this heaven is an unchangeable region 
(ἀεὶ ταυτὸν Kal ὡσαύτως ἔχον) , the first of all bodies (τὸ πρῶτον 
τῶν σωμάτων), which, being itself indestructible, is the opposite 
of all that is corruptible. 

III. Next in succession to the treatise on heaven, we have 
the two books ‘on generation and destruction’ (περὶ γενέσεως 
καὶ φθορας). Here he developes his theory that the first prin- 
ciples are not the four elements which were supposed, after the 
time of Empedocles, to produce life and death by their inter- 
mixture, but composite nature itself, the fundamental properties 
being the hot, the cold, the dry, and the moist; and of these, 
the mixture of hot and dry makes fire, that of hot and moist 
makes air, that of cold and dry makes earth, and that of cold 
and moist makes water.’ 

IV. The further prosecution of these speculations is found in ~ 
the four books ‘on meteorology’ (μετεωρολογικά, de meteoris), 
or rather in the first three of them; for the fourth book does 
not stand in any real connexion with the others, and it has 
been conjectured* that it was a separate tract entitled ‘on the 
consolidation of bodies’ (περὶ τῆς τῶν σωάτων συστάσεως). 





1 See Spengel, iiber die Reihenfolge der naturwissensch. Schriften des A ristoteles : 
Munich Transactions, 1849, pp. 143 sqq. There is also a good summary of 
Aristotle’s labours in physical philosophy, in Dr. Whewell’s History of the Inductive 
Sciences, vol. I. section 2. 

2 De Gener. et corrupt. II. 3, § 2: τὸ μὲν γὰρ πῦρ θερμὸν καὶ ξηρόν, ὁ δ᾽ ἀὴρ θερμὸν 
καὶ ὑγρόν (οἷον ἀτμὶς yap ὁ ἀήρ), τὸ δ᾽ ὕδωρ ψυχρὸν καὶ ὑγρόν, ἡ δὲ γῆ ψυχρὸν καὶ 
ξηρόν, ὥστ᾽ εὐλόγως διανέμεσθαι τὰς διαφορὰς τοῖς πρώτοις σώμασι καὶ τὸ πλῆθος 
αὐτῶν εἶναι κατὰ λόγον. 


3 Spengel, u.s., p. 156. This title is indicated in several passages ; for instance, 


NATURAL HISTORY. 305 


_ Y. The treatise ‘on the universe’ (περὶ κόσμου), which 
follows next in the Parva Naturalia, is generally admitted to be 
an extraneous addition to Aristotle’s works. It is, in fact, a 
general review of the books ‘on heaven, ‘on generation,’ &c., 
and ‘on meteorology’ (II., III., [V.); and its rhetorical style 
and stoical tone show that Aristotle could not have written it. 
Various suppositions have been made respecting the authorship. 
One critic attributes it to Chrysippus.’ Another writer main- 
tains that it is the Greek translation of a work with the same 
title by Apuleius;? and, conversely, the latest editor of 
Apuleius® regards the Greek as the original, and the Latin as 
the translation. 

VI. We are informed that Aristotle wrote no less than fifty, 
or, as one writer says, seventy treatises on his favourite subject 
of zoology. Of these we have but a small portion. It has 
been shown that the general introduction was furnished by the 
first of the four books, still extant, under the title ‘on the 
parts of animals’ (περὶ ζῴων μορίων). In the sixth chapter 
we have an expression which seems to furnish the transition 
from the discussion of indestructible substances (ἀφθαρτα)" to 
those of the world of life; and it would be in accordance with 
Aristotle’s general procedure that he should discuss the parts 
or elements before he examined the composite structure or the 
animal as a whole. 

VII. For a similar reason, he probably intended his treatise 
‘on the generation of animals’ (περὶ ζῴων γενέσεως), in five 
books, to be a preparatory treatise on the causes (διότι) of 
organic natural bodies, without which he could hardly discuss 





c. 8: ἐκ μὲν οὖν ὕδατος καὶ γῆς τὰ ὁμοιομερὴ σώματα συνίσταται; ο. 10: ἐξ ὧν 
ἤδη συνέστηκε τὰ ὁμοιομερῆ; c. 12: ἔχομεν γὰρ ἐξ ὧν ἡ τῶν ὁμοιομερῶν 
φύσις συνέστηκε... . δηλωθέντων δὲ τούτων τὰ μὴ ὁμοιομερῇ θεωρητέον καὶ τέλος 
τὰ ἐκ τούτων συνεστῶτα, οἷον ἄνθρωπον, φυτόν, καὶ τᾶλλα τὰ τοιαῦτα. 

_ ἢ Osann, Beitr. z. Gr. u. Rim. Litt. Gesch. I. pp. 141—283. 

2 Stahr, Arist. bei den Rimern, p. 165. 

8 Hildebrand, Prol. ad Apuleiwm, I. pp. XLI. sqq. 
peeubiny,H.V. ὙΠ. τη, 66. 

5 Titze, de Aristotelis operum serie, p. 55, 8. 

6 ἐπεὶ δὲ περὶ ἐκείνων (τῶν ἀφθάρτων) διήλθομεν λέγοντες τὸ φαινόμενον ἡμῖν, 
λοιπὸν περὶ τῆς ζωικῆς φύσεως εἰπεῖν μηδὲν παραλιπόντας εἰς δύναμιν μήτε ἀτιμότερον 
μήτε τιμιώτερον. , 

Vou. II. x 


306 ARISTOTLE. 


in a satisfactory manner the phenomena (ὅτι) themselves. 
Passages may be cited’ to a contrary effect from the books 
themselves ; but if these passages are carefully examined, they 
will be found to justify the inference that with Aristotle the 
general speculation preceded the description of life as it exists ? 
and the books on natural history are full of references to his 
theory of generation, as if some previous acquaintance with it 
was implied. 

VIII. Of the great work ‘on the history of animals’ (περὶ 
ζῴων ἱστορία or ζωϊκὴ ἱστορία) we have only nine books com- 
plete. There are different opinions respecting the tenth book, 
which is added in the manuscripts and the usual editions. 
Scaliger proposed to insert it between the seventh and eighth 
books ; according to Camus, it was the treatise mentioned by 
Diogenes under the title ‘ about non-productiveness’ (ὑπὲρ τοῦ 
μὴ γεννᾶν, de non gignendo) ; Schneider questions its genuine- 
ness; and it is attributed to the Latin recension of Aristotle’s 
works in a notice which appears in several manuscripts. This 
work of Aristotle’s is in many respects a wonderful performance. 
And its author may be regarded as the first founder of zoology 
and comparative anatomy. The books which we have contain 
a methodical description of the different varieties of the animal 





1 See Spengel, u.s. p. 161. 

2 One of the most important passages is the following ; De gen. Anim. v. 1, 8. δὲ 
ὥσπερ γὰρ ἐλέχθη κατ᾽ ἀρχὰς ἐν τοῖς πρώτοις λόγοις οὐ διὰ τὸ γίγνεσθαι ἕκάστον 
ποῖόν τι διὰ τοῦτο ποῖόν τι ἐστι, ὅσα τεταγμένα καὶ ὡρισμένα ἔργα τῆς φύδεως ἐστιν, 
ἀλλὰ μᾶλλον διὰ τὸ εἶναι τοιαδὶ γίγνεται τοιαῦτα" τῇ γὰρ οὐσίᾳ ἡ γένεσις ἀκολουθεῖ 
καὶ τῆς οὐσίας ἕνεκά ἐστιν, ἀλλ᾽ οὐχ αὕτη τῇ γενέσε. Now the πρώτη φιλοσοφία 
is expressly a consideration of the doctrine of causes, and the very fact that, as 
we have seen, the σωμάτων σύστασις is considered after the elements have been 
discussed, would seem to show that the description of the animal, as a particular 
σύστασις, would follow the general theory of its procreation. Otherwise we must 
infer that even the Politics were antecedent to the books on generation ; for 
Aristotle says (Pol. 4 [VII.], 15): φανερὸν δὴ Τοῦτό ye πρῶτον μὲν καθάπερ ἐν 
τοῖς ἄλλοις, ὡς ἡ γένεσις ἀπ᾽ ἀρχῆς ἐστὶ καὶ τὸ τέλος ἀπό Twos ἀρχῆς ἄλλου τέλους. 
For if the birth of the child is not the first step in the process of education, this 
can only be understood by substituting importance for priority. The unfinished 
state of the natural history is some argument for the conclusion that these details 
were prosecuted subsequently to the foundation of the principles, and references 
like the following may be very well understood as applying to investigations still 
in progress; De partibus Animal. IIL. 5, 18: τὸ δὲ μετ᾽ ἀκριβείας ὡς ἔχδυδιν al 
φλέβες πρὸς ἀλλήλας Ex Te τῶν ἀνατομιῶν δεῖ θεωρεῖν καὶ ἐκ τῆς ζωικῆς ioroplas. 


MISCELLANIES. 307 


kingdom; and the various animals are exhibited according to 
their characteristic features, with especial reference to their 
mode of life, instinctive habits, and the reproduction of the 
species. 

Aristotle’s other works on natural philosophy are an essay 
‘on the motion of animals’ (περὶ ζῴων κινήσεως), a series of 
tracts on memory, sleep, dreams, and divination in dreams, 
longevity, youth and age, respiration, life and death, which are 
collected together as his Parva Naturalia, and a fragment ‘ on 
colours’ (περὶ χρωμάτων). The two books ‘on plants’ (περὶ 
φυτῶν) seem to be described in ‘ the prologue of the interpreter’ 
(πρόλογος τοῦ ἑρμηνέως) as a translation from the Latin version 
of an Arabic edition of the work.’ Although Theophrastus is 
better known by his performances as a botanist, there can be 
little doubt that Aristotle was the real founder of botany as a 
science. 

It is usual to class the three books ‘on the soul’ with the 
physical works of Aristotle, and there can be no doubt that they 
may be regarded strictly in this connexion. But the work belongs 
also to his theory of the philosophy of mind, and we have 
preferred to consider it with his metaphysical treatises. Aris- 
totle’s writings on anatomy, to which he frequently refers, and 
one of which, in eight books, is mentioned by Diogenes, are 
entirely lost. 

δ 9. Besides the treatises on the main branches of philo- 
sophy which we have considered in this brief review, Aristotle 
has left a number of miscellaneous works, which cannot be 
included in the general classification. Thus, we have a col- 
lection of ‘ Problems’ (προβλήματα), in thirty-six sections, 
which abound in acute suggestions on almost every department 
of knowledge. They are put in the form of questions; thus :? 
‘Why does an unknown road seem to be, ceteris paribus, 





1 E. H. F. Meyer maintains that this book is a compilation by Nicolas of 
Damascus from the writings of Aristotle and Theophrastus, and has so published 
it: Nicolat Damasceni de Plantis libri duo Aristoteli vulgo adscripti, Lips. 1841. 
see p. XVIII. 

2 Problem. XXX. 4: διὰ τί δοκεῖ ἡμῖν πλείων εἶναι ἡ ὁδός, ὅταν wh εἰδότες 
πόση τις ἐστι βαδίζωμεν μᾶλλον ἢ ὅταν εἰδότες, ἐὰν τὰ ἄλλα ὁμοίως τύχωμεν 
ἔχοντες ; 


x 2 


308 ARISTOTLE: 


longer than one with which we are acquainted? Or is it 
because our knowledge of it is a knowledge of number? For 
that which is indefinite and that which is unnumbered are one 
and the same; and the indefinite is always more than the 
finite,’ and so on. Abelard’s treatise called Sic et Non is an 
analogous work, but in this the cases are stated pro and contra 
with reference only to authority. The ‘surprising stories’ 
(θαυμάσια ἀκούσματα) are a collection of anecdotes chiefly 
relating to the curiosities of natural history. It is not at all 
certain that this tract was written by Aristotle. From the 
commencement of the ‘ Mechanics’ (μηχανικά)" it would seem 
that this tract had some connexion, at least in the minds of 
those who arranged Aristotle’s works, with the θαυμάσια 
ἀκούσματα, which it follows in the editions. Its form, how- 
ever, is that of the ‘ Problems,’ 

Andronicus of Rhodes had collected twenty books of Aris- 
totle’s letters,’ and there. was a later collection by Artemon in 
eight books.* These are all lost; and the six letters now 
attributed to the philosopher are spurious.’ His speeches also 
have not been preserved. We have already referred to his 
poem on virtue, and to the epigrams attributed to him.® 

ὃ το. Aristotle’s writings are not less remarkable for their 
peculiar style and literary form than for their extent and the 
importance of their subjects, which he was the first to treat in 
a methodical and scientific manner. The parsimonious diction 
and the strict regularity with which the thoughts and facts are 
marshalled justify the remark of the poet Gray, that, when we 
are reading Aristotle, we feel as if we were studying a table 
of contents. And a more recent writer has accounted for this 
peculiarity by a reference to the characteristics which distin- 
guish Aristotle from his great teacher, Plato. ‘To collect all 
possible facts, to arrange and classify them, was his ambition, 
and perhaps his appointed function; no one is less tempted to 
find any deep meaning in facts, or to grope after it. In like 
manner, to get words pressed and settled into a definition is 





1 θαυμάζεται τῶν μὲν κατὰ φύσιν συμβαινόντων K.T.r., 
2 Demetrius, De Elocutione, “ὃ 231. 3 David, Categ. p. 24. 
4 See Stahr, Aristotelia, II. pp. 167 sqq. 5 Above, § 1. 


STYLE OF HIS WRITINGS. 309 


his highest aim ; the thought that there is a life in words, that 
they are connected with the life in us, and may lead at all to 
the interpretation of its marvels, never was admitted into his 
mind, or at least never tarried there,’ If the philosopher’s 
chief recommendation had been his style, he would have had 
few readers. He has nothing to attract those, who prefer the 
form and outer embellishments of a work to its subject-matter 
and the scientific results which it presents. Like Bishop 
Butler, one of the best of our English moralists, he repels all 
those who open his books with any other view than a desire of 
obtaining knowledge and amassing the materials and the results 
of thought. Those especially, who come to the study of 
Aristotle after contracting a familiarity with Plato, cannot but 
be impressed with the feeling that they have entered upon an 
entirely new phase of the Greek language—that they have 
passed, as it were, from a sunlit garden, gay with flowers, 
to a dark and chilly reading-room. But although Aristotle’s 
language is in the highest degree jejune and unornamented, he 
is never really obscure except when this arises from excessive 
brevity. And it may be inferred, from the fragments of his 
dialogues, and from his scolium on virtue, that the sobriety of 
his diction did not arise from any inability to express himself 
in more florid. language, and that he adopted deliberately, and 
perhaps by ar effort, a mode of writing which he considered 
more appropriate to: philosophical imvestigations than the 
exuberant and often redundant phraseology of the conventional 
rhetoric. The importance which he attached to conciseness 
and fixity of expression is shown by the fact that he has 
introduced a considerable number of well-defined words and 
phrases, which often. obviate the necessity for circumlocution.’ 





1 Maurice,. Ancient Philosophy, p. 163. 

2 The following are some of the words and phrases which: Aristotle either intro- 
duced, or used with some precise and original distinctness of meaning: ἐντελέχεια, 
ἐνέργεια, δύναμις, ἕξις, ἄλογος, μεσότης,. κατηγορία, συλλογισμός, ἐνθύμημα, παρά- 
δείγμα, ἐπαγωγή, πρότασις, ὕλη, τὸ ὑποκείμενον, ῥῆμα, ὄνομα, συνώνυμος, ὁμώνυμος, 
παρώνυμος, ἀκράτης, ἀκόλαστος, οὐσία, τί ἐστί, τὸ τί ἢν εἶναι, δικαίωμα ; and to 
these many others might be added. Bacon says that Aristotle ‘nova artium 
vocabula pro libitu cudendi licentiam usurpavit’ (De Augm. Scient. III. 4, p. 584, 
ed. Ellis, where the reader will see Bacon’s comparison of the correlative ambition 
of Aristotle and his pupil Alexander). 


310 ARISTOTLE. 


And, as we have already mentioned, one of the works included 
in his Metaphysica is an elaborate investigation of many terms 
and notions which seemed to him to require a more accurate 
definition.’ There are some to whom this logical precision, 
and scrupulous exactness in the employment of terms, will 
seem more than an equivalent for the graces of style and the 
golden flow of elocution, which Aristotle might have exhibited, 
if he had chosen to write like his contemporaries; and it will 
be maintained that it is easy to extract, even from his most 
methodical works, many passages of rare power and singular 
felicity. But we must admit that we belong to the number of 
those who are disposed to refuse to this great philosopher the 
humbler praise of having always written his best ; and we must 
express our regret that his literary fame is not supported by 
adequate remains of his more popular and attractive compo- 
sitions, 





1 Metaph. A, περὶ τῶν ποσαχῶς λεγομένων. The terms or notions examined 
are: 1. ἀρχή, ‘principle;’ 2. alriov, ‘cause;’ 3. στοιχεῖον, ‘element; 4. φύσις, 
‘nature ;’ 5. ἀναγκαῖον, ‘necessary;’ 6. τὸ ἕν, ‘unity; 7. τὸ ὄν, ‘entity; 8. 
οὐσία, ‘substance ; 9. ταὐτό, ‘identity;’ το. ἀντικείμενα, ‘contraries :᾿ 11. πρό- 
Tepa καὶ ὕστερα, ‘antecedents and consequents ; 12. δύναμις, ἀδύνατον, δυνατόν, 
‘ potentiality, impossibility, and possibility; 13. πόσον, ‘ quantity;’ 14. ποιόν, 
‘ quality ;’ 15. πρός τι, ‘relation; 16. τέλειον, ‘perfect : 17. πέρας, ‘limit;’ 18. 
καθ᾽ αὑτό, ‘self-existence ; 19—22. διάθεσις, ἕξις, πάθος, στέρησις, “ disposition, 
habit, affection, privation ;’ 23. ἔχειν, ‘state :;᾿ 24. ἔκ τινος εἶναι, ‘matter, cause,’ 
&c.; 25, 26. μέρος, ὅλον, ‘part and whole;’ 27, κολυβόν, ‘mutilated ;’ 28. γένος 
‘genus ;’ 29. ψεῦδος, ‘falsity ; 30. συμβεβηκός, ‘accident.’ 


311 


CHAPTER XLI. 


DEMOSTHENES, 


§ 1. Life of Demosthenes. ὃ 2. Harangues to the people, chiefly relating-to Philip 
of Macedon. ὃ 3. Orationson public causes. ὃ 4. Speeches against Alschines. 


§ 5. Speeches in the law courts on private causes. § 6. Style and characteris- 
tics of Demosthenes. 


§ ας ROM the two greatest philosophers of ancient Greece, 

we pass to the orator, whose eminence, as a master 
of eloquence, is quite equal to theirs as masters of human 
thought ; and it is not a little remarkable, that such men as 
Aristotle and Demosthenes should have been, in every sense of 
the term, contemporaries. It is certain that they died in the 
same year, and it is very probable that they were of the same 
age when they died. The caution, with which we entered on 
a brief sketch of the two great philosophers, must be repeated, 
in a corresponding form, at the beginning of the present 
chapter. As we then reminded the reader that we were 
writing the history of Greek literature, not that of Greek 
philosophy, so we must now beg him to remember, that we are 
not engaged with that political history of Greece, in which 
Demosthenes was one of the most prominent actors. The 
space which this orator occupies in the pages of Thirlwall and 
Grote, to say nothing of the fact that he furnishes the subject 
for at least one separate work’ of considerable extent, may 
well excuse us from any attempt to trace the events in which 
he bore a part, and to estimate fully his character as a states- 
man. It will be quite sufficient for our present purpose, if we 
give a short account of his personal biography, and of his 
speeches considered as literary compositions. 





1 For example, A. G. Becker's Demosthenes als Staatsmann und Redner, 
2 volumes, 8vo. Halle, 1815, 1816; the same writer's Demosthenes als Staats- 
biirger, Redner wnd Schriftsteller, Quedlinburg, 1830—1834; A. Schifer’s Demo- 
sthenes und seine Zeit, Leipsig, 1856, 1857. 


312 DEMOSTHENES. 


It is still a matter of controversy in what year DemostHENES 
was born.’ The earliest date is Ol. 98, 4. B.c. 385; the 
latest Ol. 99, 4. B.c. 380. . His father, who bore the same name, 
apparently not an uncommon one at Athens, was an opulent — 
citizen of the demos of Pzania, who carried on a thriving 
business as a cutler and cabinet-maker, and was also engaged 
in commercial transactions to a considerable extent. His 
mother was not of pure Athenian descent, though there is no 
reason to doubt that she was, on both sides, of Greek extraction. 
She was one of the two daughters and co-heiresses of Gylon, a 
banished Athenian, who had ingratiated himself with a Greek 
prince on the Cimmerian Bosporus, had received from his 
patron a town named Cepi in the island to the east of that 
inlet of the sea, and had there married a rich woman, probably 
the heiress of some Greek settler in that well colonized region.* 
The two daughters of Gylon were sent to Athens with large 
dowries, and married two Athenian citizens; the younger 
became the wife of Demochares, and the elder, Cleobule, was 
the mother of Demosthenes. 

The ample property of his father, increased by the handsome 
portion of his mother, seemed. to destine Demosthenes to a life 
of opulent obscurity. It happened, however, that he lost his 
father while only seven years old, and was left with a younger 
sister under the care of three guardians, Aphobus, the son of 





1 The earliest date, Ol. 98, 4. B.C. 385, is maintained by Dr. Thirlwall (Hist. of 
Gr. V. p. 248, Philological Museum, II. pp. 389 sqq.). Mr. Clinton (Fasté 
Hellenici, 11. Append. 20), C. K. Hermann (de anno natali Demosthenis, Gott. 
1846, reprinted in Dindorf’s Demosthenes, vol. VI. pp. 730 sqq.), and Mr. Grote 
(Hist. of Gr. XI. p. 369) adopt the year Ol. 99, 3. Β.0. 382, 381, and Bohnecke 
(Forschungen, pp. 1-94) agrees with Dionysius (ad Ammeuwm, 4) in dating the 
orator’s birth in the archonship of Demophilus, Ol. 99, 4. B.c. 380. We incline to 
Mr. Clinton’s date. ς 

2 Dr. Thirlwall (V. p. 247) calls him a merchant on the strength of I. Aphob, p. 
816. The nature of his property may be seen in the calculations reprinted from an 
English translation of -Voemel in Dindorf’s Demosthenes, VII. pp. 1053 sqq. 
Juvenal’s intimation (X. 127132) that the orator’s father was a working black- 
smith is an exaggeration or a mistake. 

3 Plut. Demosth. 4, isch. adv. Ctesiph. p. 78, Dem. TE. Aph. p. 835. Cepi 
(Κῆποι, ‘the gardens’) was a Milesian settlement and a considerable town (Plin. 
H. N. VI. 6). It lay in the modern island of Taman, in the sea of Corocondame 
(Strabo, p. 495) over against Kertch and Jenicale. 


HIS LIFE. 313 


his father’s sister, who was to marry Cleobule with a dowry of 
14 talent, Demophon, the son of his father’s brother, who was 
to marry the daughter when she came of age, and to receive 
at once her portion of two talents, and an old friend, Therip- 
pides, who was to enjoy the interest of τὸ talent till Demo- 
sthenes came of age.’ These guardians seem to have behaved 
as Greek guardians too often did.* They neglected the con- 
ditions of the will, and squandered the property confided to 
their charge to such an extent that out of fourteen talents, 
which the father left at his death, they paid less than two 
talents to the son on his completing the age of 18, when he 
was legally entitled to undertake the management of his own 
property After vainly attempting to obtain an amicable 
settlement of the accounts, he brought an action against 
Aphobus, and obtained damages to the amount of ten talents,’ 
part of which he must have received, as he appears to have 
performed some of the most expensive liturgies or public 
duties.» But there can be little doubt that the injustice to 
which he was exposed at first starting in life, and the fear of 
losing all, or nearly all, his patrimony, stimulated him to 





1 Dem. I. Aph. pp: 814, 816, 11. 840. 
2 It was almost a fixed phrase in classical Greek to say of the orphan that he 
was ‘torn in pieces’ by his guardians; see Soph. Ajax, 505 sqq.: 
οἴκτειρε δ᾽, ὦ vat, παῖδα τὸν σὸν, εἰ νέας 
τροφῆς στερηθείς, σοῦ διοίσεται μόνος 
ὑπ᾽ ὀρφανιστῶν μὴ φίλων. 


Cf. Herod. IIT. 53: τὸν οἶκον τοῦ πατρὸς διαφορηθέντα. Dem. I. Steph. 1120. 
25: ὑπὸ τούτου καὶ τῶν τοιούτων διαφορηθείς. Dio Chrys, XLIII. 506, C: ὑπὸ 
τῶν ξυγγενῶν καὶ τῶν ἐπιτρόπων διασπασθῆναι. 

3 Dem. I. Aph. pp. 812, 832, 815. Onetor, p. 865. 

4 See Westermann, Prolegomena ad Orationes Tutorias, reprinted in Dindorf’s 
Demosthenes, pp. 1045 sqq. 

5 Aischines insinuates (adv. Ctesiph. 78) that by the expensiveness of these 
liturgies, coupled with his own profligate extravagance, he reduced himself to the 
necessity of writing speeches for hire: περὶ δὲ τὴν καθ᾽ ἡμέραν δίαιταν τίς ἐστιν ; ἐκ 
τριηράρχου λογογράφος ἀνεφάνη, τὰ πατρῷα καταγελάστως προέμενος. We are 
surprised by Mr. Grote’s remark (XT. p. 372) that he does not ‘ clearly understand 
what is meant’ by these last words. Is the difficulty in the adverb κατα- 
γελάστως, which means ‘in a profligate manner’ (Alsch. 6. Timarch. p..5, 13), oF 
in the verb προίεσθαι, which is regularly used in the sense ‘to part with one’s 
money’ (¢.g. pro Phorm. p. 946, το, 6. Dionysod. p. 1297, 14)? 


314 DEMOSTHENES. 


commence those laborious studies which ultimately made him 
the greatest orator of ancient or modern times,. 

It does not appear that, while the guardians of Demosthenes 
were wasting or embezzling his property, they neglected to give 
him an education suitable to his supposed circumstances. He 
charges his guardians with not paying his teachers; but in 
contrasting his early advantages with those of his rival Aischines, 
he boasts that while the latter was a teacher in a low school, 
he was himself a regular attendant at some place of elementary 
instruction.? The tradition, that he received instruction from 
Plato and Isocrates,> may have arisen from a not unnatural 
wish to connect the greatest orator with the principal literary 
men of the age immediately preceding his own. There is 
probably more foundation for the statement that he was taught 
rhetoric by Iszeus, and was assisted by that orator in the com- 
position of his speeches against his guardians.‘ His first 
beginnings in a study of rhetoric, and his ambition to become 
a public speaker, are generally attributed to the fact that he 
was taken by his tutors, while still a boy, to hear the cele- 
brated Callistratus, the well-known friend of Iphicrates, defend 
himself and Chabrias on the charge of surrendering Oropus to 
the Thebans. This is supposed to have been in the year B.c. 
366, when Demosthenes was certainly not more than eight or 
nine years old.*> Whatever may have been the extent of literary 
cultivation which he received in his youth, it appears that 
Demosthenes did not enjoy the gymnastic training which 
formed an equally essential part of the early discipline of young 


Athenians. It is supposed that his delicate constitution, and — 


his mother’s anxiety for the health of her only son, preyented 
him from joining in the exercises of the palestra.£ This 





11, Aph. p. 828, 6. ; 

2 De Corond, p. 312, 22: ἐμοὶ μὲν τοίνυν ὑπῆρξεν, παιδὶ μὲν ὄντι φοιτᾶν εἰς τὰ 
προσήκοντα διδασκαλεῖα καὶ ἔχειν ὅσα χρὴ τὸν μηδὲν αἰσχρὸν ποιήσοντα δι᾽ ἔνδειαν. 
Ibid. p. 315. 8: ἐδίδασκες γράμματα, ἐγὼ δ᾽ ἐφοίτων. 

3 Plut. Dem. 5, Vit. X. Orat. 837, 844, Cic. Brut. 31, &e. 

4 Plut. Vit. X. Orat. 839, 844. Liban. Vit. Dem. p. 3. Argum. ad Orat, 6. 
Onet. p. 875. 

5 Plut. Dem. 5. Vite decem Oratorum, p. 844. Hermippus apud Aul, Gell. 
III. τὰς 

§ Thirlwall, V. p. 248. 


. 


HIS LIFE. 315 


deficiency, coupled with his lisping articulation,’ want of mus- 
cular vigour, and effeminate attire, obtained for him the name 
of Βατάλος, ‘the infantine babbler,’? a name which had also 
another meaning in the nursery,’ and was used to countenance 
an imputation of the vilest impudicity.*. Without any double 
signification, the powerful coterie, which espoused the cause of 
his guardians, contrived to fix upon him the name of ᾿Αργάς, 
‘the viper,’® as though he had turned round and bitten the 
nurturers of his youth. 

The success which attended the prosecution of Aphobus, by 
no means guaranteed his eminence as a public speaker. The 
orations are still extant, and exhibit so much talent that they 
have been attributed to Iszeus himself, who probably assisted in 
their composition, just as Demosthenes wrote many of his 
speeches to be delivered in court by the parties themselves. It 
does not appear that any great merits of elocution were expected 
in these forensic harangues. Indeed, in many cases, they may 
have been read to the dicasts or jurymen. At any rate, 
Demosthenes had no natural advantages as an orator. A feeble 
frame and a weak voice, a shy and awkward manner, the 
ungraceful gesticulations of one whose limbs had never been 
duly exercised in the palestra, and the defective articulation to 
which we have already referred, would have deterred most men 
from even attempting to address an Athenian assembly. He 
had the additional discouragement of failing on his first 
attempt. Worst of all, he was not fluent as an extempore 
speaker, and even in his best days, he required preparation, 
and was liable to break down if he spoke under novel circum- 





1 He could not pronounce the letter p till he had conquered his natural thickness 
of speech by long practice ; Cic. Div. II. 46, § 96. 

2 See Dissen and Schaefer, ad Orat. de Corond, p. 288,17. Naeke, de Battaro 
Catonis, Rhein. Mus. for 1828, pp. 113 sqq. 

3 Harpocration, s.v.; Εὔπολις δὲ τὸν πρωκτὸν βάταλον λέγει" μή ποτε οὖν ἔνθεν 
τοὺς κιναίδους βατάλους λέγουσι. Cf. Aisch. c. Tim. p. 17. 42: ταύτην ἐξ ὑποκο- 
ρίσματος τίτθης τὴν ἐπωνυμίαν ἔχω. 

4 Aisch, Fals. Leg. p. 41, 13: ἐν παισὶ μὲν ὧν ἐκλήθη δι’ αἰσχρουργίαν τινα καὶ 
κιναιδίαν Βάταλος. 

5 Aischines, ibid.: ἐκ παίδων δ᾽ ἀπαλλαττόμενος καὶ δεκαταλάντους δίκας ἑκάστῳ 
τῶν ἐπιτρόπων λαγχάνων A pyas ἐκλήθη. 

§ Plutarch, Dem. 6: τὸ πρῶτον ἐντυγχάνων τῷ δήμῳ θορύβοις περιέπιπτε καὶ 
κατεγελᾶτο δι᾽ ἀήθειαν τοῦ λόγου. 


316 DEMOSTHENES. 


stances, as when he first addressed Philip of Macedon in the 
presence of his court. But the ambition and resolute perse- 
verauce of Demosthenes enabled him to triumph over every 
disadvantage. He improved his bodily powers by running; 
his voice by speaking aloud as he walked up hill, or declaimed 
against the roar of the sea at Phalerum. He practised grace- 
ful delivery before a tall looking-glass, and controlled his unruly 
articulation by speaking with pebbles in his mouth.' His want 
of fluency he remedied by diligent composition, and by copying 
and committing to memory the works of the best authors. Of 
these his favourite was Thucydides, and it is said that he wrote 
out the eight books of that historian no less than eight times,’ 
and could almost recite him from memory. Moreover, he 
read carefully all the τέχναι, or treatises on oratory, that he 
could procure.’ And he prepared himself for the public exer- 
cise of his talents not only by writing declamations for practice 
on all the great subjects of the day, but also by composing 
speeches for the parties in private suits and public prosecutions. 
In this way he gradually surmounted all his difficulties. The 
friendly actor Satyrus was at hand to correct the faults of his 
delivery,‘ and old men in the assembly began to say that his 
speeches reminded them of the school of Pericles.’ And at 
last he came forth as the acknowledged leader of the assembly, 
and, even by the confession of his deadliest enemies, the first 
orator in Greece. 

The period, during which the name of Demosthenes identifies 
itself with the history of Athens, was eminently critical both 
for that city and for the whole of Greece. It was a time when 
an able and patriotic statesman, like Demosthenes, might have 
done greater service than any of his predecessors, if the people 
would have listened to his advice, and acted energetically in 
carrying out the counsels which he gave them. Unfortunately 
this was not the case. When Demosthenes delivered his first 





1 Plutarch, Dem. 4—9. 2 Lucian, adv. Indoctum, ο:. 4. 

3 Plut. Dem.c. 5. Vit. X. Orat. p. 844 B. 

4 Plut. Dem. c. 7. Satyrus made him recite a speech from Euripides or 
Sophocles, and then delivered it himself with all the graces of histrionic action. 

5 Eunomus the Thriasian is mentioned as one of those who told Demosthenes 
that he had τὸν λόγον ὁμοιότατον τῷ Περικλέους, Plut.. (Dem. ο. 6). 


HIS LIFE. 317 


political oration, that on the Symmorie, or companies for the 
payment of the property-tax, in the year 354 B.c.,’ Persia was 
still the only object of apprehension to united Greece, and 
Philip of Macedon was not regarded with the suspicions which 
he afterwards so fully justified. He had taken no part in the 
Social war, and had not interfered with the proceedings of 
Athens either in the Thracian Chersonesus orin Eubeea. Only 
three years after this the Phocian war broke out, and was 
closely followed by that between Philip and Olynthus; and 
while the latter led to misunderstandings between Philip and the 
Athenians, and compromised their interests in the north, the 
former ended in bringing Philip to Beotia, and enabled him, 
as the victor at Chzeronea, to dictate his own terms at Athens. 
While these events were in progress, the independence of 
Athens was staked on her policy in regard to the king of 
Macedon. And though a large and influential party were 
unwilling to oppose themselves actively and openly to the 
ambitious designs of Philip, others, who saw the danger, were 
anxious to encounter any risk rather than acquiesce in aggres- 
sions, which could have only one effect on the power of their 
country. ‘To this anti-Macedonian party, Demosthenes con- 
sistently belonged. Some of those who advocated the cause 
of peace at any price, such as Phocion, were well-meaning, but 
mistaken politicians; others, such as Philocrates and Auschines, 
were probably, or rather certainly, influenced by corrupt 
motives. Whatever doubt may be cast on the character of 
Demosthenes,’ there can be no question as to his general 
patriotism ; and his faults, whatever they were, must be regarded 
as cancelled hy his banishment and death, the consequences of 





1 See Grote, Hist, of Greece, XI. p. 398. 

2 See Thirlwall, Hist. of Greece, V. p. 255. The mere fact that Quintilian 
places Demosthenes and Cicero on the same footing in regard to the imputations 
on their character as men and citizens, shows that he did not accept these imputa- 
tions as a serious deduction from their merits. He says (XII. 1, $14): ‘ Orator 
ergo Demosthenes non fuit? Atqui malum virum accepimus. Non Cicero? atqui 
hujus quoque mores multi reprehenderunt. Quid agam? Magna responsi invidia 
subeunda est, mitigande sunt prius aures. Mihi hine nec Demosthenes tam 
gravi morum dignus videtur invidia, ut omnia, que in eum ab inimicis congesta 
sunt, credam, cum pulcherrima ejus in republica consilia, et finem vite clarum 
legam ; nec M. Tullio defuisse video in ulla parte civis optimi voluntatem.’ 


318 DEMOSTHENES. 


the opposition to the Macedonian power, which ‘had distin- 
guished him through life. 

The career of Demosthenes, so far as it contributes to explain 
his position in the history of Greek literature, may be described 
very briefly. His guardians seem to have belonged to a party 
of opulent and profligate men at Athens, who set the laws at 
defiance, and, trusting to their wealth and influence and mutual 
support, treated their poorer fellow-citizens as though they 
belonged to an inferior class. Among these persons, who were 
an active cause of the ruin of Athens, were Midias, Androtion, 
and Timocrates; and Demosthenes came into contact with the 
first of these on his own account, while he furnished a fellow- 
citizen, Diodorus, with the means of attacking the other two, 
who were partners in iniquity." About three or four days 
before the trial of Aphobus came on,’ Midias and his brother, 
Thrasylochus, had rushed into the house of Demosthenes, and 
making him an offer to exchange properties, or to undertake 
the trierarchy,* proceeded to deal with his effects as if they were 
already transferred to themselves; and even gave Aphobus a 
release from the action against him.’ Besides all this, they 
insulted in the grossest manner the female members of his 
family. Having relieved himself from this manceuvre by a 
payment of twenty mine for a deputy trierarch, Demosthenes 
brought an action for insulting language against Midias, and 
obtained judgment by default. Although entitled to execution, 
he abstained from touching the effects of the powerful culprit, 
and brought an action of ejectment,’ which he was prevented 
from trying by the evasions of the defendant. At last, the 
“rostility of Midias assumed the form of a public outrage. He 
assaulted Demosthenes in the almost sacred character of 
Choragus at the Dionysia; and in accordance with the rule in 





1 With the selfish inconsistency of Greek party-men, Midias, on one occasion, 
stood in opposition to Androtion ; Dem. ὃ. Androt. p. 596, 9. 

2 Dem. in Mid. p. 539, 26. 8 ἀντιδιδόντες τριηράρχίαν. 

4 τὰς δίκας ὡς αὐτῶν οὔσας ἠφίέσαν Τοῖς ἐπιτρόποις. 

5 In Mid. p. 540, 5. 

6 Ibid. 540, 21: δίκην δὲ Τούτων λαχὼν ὕστερον τῆς κακηγορίας εἷλον éphpiny* ob 
γὰρ ἀπήντα. 

71.23: λαβὼν δ᾽ ὑπερήμέρον καὶ ἔχων οὐδενὸς ἡψάμην πώποτε τῶν Τούτου ἀλλὰ 
λαχὼν ἐξούλης πάλιν οὐδέπω καὶ τήμερον εἰσελθεῖν δεδύνημαι. 


ΒΝ ΝΑ... κει. .«.......ἡ 


HIS LIFE. 319 


such cases, the matter was brought before the popular assembly,' 
and on a show of hands the offender was ordered to be prose- 
euted.2 The speech which Demosthenes composed for the 
occasion is extant, but was never delivered, as Midias com- 
pounded the charge by a payment of half a talent.* The 
charges against Androtion and Timocrates were also stimulated 
by their ill-usage of the accuser Diodorus, but the grounds 
alleged are entirely of a public nature. About the same time, 
Demosthenes appeared as the advocate of Ctesippus, the son of 
Chabrias, to prosecute Leptines, who had in 356 B.c. passed a 
statute for the abolition of hereditary exemptions from the 
public burdens, Chabrias having been one of those to whose 
family this privilege had been granted. And in 352 B.c., he 
composed a most elaborate speech for Euthycles, who indicted 
Aristocrates for moving a decree in favour of the adventurer, 
Charidemus, which contained a clause making his person in- 
violable. He also composed at this time a great many orations 
for suitors in private causes. His most important efforts, 
however, were the series of public speeches referring to the 
proceedings of Philip of Macedon, and known to the ancients 
as the twelve Philippics, a name which has become a general 
designation for spirited invectives.‘ These speeches extended 
over the period from 352 to 339 B.c. But he was not merely 
a statesman—that is, in the Athenian sense of the term, an 
influential speaker in the senate and in the public assembly. 
He was also an active diplomatist, and when not thwarted by the 





1 Dem. Mid. 514, 6: προὐβαλόμην αὐτὸν ἀδικεῖν. The προβολὴ or ‘ plaint to 
the assembly,’ as Mr. Kennedy renders it (Dem. against Leptines, Midias, &c., 
p- 365), ‘was an application to the people for leave to prefer a criminal charge ;’ 
_see Meier and Schémann, Alt. Proz. p. 271. 

2 70. p. 515, 2: μιᾷ γνώμῃ κατεχειροτόνησεν αὐτοῦ. 

3. Aischines says distinctly (c. Ctesiph. 61, 64), that Demosthenes ἀπέδοτο τριά- 
κοντα μνῶν ἅμα τήν τε els αὑτὸν ὕβριν καὶ τὴν τοῦ δήμου καταχειροτονίαν ἣν ἐν Διο- 
νύσου κατεχειροτόνησε Μειδίου. Plutarch, who recognizes the fact, attributes it to 
a belief, on the part of Demosthenes, that he could not cope with the influence of 
Midias (Vit. Dem. c. 12). Mr. Grote suggests that ‘he may have delivered tie 
discourse and obtained judgment in his favour ; and then afterwards—when the 
second vote of the dicasts was about to come on for estimation of the penalty— 
may have accepted the offer of the defendant to pay a moderate fine, in fear of 
exasperating too far the powerful friends around Midias’ (Hist. of Greece, XI. 
Ρ. 479). 4 See e.g. Juvenal, X. 129. 


320 DEMOSTHENES. 


misconduct of indolent or corrupt colleagues, he performed the 
most important services to his country in this capacity. He was 
one of the ten ambassadors who were sent to Philip at the end of 
347 B.c. His colleague, Aischines, whose words we are obliged 
to receive with the greatest caution, tells us' that on this 
occasion, when he appeared for the first time in the presence 
of the king of Macedon, whose designs he had so often de- 
nounced at home, his presence of mind entirely failed him ; and 
that, in spite of some good-natured encouragement from Philip,’ 
who was no doubt curious to hear the most renowned speaker 
of the anti-Macedonian party, he was unable to deliver more 
than a few confused and incoherent sentences. It is not 
impossible that this story rests on a foundation of facts, dis- 
torted, of course, by the malignity of a rival politician. Either, 
as Mr. Grote suggests,* Demosthenes was really intimidated by 
his new and formidable audience, or his common sense assured 
him that this was not an occasion on which fine speaking could 
produce any practical results, and so he contented himself with 
a very brief address. When it was agreed that peace should 
be made with Philip, Demosthenes was again one of the ten 
ambassadors sent to take the oaths from him.‘ The majority 
of his colleagues, probably bribed with Macedonian gold, de- 
layed their journey, so as to enable Philip to complete his 
Thracian conquests, and even to prepare for the immediate 
invasion of Phocis. The ruin of their unfortunate neighbours 
opened the eyes of the Athenians to the treacherous counsels 
by which they had been misled. Philocrates, the proposer of 
the peace, was impeached by Hypereides, and fled from Athens? 





1 Fals. Leg. p. 32. 

2 Tbid.1. 44: ἰδὼν δὲ ὁ Φίλιππος ws διέκειτο θαῤῥεῖν τε παρεκελεύετο Kal μὴ νομί- 
few, ὥσπερ ἐν τοῖς θεάτροις, διὰ τοῦτο οἴεσθαί τι πεπονθέναι, κ.τ.λ. 

3 XI. p. 530. He inclines to believe ‘that Demosthenes was partially divested 
of his oratorical powers, by finding himself speaking not only before the enemy 
whom he had so bitterly denounced, but surrounded by all the evidences of Mace- 
donian power, and doubtless exposed to unequivocal marks of well-earned hatred, 
from those Macedonians who took less pains than Philip to disguise their real 
feelings.’ 

4 See Thirlwall (Hist. of Greece, V. pp. 356 foll.), and Grote (XI. pp. 556 foll.), 
whose accounts of all these proceedings are accompanied by a criticism of the con- 
tradictory explanations, given by Demosthenes and Aischines. 

5 Demosth. Fals. Leg. p. 376; Hypereides, Pro Euxenippo, col. 39, 1: 7 [01]. 
d. Babington. . 


HIS LIFE. 321 


The accusation Alschines, which Demosthenes and Timarchus 
had undertaken, was delayed by the successful attack made by 
Aaschines on the latter,’ and by his procrastination in sub- 
mitting to the usual scrutiny.2, It came on, however, in B.c. 
343, and the two great speeches of the rival orators are still 
extant. Aischines, with the help of Eubulus and Phocion, was 
acquitted by a majority of 30 votes.’ This partial check did 
not interfere with the growing influence of Demosthenes. He 
was the life and soul of all the opposition which Athens raised 
to the restless intrigues and attempts of Philip. It was by his 
counsels that embassies, in which he took a part, were sent to 
the Peloponnesus, to the Ionian Isles, to Illyria, Thessaly, the 
Chersonese, and Byzantium.‘ He recommended the expe- 
dition to Eubcea, which detached that island from Macedon.’ 
And when the war was renewed between the Athenians and 
Philip, it was he who induced his countrymen to send a fleet to 
the relief of Byzantium, in B.c. 340, and thus to bring the 
Thracian campaign to a successful issue.® His greatest 
triumph was the alliance which he brought about between 
Athens and Thebes,’ when the insane proceedings of Aischines* 
had stirred up a second sacred war, and introduced Philip into 
Beotia. Although the unfortunate issue of the battle of 
Cheeroneia in B.c. 338 overthrew the independence of Athens, 
the active patriotism of Demosthenes had saved his country 
from a greater disaster,’ and he maintained his position in spite 
of that event. The death of Philip, in B.c. 336, opened an 
avenue for successful exertion, but the Athenians, under the evil 
influence of Phocion, took no advantage of it. The destruction of 





1 See Thirlwall, VI. pp. 28 foll. The success of Auschines was due to the 
notorious profligacy of Timarchus, which enabled him to dispense with witnesses. 
On this account Demosthenes says, with express reference to the prosecution of 
Timarchus, the only public indictment which had, up to that time, been brought 
forward by Aischines: ὃς yap ἀγῶνας καινοὺς ὥσπερ δράματα καὶ τούτους ἀμάρ- 
Tupas πρὸς διαμεμετρημένην τὴν ἡμέραν αἱρεῖς διώκων δῆλον ὅτι πάνδεινος εἶ τις (De 
Fals. Leg. p. 578). 


2 Thirlwall, VI. p. 26. 3 Below, 8 4, p. 336 [176]. 
4 Grote, XI. pp. 626 sqq. 5 De Corond, p. 252. 
6. Ibid. pp. 254, 304-308. 7 Ibid. pp. 286, 7. 


8 Asch. ¢. Ctes. pp. 69 foll. 
9. 4.6. an invasion of Attica from Elatea in B.c. 339; see Thirlwall, VI. p. 62, 
Grote, XI. p. 671. 
Vou. IL Y 


522 DEMOSTHENES. 


Thebes was followed by Alexander’s demand for the extradition 
of Demosthenes and the other anti-Macedonian leaders.’ 
Although Phocion recommended compliance, the Athenians 
magnanimously rejected the demand, and Alexander was induced 
to modify it. Demosthenes, though no longer a leader, still 
retained considerable influence at Athens, which was shown by 
the results of his second great contest with Aischines, in B.c. 
330. . This arose from the proposal made by Ctesiphon, in B.c. 
338, not long after the battle of Chzeroneia, that Demosthenes 
should be rewarded with a golden crown and an eulogistic 
proclamation at the great Dionysia, specially for his exertions 
and expenditure in repairing the city walls, and generally for 
his patriotic and able. conduct as a statesman.* This proposal 
was indicted by Aischines, as the representative of the Mace- 
donian party, nominally on various technical grounds, but 
really as an impeachment of the political life of Demosthenes. 
The circumstances of the intervening years had prevented the 
Macedonizers from bringing on the case; but when the death 
of Agis, in 330 B.c., had made their cause stronger than ever,‘ 
they thought that a favourable opportunity had arrived. for 
effecting the ruin or discredit of their chief opponent. The 
speech by which Aischines supported his prosecution, and the 
triumphant answer of Demosthenes, are still extant, and are 
perhaps the best specimens of Greek oratory which we have. 
The latter is by universal consent an unequalled effort of 
human eloquence. Aischines did not. obtain the fifth part of 
the votes, and in bitter mortification withdrew from Athens.’ 
But this was the last happiness of Demosthenes, so far as we 
know his history. For the next five or six years we read 
nothing of his proceedings. But in the year 324 B.c., Har- 
palus, the satrap of Babylonia, sought an asylum in Attica 





1 The persons demanded were, Demosthenes, Lycurgus, Hypereides, Polyeuctus, 
Chares, Charidemus, Ephialtes, Diotimus, and Mcerocles (Arrian, Anabd. I. το, 
§ 6. Plut. Dem. c. 23, mentions Demon instead of Diotimus,. and Callisthenes 
instead of Hypereides). 

* He was satisfied with demanding the surrender of Charidemus and Ephialtes, 
who fled from Athens and took service with the Persians. 

3 In the terms of the proposed decree. 

4 Thirlwall, VI. p. 257. 

5 See the remarks of Grote on the causes of the exile of A’schines (XII. p. 395). 


HIS LIFE. 323 


with a considerable treasure, of which the Athenians took 
possession in trust for Alexander. On counting over the 
money, it was found to be much less than Harpalus said that 
he had brought with him, and Demosthenes was charged by 
Hypereides with having embezzled, or received as bribes, some 
portion of the deficit. Although it seems to us in the highest 
degree improbable that there should be any solid foundation 
for such a charge, fear of the Macedonians, or some other 
political motives, induced the Athenians to find Demosthenes 
guilty.’ He was thrown into prison, but allowed to escape to 
Aigina and Troezen, where he resided, gazing with tearful 
eyes on the coast of Attica,? till the death of Alexander, 
and the renewed opposition to Macedon, which led to the 
Lamian war, restored him in triumph to his native land. In 
the vigorous measures, which had nearly led to the ruin of 
Antipater, Demosthenes was the prime mover. But these 
bright prospects were soon clouded by the death of the 
Athenian general Leosthenes, by the loss of the battle of 
Crannon, and by the subsequent disunion of the allied Greeks. 
And when Antipater marched into Beotia, in B.c. 322, Athens 
was prostrate at his feet. Besides demanding the overthrow of 
the democratical constitution, he insisted that the anti- 
Macedonian orators should be given up to him. They fled 
from Athens, and Demades in their absence induced the gooo 
citizens, to whom Antipater had left the right of voting, to 
condemn them to death. This sentence was passed against 
Demosthenes, Hypereides, Aristonicus, and Himereus, the 
brother of Demetrius of Phalerum. One of the officers of 
Antipater, Archias, an Italian mercenary of Thurii, ‘ the exile- 
hunter ’ as he was called,* tore the last three of them from the 
sanctuary of Aiacus,in Aigina, and sent them to Antipater, who 





1 Grote has given good reasons for his conclusion, that ‘the verdict against him 
was not judicial but political, growing out of the embarrassing necessities of the 
time’ (XII. p. 113). Thirlwall comes to the similar result, that ‘ Demosthenes 
fell a victim to political intrigues, which derived their chief strength from the 
critical position in which Athens was placed by her resistance to Alexander’s 
decree for the restoration of the exiles’ (VII. 16r). 

2 Plut. Dem. 27: ἤνεγκε δὲ τὴν φυγὴν μαλακῶς ἐν Αὐγίνῃ καὶ Τροιζῆνι καθεζό- 
μενος τὰ πολλὰ καὶ πρὸς τὴν ᾿Αττικὴν ἀποβλέπων δεδακρυμένος. 

3 Plut. Dem. 28: ᾿Αρχίας ὁ κληθεὶς Φυγαδοθήρας, ὁ. 6., ‘the blood-hound.’ It 

Y 2 


824 DEMOSTHENES. ‘ 


put them all to death. With a band of Thracian soldiers, 
Archias tracked Demosthenes to his place of refuge, the temple 
of Poseidon, in the isle of Calauria, near Troezen, where he had 
spent part of his year of exile. Archias, who had been an actor, 
and a student of rhetoric, tried to induce Demosthenes to quit 
the sanctuary by some promises of mediation couched in high- 
flown and theatrical language.’ Demosthenes obliged him to 
throw off the mask by an irritating reference to his former 
employment as a stage-player, and the agent of Antipater 
broke out into undisguised and angry menaces. ‘ Now,’ said 
Demosthenes, ‘ you speak the true words of the Macedonian 
oracle—before you were but acting.’ He then asked Archias 
to wait till he had written home, and withdrawing to the inner 
part of the temple, took a dose of poison which he carried 
about his person. Having waited till the effects began to be 
felt, he rose up and staggered to the door of the temple, where 
he fell dead. His last words were : ‘ You may at once, Ὁ Archias, 
enact the part of Creon, and cast out this body unburied. O 
dear Poseidon, I quit thy temple still alive, but Antipater and 
the Macedonians have not allowed even thy sanctuary to be 
uncontaminated.’? 

Such was the miserable end of this great orator. It was 
not very long before the Athenians returned to their appre- 
ciation of the man who had served them so well for more than 





appears that he had been a pupil of the celebrated actor Polus, and of the rheto- 
ricians Lacritus and Anaximenes. It is worth noticing that Lacritus, who had been 
a pupil of Isocrates, is severely handled in one of the private orations of Demo- 
sthenes, below, § 5. 

1 We cannot agree with Mr. Grote (XIT. p. 441) in his rejection of Plutarch’s 
account of the death of Demosthenes. It appears to us not only very vivid and 
natural in itself, but also not improbable, for Archias would be likely to recollect 
and recount incidents in which he imagined that he had played a creditable part : 
such a statement as’Apxlov πολλὰ φιλάνθρωπα διαλεχθέντος (Plut. Dem. 29) could 
hardly have proceeded from any other informant, and if we compare the moderate 
language in which Demosthenes alludes to the histrionic antecedents of this tool of 
tyranny with the taunts which he flings out against Alschines, we may almost sup- 
pose that Archias softened down some unpleasant things that were said to him. 
The reference to Creon is quite in the spirit of Demosthenes: see De Corond, 
p- 288, 1. 19; and Archias was literally the representative of a tyrant. 

2 Plut. Dem. 29: οὐκ ἂν φθάνοις ἤδη τὸν ἐκ τῆς τραγῳδίας ὑποκρινόμενος Kpéovra 
καὶ τὸ σῶμα τοῦτο ῥίπτων ἄταφον. ἐγὼ δ᾽, ὦ φίλε Πόσειδον, ἔτι ζῶν ἐξανίσταμαι τοῦ 
ἱεροῦ" τῳ δὲ᾽ Ἀντιπάτρῳ καὶ Μακέδοσιν οὐδ᾽ ὁ σὸς ναὸς καθαρὸς ἀπολέλειπται. 


HIS SPEECHES. 325 


thirty years. His nephew, Demochares, lived to propose and 
carry a decree,’ by which his eldest descendant for the time 
being had reserved to him a seat at the public table in the 
Prytaneum ; and a statue of bronze was erected in his honour 
both in the agora at Athens and in the temple at Calauria, where 
he died.?,_ The former bore the plain-spoken inscription :— 


Had but thy power, Demosthenes, mated thy prudent mind, 
No chains of warlike Macedon would free-born Hellas bind! 


His countrymen were pleased to see that a just retribution 
punished the immediate authors of his death, Archias died in 
poverty, and universally detested. And one of the last acts of 
Antipater was to order the execution of the corrupt and 
treacherous Demades.’ To these feelings on the part of the 
Athenians, when they looked back, a few years afterwards, on 
the completed career of Demosthenes, we lend a ready sym- 
pathy. It is our present business to regard this great man in 
his literary rather than his political capacity, but we cannot 
refrain from recording our concurrence in the sentiment so 
strongly expressed by Niebuhr, that Demosthenes was politically 
a saint, that we do not envy the man who judges him diffe- 
rently, and that his whole political life, and all that concerns 
his honour as a statesman, are without spot or change.° 

§ 2. The sixty-one speeches which have come down to us 
under the name of Demosthenes, probably include all that he 
left in writing.’ And the collection contains besides many 
that he did not compose or deliver. They are generally 
divided into three classes—the harangues to the people 
(Snunyopiat), the orations on public causes (δημόσιοι λόγοι), 





1 Vit. X.-Orat. p. 847 D. 2 Pausanias, IT. 33, § 5. 
3 εἴπερ ἴσην ῥώμην γνώμῃ, Δημόσθενες, εἶχες, 
οὔποτ᾽ ἂν Ἑλλήνων ἦρξεν "Ἄρης Μακέδων. 
Plut. Dem. 30; who speaks of it as τὸ ἐπίγραμμα τὸ θρυλλούμενον. 
4 Arrian, ap. Phot. cod. XCII. p. 218: ’Apxlas ὁ Θούριος ἐν ἐσχάτῃ πενίᾳ καὶ 
ἀτιμίᾳ διατρίψας ἐτελεύτησε τὸν βίον. 
® Diod. XVIII. 48, Arrian, ἃ. 5. Athen. XIII. κοι. Τὸ was Cassander who 
executed judgment on Demades according to Plutarch, Dem. 31, Phoc. 30. 
§ Philological Museum, I. pp. 487, 497. 
7 See Clinton, 27, H. ΤΙ. p. 355. Photius (cod. CCLXV.) says: φέρονται λόγοι 
γνήσιοι ἑξήκοντα πέντε, but, as Mr. Clinton remarks, it is not explained what this 
list of sixty-five contained, and it might include some spurious pieces. 


326 DEMOSTHENES. 


and the speeches upon private causes (ἰδιωτικοὶ λόγοι). We 
shall consider them according to this division, but we shall 
place by themselves the two great speeches which he made 
against Aischines, both because the corresponding orations of 
the rival orator are still extant, and also because these com- 
positions have a distinct historical and oratorical value. 

We have fifteen parliamentary speeches or harangues addressed 
to the popular assembly, and this is the number recognized 
by Dionysius.? Of these, twelve relate more or less directly to 
the proceedings of Philip, and, as we have already mentioned, 
are called the Philippics. This title, however, is generally 
restricted to five of them, the first and fifth being contained in 
one. Three others are called the Olynthiacs, and the 
remaining four have special designations—‘On the Peace, 
‘The Halonnesus,’ and ‘The Chersonesus.? The three other 
public speeches are these—‘ On the Symmorie,’ ‘ For the People 
of Megalopolis, and ‘ For the Rhodians.’ 

It has been already stated that the first in point of time of 
this collection of parliamentary addresses was the speech 
respecting the Symmorie, in B.c. 354. The object of this 
speech was to show that, although there was no immediate 
occasion for a special confederacy of the Greeks to resist the 
king of Persia, it was still necessary that Athens should be 
well prepared for any eventuality. With this view he brings 
forward an elaborate and well-conceived scheme for the classi- 
fication of the 1200 wealthiest citizens in the twenty companies 
(συμμορίαι), two for each tribe, which were required, each in 
its turn, to advance the special war contribution or property-tax. 
(εἰσφορά)." 

The next in order was the speech for the people of Megalo- 
polis, delivered in B.c. 353. In this oration, as in the preceding, 
Macedon and Philip do not enter into the speaker’s thoughts. 
The principle which he lays down is, that it is expedient for 
Athens that both Sparta and Thebes should be as weak as 
possible. And, as Thebes at this time was sufficiently enfeebled 





1 They are arranged according to their dates, and in these classes, by Mr. 
Clinton, 11. Ρ. 86ο. 
39 Ad Ammeum, p. 744, Reiske. 3 See Grote, XI. pp. 398 foll. 


THE PHILIPPICS. 327 


by her contest with the Phocians, the orator recommends his 
countrymen to accept the alliance of Megalopolis, and so to 
check the designs of Sparta in the south.’ 

The first Philippic was spoken in B.c. 352. Here we have 
Demosthenes in the character which he sustained to the last— 
the sagacious discoverer of the dangerous designs of Philip, the 
energetic statesman who roused his indolent countrymen to a true 
sense of their perils and their duty. “He boldly throws the blame 
on the people no less than their advisers ; and calling upon the 
Athenians to serve in person instead of leaving the military 
functions of the free citizen to be performed by mercenaries, 
he proposes to equip an adequate standing force, and to provide 
the means for paying the soldiers and sailors by a financial 
scheme which has not come down to us.’ 

In B.c. 351, he delivered his speech about the freedom of 
the Rhodians, urging the Athenians to support the democratical 
party in that island, and obviating the fear that either the 
queen of Caria, or the Persian king, would espouse the cause of 
the ruling oligarchy. The former, he shows, would. probably 
abstain from all interference, and the king of Persia was 
not by any means so formidable an opponent as Philip of 
Macedon, whom some affected to hold cheap.’ 

The three Olynthiac speeches were delivered in the year 8.0. 
349. The chronological order of these vigorous harangues has 
been made the subject of learned discussions by able scholars.‘ 
On the whole, there seems to be good ground for acquiescing 
in the conclusion of Stiive and Mr. Grote, that the third 
Olynthiae should retain its old place, and that the order of the 
first and second should be reversed. According to this view, 
the earliest of these speeches considers the affairs of Olynthus 
as only one element in the general opposition to the designs of 
Philip, and dwells rather on the advantage of an alliance with 
that important city than on the risk to which it was exposed, 





1 See Grote, XI. pp. 406 foll. 3.74. pp. 431 foll. 3 Thirlwall, V. p. 304. 
4 See Mr. Grote’s Appendix to his 88th chapter (vol. XI. pp. 499—504). The 
three arrangements are :— 
Hdited/order 22.55 Soke so πον, TB, TO: 
- Order of Dionysius. . . . IL. Ill. 1. 
StueveandGrote . . . . Il. I. ΤΠ. 


328 DEMOSTHENES. 


and the consequences which the success of Philip in that 
quarter would probably entail.’ In the next Olynthiac speech 
—that which is first in the ordinary arrangement—Demosthenes 
enlarges upon these special considerations. Olynthus is in 
danger, and if Philip conquers it, he will soon be able, instead 
of fighting the Athenians in the north, to transfer the war to 
their own soil. And under the emergency, as he presents it to 
them, he recommends an adequate armament, both military and 
naval, which must be provided for, if necessary, by even an 
appropriation of the public-spectacle money —the theoricon, as 
it was called? The Athenians partially acted on this advice, 
and their troops gained some trifling success which led them to 
indulge in overweening exultation. To repress this feeling and to 
point out the real state of the case, Demosthenes delivered the 
third Olynthiac oration. And he is so far from encouraging 
them in the belief that they had the game in their hands, that 
he insists upon the necessity of increased exertions, and goes so 
far as to suggest the immediate appointment of a board for a 
revision of the laws with a view to the application of the 
theoricon to the purposes of the war. This third Olynthiac is 
one of the noblest of all the speeches of Demosthenes. 

The speech on the Peace, which was delivered in B.c. 346, 
after the ruin of Phocis, and the promotion of Philip to the 
Amphictyonic dignity, contains ‘a calm and statesmanlike view 
of the question, whether Philip’s newly usurped honours 
should be recognized. Disapproving of the peace, he did not 
think that either the time or the cause warranted an appeal to 
arms. It would be foolish, he said, and absolutely monstrous, 
when they had so demeaned themselves with the separate states 
in regard to their dearest interests for the sake of peace, to 
go to war with them all collectively for the sake of a seat in 
the shady nook at Delphi.’ 

In B.c. 344, the second Philippic was spoken. Philip had 
sent ambassadors to Athens, probably the mission in which the 





1 Grote, XI. p. 457. 2 Olynth. I. p. 15. 
3 Grote, XI. p. 468. 4 Olynth. ITI. pp. 31, 32. 
5 De Pace, p. 63, 1. 23: οὐκοῦν εὔηθες καὶ κομιδῇ σχέτλιον πρὸς ἑκάστους καθ᾽ ἕνα 
οὕτω προσενηνεγμένους περὶ τῶν ἀναγκαίων καὶ ἀναγκαιοτάτων, πρὸς πάντας περὶ τῆς 
ἐν Δελφοῖς σκιᾶς νυνὶ πολεμῆσαι. 


> 


4 


THE PHILIPPICS. 329 


Byzantine orator Python took a prominent part, and, as Dr. 
Thirlwall suggests,’ it ‘seems to have been the speech with 
which Demosthenes prefaced a motion for the answer which he 
proposed to give to the ambassadors.’ It is directed in great 
measure against the Philippizing Orators,? and it warns the 
Athenians to be on their guard against the Macedonian king, 
and to form alliances against him. 

The oration ‘about the Halonnesus,’ which was delivered in 
B.C. 343, is wrongly attributed to Demosthenes. There is good 
reason for believing that its author was Hegesippus, an orator 
of the anti-Macedonian party.2 Demosthenes spoke on the 
occasion, but his harangue is lost.‘ 

The oration on the Affairs of the Chersonesus’ and the third 
Philippic were both delivered in B.c. 342, when the peace 
between Philip and the Athenians was growing more and more 
nominal, and the rupture becoming gradually more inevitable. In 
the former, which is a masterpiece of eloquence, the orator depre- 
cates the recal of Diopeithes,’ au active leader of mercenaries, 
who had engaged in unauthorized hostilities with Philip, and had 
levied contributions from his subjects in Thrace, and even appre- 
hended an envoy sent to treat with him.’ In both orations he 
deals immediately with the affairs of the Chersonesus, and it 
has been supposed® that the third Philippic had reference to a 
request for protection from the subjects of Athens in that 
quarter. The Philippic boldly states that the nominal peace 
had been really a state of war, as far as Philip’s actions were 





1 Thirlwall, VI. p. το. 

3 There is a special allusion to Philocrates in p. 73, 1. 2, for it was this corrupt 
orator who reviled Demosthenes as a teetotalist ; see Pals. Leg. p. 355. 1. 25. 

3 See Alsch. ο, Ctes. 65, and the arguments of Winiewski and Vémel, cited, the 
former at length and the latter briefly, in Dindorf’s Annotationes (Oxford, 1849, 
vol. I. pp. 139—142). 

4 Libanius, Argum.: ὁ μὲν τοῦ Δημοσθένους λόγος 6 περὶ τῆς ᾿Αλοννήσου ῥηθεὶς οὐ 
σώζεται, ἐκείνου δὲ οὐκ ὄντος τὸν εὑρεθέντα προσέθεσαν αὐτῷ. 

ὅ There is a spirited translation of this speech in Lord Brougham’s Works, vol. 
VII. pp. 73 foll. 

_ § Diopeithes has another contact with Greek literature as the father of the poet 
Menander. 

7 Epist. Philippi, p. 159, 1. 13. 

8 By Winiewski (ad Orat. de Corond, p. 176), on the strength of the expression 
τἄλλα ὅσα ἀξιοῦσι, Phil. 111. p. 129, 1. 28. 


330 DEMOSTHENES. 


concerned, and both speeches insist on the necessity of sending 
embassies and organizing a confederacy to check the king’s 
increasing ambition. 

The fourth Philippic is generally regarded’ as a spurious 
composition, made up of passages taken from the genuine 
orations of Demosthenes... Scholars have come to a similar 
conclusion respecting the speech on the Letter of Philip, and 
the Funeral Oration. That on the Arrangement of the Republic 
(wept συντάξεως) has been pronounced by F. A. Wolf to be a 
patchwork made up in great measure of extracts from the third 
Olynthiac, and the speech against Aristocrates? 

§ 3. A general reference has been already made to the 
speeches against Androtion and Leptines, delivered in B.c. 355, 
against Timocrates in B.c. 353, against Aristocrates in B.C. 352, 
and that prepared for delivery against Midias in B.c. 348. 
They are distinguished by the same characteristics—great 
knowledge of the laws and history of Athens, acute reasoning, 
and powerful declamation. That against Leptines was a 
special favourite with the ancient critics. Dionysius says that 
of all the speeches of Demosthenes, this oration on the immu- 
nities has the greatest polish and literary finish ;* and the 
eminent rhetorician, Aristides, has left us a formal imitation 
of it. Cicero specially praises it for its subtlety,‘ and the great 
modern scholar, F. A. Wolf, assigns it the next place in point 
of excellence to the noble speech on the Crown.’ ‘The accuracy 
of the language is very remarkable, and we have some examples 
of refinements and distinctions, which evince the most laborious 
and careful preparation.° 





1 See Dindorf, Annot. I. p. 202. 

2 Wolf, Proleg. ad Leptineam, p. 74: ‘si quid video, oratio que inscribitur περὶ 
συντάξεως seu de Republic& ordinandé, Demosthenis non est, sed ex aliis ejus, 
maxime Olynth. III. et Aristocratea, ab aliquo declamatore consutis pannis 
confecta.’ 

3 Ad Ammeuwm, p. 724: ὁ περὶ τῶν ἀτελειῶν λόγος χαριέστατος ἁπάντων τῶν 
λόγων καὶ γραφικώτατος. 

4 Orator. 31: ‘multe sunt Demosthenis orationes tote subtiles, ut contra 
Leptinem: multe tote graves ut quedam Philippice: multe varie, ut contra 
Aéschinem false legationis, ut contra eundem pro causs& Ctesiphontis.’ 

> Prolegomena in Lept. p. 42. 

6 As in the refined distinction between ἀφαιρεῖν and ἀφαιρεῖσθαι, p. 462, 1, 3. 


SPEECHES AGAINST ANDROTION AND TIMOCRATES. 331 


The orations against Androtion, Timocrates, and Aristo- 
crates, are marked by a similarity of subject and a resemblance 
of style, which sometimes amounts to a repetition of the same 
arguments and even the same expressions. This parsimony, 
or at least economy of diction, is particularly observable in 
the two former speeches, which are written for the same 
accuser, and virtually directed against the same offending party. 
It is interesting to examine the relations between Demosthenes 
and the persons who figure in these two orations. Androtion, 
the son of Andron, was an orator of no mean eminence. He 
had been a pupil of Isocrates,’ and has received commenda- 
tion from Aristotle, who preserves a fragment from one of 
his speeches.” At the time when this action was brought 
against him, he had been a leading politician for more than 
thirty years, and had held many offices of great responsibility.’ 
But he seems to have been a selfish demagogue, and his 
private character was on a par with his political reputation. 
It has been supposed, and, as we shall see, not without 
reason, that he was the same person as the historian Androtion, 
who wrote the Aithis.* He is attacked in the cause, for which 
the speech of Demosthenes was written, by Euctemon and 
Diodorus, both of whom he had wronged in the most signal 
manner, on the ground that he had illegally proposed the usual 
honour of a crown to the council of the five hundred, although 
they had not performed their prescribed duty of building some 
additional triremes. This was in B.c. 355, and we do not 
know precisely the result of the action. In B.c. 353, the same 
Androtion is the cause of the attack made by Euctemon and 
Diodorus against Timocrates. He had been sent as ambas- 
sador to Caria, and on the way the trireme in which he sailed 
had captured a merchant ship of Naucratis, and brought her 
into the Peirzus. The ambassadors had sold and appropriated 
the captured goods, which really belonged to the state, and had 
been summoned to refund the proceeds. In order to screen 
them, Timocrates, a hireling orator, had proposed a law, which 





1 Dem. c. Androt. p. 594, 15. 

2 Rhet. 111. 4, § 3. He compared his adversary Idrieus to an unchained and 
savage dog. 

3. Dem. c. Timocr. pp. 734, 5. 4 Below, chapter XLIII. § 6. 


oan DEMOSTHENES. 


would have relieved Androtion from the usual penalties. And 
in arguing against this law, Demosthenes has to take a course 
the very opposite to that which was necessary in the attack on 
Leptines. It is curious to observe how the personal relations 
of these public men varied at different times in their career, 
fully justifying the saying of Bias, quoted by Sophocles, that 
the harbour of political partizanship was not a safe place of 
refuge, and that we must limit our animosity by the thought 
that our enemy may one day be our friend.’ In the speech 
against Midias, which was delivered in B.c. 348, we find that 
Euctemon had become one of the party of that insolent enemy 
of Demosthenes. ‘ Now,’ he says,’ ‘ Polyeuctus, Timocrates, 
Euctemon, that dirty fellow (ὁ κονιορτός), are the protectors of 
Midias. These and others too are his hireling attendants, a 
confederate association of witnesses, not indeed troubling you 
openly, but without any scruple expressing their assent 
to falsehoods. By heaven, I do not believe that they 
derive any advantage from him, but they have a surprising 
habit of surrendering themselves disgracefully (φθείρεσθαι) 
to the rich, and following at their heels, and giving testimony 
for them.’ Another Euctemon is mentioned with great com- 
mendation in the same speech,’ and has been identified with 
the prosecutor of Timocrates and Androtion; but the fact 
that Euctemon takes the lead in an attack on such a for- 
midable antagonist as the latter, seems to show that he was, 
like the other Euctemon, an orator and public man, as in- 
deed we know he was; and the friendly relations, which after- 
wards subsisted between Polyeuctus and Demosthenes, are at 





1 Soph, Ajax, 678: 
ἐγὼ δ᾽ ἐπίσταμαι yap ἀρτίως ὅτι 
ὅ τ᾽ ἐχθρὸς ἡμῖν ἐς τοσόνδ᾽ ἐχθαρτέος 
- ws καὶ φιλήσων αὖθις" ἔς τε τὸν φίλον“ 
τοσαῦθ᾽ ὑπουργῶν ὠφελεῖν βουλήσομαι 
ὡς αἰὲν οὐ μενοῦντα᾽ τοῖς πολλοῖσι γὰρ 
βροτῶν ἄπιστός ἐσθ᾽ ἑταιρείας λιμήν. 
Cf. Dem. 6. Aristocr. p. 660, 24, who expresses this sentiment in his own words, 
and see Arist. Rhet. II. 13, § 4; Cic. Lal. c. 16. 

2 0. Mid. p. 560,§2. It is the opinion of Ruhnken that the Polyeuctus 
here was the same as the orator of Sphettus, but Béhnecke and Dindorf think 
this improbable. 

3. C. Mid. p. 568, 1. 24. 





THE ORATION AGAINST ARISTOCRATES. 333 


least as inconsistent with this passage as the association here 
of Euctemon and Timocrates. 

The elaborate oration against Aristocrates, in B.c. 352, was 
composed for one Euthycles, who had served as a trierarch on 
the coast of Thrace, and had appeared on former occasions as 
an accuser.’ The oration is interesting from the information, 
which we derive from it, respecting the laws of Athens and the 
affairs of Thrace, and though it generally exhibits an elaboration 
of arguments rather than the energy of fervid eloquence, there 
are here and there some very striking passages, as, for example, 
that in which he compares the selfishness of the contemporary 
statesmen with the patriotism of such citizens as Miltiades, 
Themistocles, and Aristides. ‘In those days,’ he says,’ ‘the 
people was the master, now it is the ministering slave of the 
public men. They, who propose such decrees—who accustom 
you to think lightly of yourselves, and to hold in reverence some 
one or two individuals,—are to blame for all this. They it is 
who have stepped into the inheritance of your glory and your 
possessions, whereas you have not the least advantage from them, 
but witness the prosperity of others ; having no share in anything 
—except being cheated. And yet what would be the groaning 
of those great men, who died for glory and for freedom, and 
left behind the records of many noble deeds, if by any possi- 
bility they could be aware that the city has now degraded itself 
to the form and office of a dependent, and is actually debating 
whether it is right to protect the person of Charidemus. Of | 
Charidemus! out upon him "ἢ 

The investigations of modern scholars have confirmed the 
opinions of the old critics, that the orations against Theocrines‘ 
and Neera, and the two speeches against Aristogeiton, are not 
the genuine works of Demosthenes. The first of these, which 





1 ©. Aristocr. p. 622, 1. 27. 2 Ibid. p. 690, 1. το. 

3 The conclusion deserves to be quoted in the original: καίτοι πηλίκον τί ποτ 
ἂν στενάξειαν οἱ ἄνδρες ἐκεῖνοι, οἱ ὑπὲρ δόξης Kal ἐλευθερίας τελευτήσαντες Kal πολλῶν 
καὶ καλῶν ἔργων ὑπομνήματα καταλιπόντες εἰ ἄρα αἴσθοιντο ὅτι νῦν ἡ πόλις εἰς 
ὑπηρέτου σχῆμα καὶ τάξιν προελήλυθε, καὶ Χαρίδημον εἰ χρὴ φρουρεῖν βουλεύεται ; 
Kaplinuor ; οἴμοι (6. Aristocr. p. 690, 1. 17). For the force of οἴμοι, see Soph, 
Antig. 86. Aristoph. Aves, 145. 

4 The Theocrines, in this case, was perhaps the loud-voiced and histrionic 
speaker mentioned in the Qrat. de Coron. p. 329, 26, 


834 DEMOSTHENES. 


was delivered in B.c. 333, is an ἔνδειξις brought by one 
Epichares, and is distinctly attributed to Deimarchus by 
Dionysius of Halicarnassus." The second was probably classed 
with the works of Demosthenes, because it was drawn up for 
Apollodorus, the son of Pasion, for whom Demosthenes com- 
posed so many forensic addresses. It is referred to the year 
B.C. 340. Its genuineness is doubted by Phrynichus,’ Photius,’ 
and Athenzeus,‘ chiefly on account of its style. The majority 
of modern critics have agreed in discarding it. The two 
speeches against <Aristogeiton are rhetorical exercitations by 
later sophists analogous to that which Aristides composed on 
the same subject as the Leptinean oration.’ It is a fact that 
Demosthenes took a part, apparently a secondary part, with 
Lycurgus, in the prosecution of Aristogeiton in B.c. 331 ;° and 
we have still the speech in which the same individual was 
attacked by Deinarchus in B.c. 324. And this was a sufficient 
reason for the selection of this cause for an exercise by some 
rhetorician. But it is probable that Demosthenes, who followed 
Lycurgus, had not much occasion to make an elaborate speech, 
and that he did not think it worth while to publish what he 
had spoken. 

§ 4. The two great speeches against Alschines, the un- 
successful attack in the speech on the Embassy in B.c. 343, and 
the triumphant defence in the speech on the Crown in B.c. 330, 
are the most elaborate and important of all the orations of 
Demosthenes; and in studying them we have the peculiar 
advantage of possessing the corresponding addresses of the rival 
orator, 

Both in literary merit and in real power, the speech on the 
Embassy appears to us conspicuously inferior to that on the 
Crown. In the former, Demosthenes seems to feel throughout 
an imperfect confidence in the goodness of. his cause. That 





1 De Dinarcho, p. 652; Reiske. Cf, Harpocration, s.vv. ἀγραφίου and Θεοκρίνης. 

2 p. 225, Lobeck: διά re τὰ ἄλλα ὑπωπτεύθη μὴ εἶναι Δημοσθένους καὶ διὰ τὰ 
τοιαῦτα τῶν ἀδοκίμων ὀνομάτων. 

8 Cod. ΟΟἸΧΥ, 4 XIII. p. 573 B.: εἰ γνήσιος. 

5 See Westermann, Quest. Demosthen. pars 111,, reprinted in Dindorf’s Anno- 
tationes, II. pp. 1012-1020. 

6 Liban. Argum. p. 769, Phot. Cod. CCLXV. 


THE SPEECH ON THE EMBASSY. 335 


Philocrates had been guilty of corruption and treason might be 
regarded as an established fact. But the anti-Macedonian 
party had no sufficient evidence to bring home the same charge 
to Aischines. There can be little doubt that Aischines, like 
Phocion and Eubulus, was influenced at first by the general 
tendencies of the Athenian people, and by a wish to make 
political capital in following the stream of public opinion, 
rather than by any corrupt motives; though in all probability 
these were superadded when A%schines came under the imme- 
diate pressure of Macedonian seductions. Demosthenes, too, 
may have felt that he had been too ready himself to accept the 
peace, and that he had not spoken out on some points so plainly 
as he ought to have done.’ Perhaps, too, the ruin of Timarchus,? 
who had been originally associated with him in the prosecution, 
may have damped his ardour, or at least that of his supporters. 
Be this as it may, there is certainly a want of cogency in many 
parts of this speech; it is comparatively lax in its order and 
arrangement; there are repetitions, as though the author 
thought that a re-assertion was equivalent to an additional 
argument; and in some parts the evidence seems to have 
broken down altogether.’ Nevertheless, its general tendency 
is to explain and justify the policy which Demosthenes con- 
sistently adopted; and when the orator speaks more of the 
general corruption of the age than of the particular faults of 
Aaschines, his eloquence is irresistible. Nothing, for example, 
could be finer, than the passage in which he describes the 
morbid state of political morals in Greece :* ‘ A disease, men of 
Athens, a dreadful and violent disease, has fallen on Greece— 
one that exacts on your part extraordinary good fortune and 





1 See the criticisms of Grote, XI. pp. 553 foll. 

2 De Pals. Legat. p. 341: τὸν μὲν ἀνήρηκε τῶν ἐπὶ ras εὐθύνας ἐλθόντων. That 
this means the disfranchisement and not the death of Timarchus is clear from the 
glosses in Bekker’s Anecdota, pp. 27, 16, 402, 23, and the passages quoted by Mr. 
Shilleto, Pals. Leg. p. 432 ; Mid. p. 548. ‘According to one account,’ says Dr. 
Thirlwall (VI. p. 29), ‘he put an end to his life—a sign of greater sensibility than 
might have been expected from so profligate a man.’ This other account is given 
in the Vite X. Oratorum, p. 841 A. 

3 As in the story of the Olynthian woman. Cf. Dem. Fals. Leg. p. 402, with 
Ausch. Fals. Leg. sub initio, and pp. 48, 49. 

4 Fals. Leg. p. 424. 


336 DEMOSTHENES. 


unusual care. For the men of most consideration in the par- 
ticular cities, and those who are entrusted with the manage- 
ment of affairs, betraying their own freedom, the unfortunate 
men! are bringing on themselves a voluntary servitude, calling 
it by the flattering names of correspondence, association, inti- 
macy with Philip, and the like;’ while the rest, and whatever 
are the governing bodies in the several cities, whose duty it is 
to punish these men, and put them to death on the spot, are 
so far from doing any such thing that they admire and envy 
them, and would willingly act in the same way, every one for 
himself.” The story, too, about the Olynthian woman, though 
unsupported or rather contradicted by evidence, is a masterpiece 
of criminatory narrative. And the speech, as a whole, must 
have produced a great effect. For though Aischines made an 
admirable defence, and was supported by men of great influence, 
though the allegations of Demosthenes were often false or 
inaccurate, and though he laboured throughout under the dis- 
advantage of bringing an invidious charge against a colleague 
with whom he had acted with general harmony and agreement, 
aschines did not obtain a triumphant acquittal, but could only 
command a majority of thirty votes,’ which in so numerous a 
jury was quite inconsiderable; and we do not find that he 
afterwards regarded his victory with much satisfaction. 

To the universal admiration with which the oration on the 
Crown has been regarded we have no qualifications to make. 
As an effort of oratory it is unsurpassed by any composition in 
ancient or modern times; and it has been justly remarked that 
it ‘has an historical value as a funeral oration of extinct 
Athenian and Grecian freedom.* The grounds, on which 
/Eschines impeached Ctesiphon’s proposal to crown and eulogize 
Demosthenes, not only justified but exacted from the latter a 
complete review of his whole political career. The accuser 
maintained that Ctesiphon had broken the Athenian laws in 
three points: (1) because it was unlawful to crown a public 
functionary before he had rendered an account of his conduct ; 





1 Φιλίππου ἕενίαν καὶ ἑταιρίαν καὶ φιλίαν καὶ τοιαῦθ᾽ ὑποκοριζόμενοι. 

2 Plutarch, Dem. 15, on the authority of Idomeneus οὗ Lampsacus, who was 
nearly a contemporary of Demosthenes. 

3 Grote, History of Greece, XII. p. 393. 


: a 


THE SPEECH ON THE CROWN. 857 


(2) because it was unlawful to proclaim the distinction at the 
Dionysian festival, the proper place being the Council-hall, if 
the Council awarded the crown, and the Pnyx, if the assembly 
decreed it; (3) because it was unlawful to state a falsehood in 
a public document, and it was false that Demosthenes had 
deserved any reward, as was stated in the decree, Both the 
speech of Alschines and the reply of Demosthenes discuss the 
legal arguments with comparative brevity, and direct all their 
efforts to the establishment or refutation of the statement that 
Demosthenes had deserved a public recognition of his virtue 
and patriotism.’ In the oration for the defence, which is now 
before us, it is the main object of the speaker to show that the 
policy, which he had consistently pursued, had been designed 
and calculated to strengthen Athens, and to defeat the machi- 
nations of foreign enemies, especially Philip of Macedon; and 
acknowledging that he had failed, he shows that his failure had ᾿ 
not been occasioned by any lack of exertions on his part, and 
that his fellow-citizens had, in the midst of their disasters, 
gained more glory than they would have obtained by the 
highest success, if they had followed the converse policy. That 
the Athenians felt this is proved by the result of the trial—a 
result not less honourable to the judges than to Demosthenes 
himself. For in spite of the bitter memories of Cheroneia, the 
near approach of danger after the downfal of the Thebans, and 
the subsequent growth of Alexander’s power, the men of Athens 
had the magnanimity to re-affirm their approbation of the anti- 
Macedonian policy, by such a complete acquittal of Ctesiphon 
as amounted to a direct censure of his prosecutor. Aischines 
did not obtain the fifth part of the votes, and feeling that his 
influence at Athens was at an end, at least so long as the 
commonwealth retained its freedom of deliberation, he retired 
from the scene of his discomfiture, and went over to Asia in 
the hope of obtaining fresh countenance and support from 
Alexander—a hope which the king’s death soon dissipated ; and 
he passed the remainder of his life as a teacher of rhetoric at 
Rhodes. 





1 This issue is fairly challenged in the words of the decree (Argum. p. 223): 
ἐπειδὴ διατελεῖ Δημοσθένης ὁ Δημοσθένους map’ ὅλον τὸν βίον εὔνοιαν εἰς τὴν πόλιν 
ἐπιδεικνύμενος. ᾿ 


Vou. II. Z 


338 DEMOSTHENES. 


Our limits do not allow us to attempt any lengthened analysis 
of this great oration, or to exhibit its peculiar beauties by 
adequate specimens. It must be read as a whole by those who 
would thoroughly appreciate it. Still, it is impossible to 
mention it without referrmg to some of the brilliant passages, 
which are cited invariably as the best illustration of the orator’s 
peculiar genius. Nothing, for example, can surpass the passage 
in which he maintains the wisdom of facing death in the 
unselfish pursuit of glory.’ ‘ Death is to all men the end 
of life, even though one should keep oneself shut up in a cage; 
but it is the duty of good men to aim at all that is noble, 
holding ever before their eyes a hope for the best, ‘and en- 
during in a manly spirit whatever the Deity may impose.’ 
In a similar strain we have the celebrated passage in which he 
assures the Athenians that his policy was in accordance with 
their own true instincts, and that it would be an imsult to 
them to say that he instructed them in sentiments worthy of 
their ancestors; but that if they convicted Ctesiphon they 
would convict themselves, not their ‘adviser, of an erroneous 
policy. ‘ But it is impossible,’ he cries, ‘it is impossible that 
you have erred, men of Athens, in taking on yourselves the 
risk for the freedom and ‘safety of all Greece! No! I swear 
it, by those of your ancestors who placed themselves in danger’s 
van at Marathon, by those who joined the line of battle at 
Plateea, by those who fought in the ships at Salamis and 
Artemisium, and many other brave men who are laid to rest 
in the public monuments, all of whom alike the city interred, 
thinking them all worthy of the same honour, Aischines, and 
not merely those among them who had succeeded and were 
victorious. Justly! for that which was the duty of brave men 
was done by all of them, and the fortune which they expe- 
rienced was that which the Deity assigned to each of them,’ 
Other passages of the most fervid eloquence, which ‘are gene- 
rally cited from this speech, are the description of the excite- 
ment at Athens, when the news came that Philip had occupied 





1 De Corona, p. 258: πέρας yap ἅπασιν ἀνθρώποις ἐστὶ τοῦ βίου θάνατος κἂν ἐν 
οἰκίσκῳ τις αὑτὸν καθείρξας τηρῇ᾽ δεῖ δὲ τοὺς ἀγαθοὺς ἄνδρας ἐγχειρεῖν μὲν ἅπασιν ἀεὶ 
τοῖς καλοῖς τὴν ἀγαθὴν προβαλλομένους ἐλπίδα, φέρειν δὲ ὅτι ἂν ὁ θεὸς διδῷ γενναίως, 

2 De Corond, p. 297. 


THE SPEECH ON THE CROWN. 839 


Elatea,' that in which Demosthenes maintains that he has fortified 
Athens, not with material walls only, but with armaments and 
fleets,’ that in which he asserts the high principles by which his 
public life had been actuated,* and that in which he contrasts the 
motives by which the Athenians were bound to be influenced 
with those of the semi-barbarous Philip, who was willing to 
sacrifice any part of his body which fortune chose to take from 
him, provided he might live in honour and glory with what 
remained.‘ Nor is the oration remarkable only for passages of 
an elevated character. Its sarcasm and invective are un- 
equalled. His elaborate comparison of his own respectability with 
the humble early life of his rival,’ and his attack on the father 
of Aischines as not only a slave, but a runaway slave, on his 
mother as not only a harlot, but a shameless one’—whatever 
we may think of their taste or even of their strict veracity— 
are unsurpassed as efforts of withering scorn and overwhelming 
contumely. ‘The speech, too, abounds in those figures of diction 
which by their pungency leave the sting in the memory, as when 
he speaks of ‘ the crop of traitors, and bought statesmen, and 
heaven-hated wretches,” who had sprung up as the aiders and 
abettors of Philip ; or where he says,° that ‘ whenever anything 
untoward happens, Aischines is sure to come forth, just as 
fractures and sprains are most felt when the body is attacked 
by some disease.’ 

Great as are the literary merits of the oration on the Crown, 
they were very much enhanced by the splendid action with 
which it was delivered ; and a story is told that, when Aischines 
read the speech to his hearers at Rhodes, and when some of 
them loudly expressed their admiration, the defeated accuser 
could not refrain from exclaiming, ‘what would you say if you 
had heard the villain himself speak it ?”° 





1 De Oorond, p. 284. 2 Ibid. p. 325. 1. 22. 

8 Tbid. 1. 4. 4 Ibid. p. 247. 

5 Ibid. p. 315. Of. Milton, Smectymnuus, p. 80 (prose works, in.one volume). 

6 p. 270. 

7 p. 245. 1. 16: φορὰ προδοτῶν καὶ δωροδόκων καὶ θεοῖς ἐχθρῶν ἀνθρώπων. 

8 p. 294. lar. 

9 Cic. de Orat. III. 56. Quintil. XI. 3, § 6. Philostrat. Vit. Sophist. I. το. 
5. Vit. X. Orat. Photius. Ood. CCLXIV. Valer. Max. VIII..10. p. 840 D. 
Plin. H. N. VIII. 30. Plin. Epist, ΤΙ. 3. το. 

Z2 


340 DEMOSTHENES. 


§ 5. Of the thirty-one private orations of Demosthenes 
which have come down to us, only four are regarded with any 
doubt by the ancient grammarians—that against Euergus and 
Mnesibulus, which is questioned by Harpocration ;' that against 
Phenippus concerning the Exchange, which the author of the 
argument tells us was by some not referred to the great orator 7 
that in answer to the Demurrer of Lacritus, which the author 
of the argument tells us was regarded by some as not genuine, 
but on very feeble arguments ;* and that against Nicostratus, 
which Harpocration seems to doubt. But the evidence in 
favour of the authenticity of the last two of these speeches 
outweighs that in the contrary scale. Of the remaining 
twenty-seven, five are the speeches against his guardians 
(ἐπιτροπικοὶ λόγοι), to which we have made reference already, 
and no less than eight had reference to the litigations in which 
Apollodorus was engaged. All these private speeches have a 
general interest for the scholar, not only as furnishing specimens 
of the legal knowledge and argumentative ability of the writer, 
but also as contributing in no small degree to our knowledge 
of the public and private economy of Athens. The speeches 
composed for Apollodorus demand a special notice, on account 
of some critical questions which affect not merely the chrono- 
logical arrangement of these orations, but also in some measure 
the moral character of Demosthenes himself. 

Apollodorus was the son of Pasion, an eminent banker at 
Athens, who died in B.c. 370,° leaving two sons by his wife 
Archippe, namely, Apollodorus, who was then twenty-four, and 
Pasicles who was a minor. He consigned his wife and the 
guardianship of Pasicles to Phormio, his freedman, who had 





1 s.vv. ἐκαλίστρουν, ἠτημένην. He says he feels disposed to assign it to 
Deinarchus. , 

2 p. 1037. 21: ὃ μὲν λόγος οὐκ ἀναφέρεται παρά τινων els τὸν Δημοσθένην. 

3 p. 923.1. 10: οὐκ ὀρθῶς δέ τινες ἐνόμισαν τὸν λόγον μὴ γνήσιον εἶναι ἀμυδροῖς 
ἀπατηθέντες τεκμηρίοις. 

4 s.v. ἀπογραφή: ἐν τῷ Δημοσθένους πρὸς Νικόστρατον περὶ τῶν ᾿Αρεθουσίου 
ἀνδραπόδων, εἰ γνήσιος. 

5 The relations between Apollodorus and Demosthenes are discussed by Beels in 
his Diatribe in Demosthenis Orationes, I. et II. in Stephanuwm, Lugd. Bat. 1825, — 
from which there are some extracts in Dindorf’s Annotationes, ITI. pp. 1226—1233. 

6 Dem. in Steph. II. p. 1132. 1. 25. x 


HIS PRIVATE ORATIONS. 341 


hired the management of his bank. Apollodorus was at that 
time absent from Athens, as the commander of a trireme, and 
being dissatisfied with his mother’s marriage, he commenced an 
action against Phormio, which was dropped partly on her 
intercession.’ For the rest of his mother’s life he remained on 
good terms with Phormio. Archippe died in B.c. 360,” imme- 
diately after the return of Apollodorus from the protracted 
trierarchy which led to his action against Polycles, and to 
the speech which Demosthenes composed for that prosecution. 
The death of his mother brought Apollodorus into other dis- 
putes with Phormio, which were compromised by a payment 
from Phormio of 5000 drachme, and the parties were reconciled.® 
Notwithstanding this, in the year B.c. 350, Apollodorus brought 
an action for twenty talents, the capital (ἀφορμή) of the bank, 
against Phormio,* who entered a demurrer (zapaypagn), and 
by this means was enabled to take the initiative in the suit, 
and, by establishing the fact of the compromise, to nonsuit the 
plaintiff Apollodorus.’ Here we find Demosthenes opposed to 
his old client, and the speech for Phormio was that which gave 
success to the demurrer or cross-action. The litigious son of 
Pasion was not satisfied with this decision, and brought an action 
for perjury against one of the witnesses, Stephanus, in support of 
which Demosthenes composed the two extant orations against 
Stephanus ; and we find that Demosthenes was engaged for 
Apollodorus when he wrote the speech against Nicostratus, 
about the same time as the prosecution of Midias in B.c. 348.° 
Now it was im reference to this acceptance of a brief for 
Phormio, probably the only occasion on which Demosthenes 
wrote a speech against Apollodorus, that Aischines, in his 
speech on the Embassy, in 8.c. 343, taunts him with treachery 





1 in Steph. I. p. 1102, II. p. 1135. 2 adv. Polyclem. p. 4225. 

3 Pro Phormione, pp. 948 sqq. 

* Ibid. pp.-945, 949. 

5 Beels’ erroneously supposes that Demosthenes wrote a speech πρὸς. Φορμίωνα 
for Apollodorus, as well as the speech ὑπὲρ Φορμίωνος, which is found.among his 
works. But this rests on a misunderstanding of the words of Plutarch, who, in 
speaking of the τοὺς πρὸς Φορμίωνα καὶ Στέφανον λόγους, merely means the two 
speeches against Stephanus, which were virtually against Phormio; see Dindorf. 
Annot, III, p. 1230. 

§ Dindorf, ad Dem. Nicostr. Ὁ. 1247, 6. 


842 DEMOSTHENES. 


not to Apollodorus, but to Phormio,’ and both Aischines and 
Deinarchus’ insinuate that the opulence of Phormio enabled 
him to purchase the services of the venal orator. It appears to 
us most probable that at the time of the final quarrel between 
Apollodorus and Phormio, Demosthenes was equally intimate 
with both parties, but was shortly after led to associate him- 
self more closely with Apollodorus, by their common opposition 
to Eubulus, the supporter of Midias and the patron of 
fischines. It must not be forgotten that it was about this 
time that Apollodorus made the patriotic motion about the 
Theoric fund, in opposition to Eubulus, and in accordance with 
the opinion of Demosthenes, and that he was prosecuted for it 
in a most vindictive manner by a man named Stephanus,’ 
perhaps the very Stephanus against whom Demosthenes wrote 
the speech. This union in public matters would be quite 
sufficient to account for the conduct of Demosthenes, and for 
the mode in which Aischines alludes to it. At any rate, there 
is not the slightest ground for the opinion which has been 
derived from Plutarch,’ that Demosthenes wrote speeches both 
for Phormio and for Apollodorus in one and the same 
cause. 

§ 6. The style and characteristics of Demosthenes have fur- 
nished the ancient critic Dionysius, of Halicarnassus, with the 
materials for a special treatise ; and a great modern orator, Lord 
Brougham, has made this master of ancient eloquence the theme 
of more than one glowing tribute of praise. As Thucydides 
was the historian, and Homer ¢he poet of the old grammarians, in 
a special and emphatic sense, so Demosthenes was their orator, 
par excellence. Hermogenes places him at the head of all 





1 Asch. Fals. Legat. p. 50, 1. 23: Gpd γε οὐχ ὡς σὺ τοῖς ἐντυγχάνουσι καὶ 
πιστεύσασι κέχρησαι, λόγους els δικαστήρια γράφοντα μισθοῦ τούτους ἐκφέρειν τοῖς 
ἀντιδίκοις ; ἔγραψας λόγον Φορμίωνι τῷ τραπεζίτῃ χρήματα λαβών. τοῦτον ἐξήνεγκαΞ 
᾿Απολλοδώρῳ τῷ περὶ τοῦ σώματος κρίνοντι Φορμίωνα. Of. im Nicostr. p. 1251, 1. 

2 In Demosth. p. 104, 1. 19. 3 Grote, XI. p. 485. 

4 Plutarch, Dem. 15 ; see Clinton, F. H. II. p. 358, and note 5 in the preceding 
page. 

5 Anonym. ad Aphthoniwm, Rhet. Gr. II. p. τό, το, Walz.: κατ᾽ ἐξοχὴν εἴρη- 
Tat... . ὥσπερ καὶ τὸν Δημοσθένην ῥήτορα λέγομεν. Doxopater, Homil. in 
Aphthon. II. p. 515, Walz: συγγραφέα 6’A, τὸν Θουκυδίδην φησὶ κατὰ τὸ ἐξαίρετον, 
ὥσπερ καὶ ποιητὴν τὸν Ὅμηρόν φαμεν... .. καὶ ῥήτορα ὁμοίως τὸν Δημοσθένην. 


HIS STYLE. 343 


political speakers,’ and the same was the opinion of Theon.? 
Cicero calls him the prince of orators,’ and declares that nothing 
was wanting to his perfection.‘ He was not inferior, says the 
Roman master of eloquence, to Lysias in subtilty, to 
Hypereides in ingenuity and acuteness, or to Aischines in the 
exquisite finish and brilliancy of his style.’ 

Dionysius, as we have already mentioned,’ places Demo- 
sthenes and Plato at the head of the most perfect writers in 
that middle or mixed style, which combined the simplicity of 
Lysias with the weightier eloquence of Thucydides and Gorgias, 
and which Thrasymachus was the first to introduce. That 
Demosthenes was a diligent student of Thucydides is sufficiently 
attested by the fact, if it is a fact, that he copied out the history 
eight times.’ His direct imitation of Thucydides has been 
recognized by Dionysius,* who also saw that his enthymemes 
or rhetorical arguments were the same as those of the histo- 
rian.’ At the same time it is observed that he followed closely 
in the steps of Isocrates and Iszeus,”* being especially indebted 
to the latter." The extent to which Plato contributed to form 
the style of Demosthenes has been differently estimated. 
Cicero says, distinctly enough, that Demosthenes was not 
merely a diligent reader of Plato, but that he had been one of 
his hearers, and that he had admitted this in a letter.” This 
is also stated by Plutarch, on the authority of Hermippus, who 
adds that Demosthenes was much benefited in his oratorical 





1 Hermogenes, περὶ ἰδεῶν, III. p. 366, 18, Walz: ἄριστός τε γὰρ πολιτικῶν 
λόγων 6 Δημοσθενικός, ὅ τε αὖ Δημοσθενικὸς λόγος τῶν πολιτικῶν ἄριστος. 

3 Theo. προγυμνάσματα, I. p. 200, 6, Walz. 

8 Brutus, 37, § 141. 

4 Thid. 9, § 33; De Oratore, I. 13, ὃ 58. 

5 Orator. 31, ὃ 110: ‘Demosthenes .. . nihil Lysie subtilitate cedit, nihil 
argutiis et acumine Hyperidi, nihil levitate Aischini et splendore verborum.’ 

6 Above, c, XX XIX. § το. 

7 Lucian adv. indoctum, p. 102. 

8 De Thucyd. judicium, p. 944, Reiske. 

9. Ad Pomp. de precip. historicis, p. 777, Reiske. 

10 Dionys. Hal. de Demosth. et Aristot. p. 723, Reiske. 

11 Dionys. Hal. de Iswo, p. 586, 592, O11. 

2 Brutus, 31, § 121: ‘lectitavisse Platonem studiose, audivisse etiam Demo- 
sthenes dicitur, idque apparet ex genere et granditate verborum ; dicit etiam in 
qu&dam epistol& hoc ipse de sese.’ Cf. De Oratore, I. 20, De Offciis, I. τ, 


344 DEMOSTHENES. 


style by the lessons which he received from Plato.’ And a 
modern Dutch scholar, who is an enthusiastic admirer of the 
great philosopher, not only maintains that the style of Demo- 
sthenes was framed on the Platonic model, but even discerns in 
his speeches some genuine fragments of dialogues and dramatic 
scenes in direct imitation of Plato. On the other hand, 
Dionysius more than once asserts that the composition (σύνθεσις) 
of Demosthenes was decidedly superior to that of Plato,* and 
tells us that the orator was not an imitator of any style or 
any man, thinking that all his predecessors had only gone 
half-way, and were incomplete, but that he selected from all of 
them what was best and most useful, and wove it into one 
texture, making from them all one new dialect at once rich and 
simple, elaborate and ordinary, novel and common, showy and 
solid, grave and gay, vehement and tranquil, pleasant and bitter, 
moral and impassioned, exhibiting in faet as many changes as 
the fabled Proteus.‘ It appears to us that the main characteristic 
of the eloquence of Demosthenes—that, in fact, which explains 
the wonderful effects produced by it on popular assemblies—is this, 
that he used the common language of his age and country, that 
he took the greatest pains in choosing and arranging his words, 
that he aimed at the utmost conciseness, making epithets, even 
common adjectives, do the work of a whole sentence, and that 
he was enabled, by a perfect delivery and action, to give the 
proper emphasis and the full effect to the terms which he had 
selected with so much care, so that a sentence, composed of 
ordinary terms, sometimes smote with the weight of a sledge- 
hammer. His rival, Aischines, who sometimes admits inci- 
dentally this wonderful power of Demosthenes in putting his 





1 Plut. Vita Demosth. 5: “Ἕρμιππος δέ φησιν ἀδεσπότοις ὑπομνήμασιν ἐντυχεῖν, 
ἐν οἷς ἐγέγραπτο τὸν Δημοσθένη συνεσχολακέναι Πλάτωνι, καὶ πλεῖστον εἰς τοὺς 
λόγους ὠφελῆσθαι. : 

2 P. W. van Heusde, Initia Philosophie Platonice, vol. II. partI. pp. 151 sqq. 
He says: ‘exstant in ejus orationibus colloquia forma et ratione prorsus Platonica,’ 
and he cites, Cherson., p. 98 D; Philipp. IV. p. 150 A; Phil. I. p. 43 A. Cf. 
Phil. TV. 138 B. C. 

3 De Compos. verborum, p. 117, Reiske. 

4 De admir. vi dicendi in Dem. p. 974; 5, Reiske: μιὰν ἐκ πολλῶν διάλεκτον 
ἀπετέλει, μεγαχοπρεπῆ, λιτήν" περιττήν, ἀπέριττον' ἐξηλλαγμένην, συνήθη" πανη- 
γυρικήν, ἀληθινήν' αὐστηράν, ἵλαράν' σύντονον, ἀνειμένην" ἡδεῖαν, πικράν' ἠθικήν, 
παθητικήν, κιτ.Ὰ. 


HIS STYLE. 345 


words together,’ in one passage charges him with using the 
most uncouth and offensive figures of speech.” He wonders 
how the Athenians could tolerate such expressions as ‘ some 
people are vinedressing the state,’ ‘some have amputated the 
vine-twigs of the people, ‘our affairs have been hamstrung,’ 
‘ we are being stitched into baskets,’ ‘ some persons are inserting 
themselves like needles into the interstices,’ and then exclaims, 
‘what are these expressions, you fox? are they words or 
wonders?? Dionysius seems to be justified in treating this 
statement as a calumny, and says that although Demosthenes 
has left 50,000 or 60,000 lines: of his writing, no such expres- 
sions are to be found in any of his speeches.* Aischines knew 
as well as any one that the strength of Demosthenes did not 
consist in tumid extravagances like these. In the last speech 
which he heard Demosthenes deliver, Demosthenes inveighed 
with deliberate and concentrated virulence against the parents 
of his opponent, and contrived to express the most cruel impu- 
tations, without using any extravagant compounds. By a 
skilful use of the simplest terms, he tells the Athenians that 
the father of Aischines was the runaway slave of a poor school- 
master in the worst part of the town, and that his mother 
combined shameless profligacy with the most abject poverty.’ 





1 Dionys. Hal. De adm. vi dicendi in Dem. p. 1064. 

2 Misch. adv. Ctesiph. p. 77, ὃ 166: οὐ μέμνησθε αὐτοῦ τὰ μιαρὰ καὶ ἀπίθανα 
ῥήματα, ἃ πῶς ποθ᾽ ὑμεῖς, ὦ σιδήρεοι, ἐκαρτερεῖτε ἀκροώμενοι ; ὅτ᾽ ἔφη παρελθὼν 
* ἀμπελουργοῦσέτινες τὴν πολιν,᾽ ‘ ἀνατέτμηκασί τινες τὰ κλήματα τοῦ δήμου, “" ὑποτέ- 
τμηται τὰ νεῦρα τῶν πραγμάτων, "“φορμοῤῥαφούμεθα,᾽ " ἐπὶ τὰ στενά τινες ἑαυτοὺς ὥσπερ 
τὰς βελόνας διείρουσι. ταῦτα δὲ τί ἐστι, ὦ κίναδος ; ῥήματα ἢ θαύματα ; We have 
here emended πρῶτον in the last phrase attributed to Demosthenes, and have sub- 
stituted ἑαυτούς to explain the comparison ; for διείρειν βελονὰς was the regular 
phrase, as we see in the passage of Galen quoted by Budeus: διεκβάλλειν καὶ 
διείρειν τὴν βελονὴν ἐν τῇ γαστροῤῥαφίᾳ. That φορμοῤῥαφούμεθα ἐπὶ τὰ στενὰ is not 
the construction is shown by the citation in Dionysius, p. 1126, who puts καὶ after 
the verb. 

3 ubi supra p. 1126. 

4 De Corond, p.270. The insinuation against the father of Auschines is exagge- 
rated by every turn in the expression: ‘he was a slave—in the house of an ele- 
mentary schoolmaster—near the Theseum—and wore fetters and a collar!’ So 
also of the mother: ‘She lived by her broad daylight espousals—in a temporary 
hovel—close by the shop of Hero the quack-doctor!’ The reference to the κλίσιον 
reminds one of Lady Wishfort’s vituperation of her maid, whom she found ‘ dining 
behind a traverse rag in a shop no bigger than a bird-cage’ (Congreve, Way of the 
World, act V. sc. I.). 


346 DEMOSTHENES. 


And he excuses himself from any further prosecution of the 
subject: ‘ Really,’ he says, ‘ Aischines was not even the son of 
merely commonplace parents; he springs from those who are 
included in the public execrations with which we commence our 
meetings.’ In such a passage as this, and there are many like 
it, we see that he had carefully considered every word, and that 
a good deal of the effect must have been due to the delivery. 
The elaborate painstaking which characterizes the composition 
of Demosthenes explains the repetitions of striking passages 
which we find in his speeches. ‘Practised as he was,’ says 
Lord Brougham,’ ‘and able surely, if any man ever was, by 
his mastery over language, to pour out his ideas with facility, 
he elaborated every passage with almost equal care. Having 
the same ideas to express, he did not, like our easy and fluent 
moderns, clothe them in different language for the sake of 
variety, but reflecting that he had, upon the fullest deliberation, 
adopted one form of expression as the best, and because every 
other must needs be worse, he used it again without any 
change, unless further labour and more trials had enabled him 
in any particular to improve the workmanship.’ The same 
eminent modern orator has, as it seems to us, most accurately 
described the general characteristics of Demosthenes in another 
passage of the same essay, where he says,’ that ‘ there is not 
any long or close train of reasoning in the orations of Demo- 
sthenes, still less any profound observations or remote and 
ingenious allusions, but a constant succession of remarks, 
bearing immediately on the matter in hand, perfectly plain, and 
as readily admitted as easily understood. These are inter- 
mingled with the most striking appeals, sometimes to feelings 
which all were conscious of, and deeply agitated by, though 
ashamed to own; sometimes to sentiments which every man 
was panting to utter, and delighted to hear thundered forth— 
bursts of oratory, therefore, which either overwhelmed or 





1 οὐδὲ yap ὧν ἔτυχεν ἣν ἀλλ᾽ οἷς ὁ δῆμος καταρᾶται, The reference is to the public 
prayers and execrations proclaimed by the herald, a sort of bidding-prayer, before 
the commencement of business in the Athenian ecclesia, 

2 Rhetorical and Literary Dissertations and Addresses, Works, vol. VII. p. 192. 

3 Ibid. p. 196. 


4 


HIS STYLE.  §aF 


relieved the audience. Such hits,if we may use such a homely 
phrase (for more dignified language has no word to express the 
thing), are the principal glory of the great combatant; it is 
by them that he carries all before him, and to these that he 
sacrifices all the paltry graces which are the delight of the 
Asian and Italian schools.’ 


348 


CHAPTER XLII. 


ORATORS CONTEMPORARY WITH DEMOSTHENES, 


§ 1. The contemporaries of Demosthenes, with the exception of Iseus, may be 
classed as patriots and Macedonizers. § 2. Orators of the Alexandrian Canon. 
Iseus. ὃ 3. Party of the patriots (a.) Lycurgus. ὃ 4. (b.) Hypereides. 
8 5. Macedonian party (a.) Aischines. ὃ 6. (b.) Deinarchus. 


§ 1. MONG the orators who are regarded as the contem- 

poraries of Demosthenes, we must count Iszeus, from 
whom he received instruction and assistance at the beginning 
of his career, and Deinarchus and Demochares, whose chief 
activity on opposite sides belongs to the period succeeding the 
death of the great statesman. In the long interval between 
the first and the last of these public speakers—an interval which 
extends from the days of Lysias to those of Demetrius 
Phalereus—the most prominent subject of discussion was the 
opposition between the interests of Macedon and Athens; and 
we may therefore divide all the contemporary orators, with the 
exception of Iseeus, into two great parties—that of the patriots, 
who devoted themselves to the good work of denouncing Philip, 
and endeavouring to contravene his machinations, and that of the 
Macedonizers, who either corruptly, or from an unwise love of 
peace at any price, opposed all warlike and vigorous measures, 
and contributed to the downfal of their country’s honour and 
independence. 

The orators of the patriotic party, besides Demosthenes, 
who was the soul of the party, and his nephew Demo- 
chares, who maintained or revived it after his death, were 
Lycurgus, Hypereides, Polyeuctus,' Hegesippus,? Meerocles, 





1 There were two contemporary orators of this name, one of the demus Cydan- 
tide, who is known to us particularly in connexion with the newly-discovered frag- 


ments of Hypereides, and the other of the demus Sphettus, who is alluded to in the ἡ 


text, and whose speech against Demades is quoted by Longinus (EX..p. 544, Walz.). 
2 Hegesippus defended Timarchus against Aischines, who nicknamed him xpw- 


ISUS. 349 


Diophantus,’ Aristophon, and a number of others of less ability 
and influence. The orators of the Macedonian party, besides 
Aischines, who was their leader, were his original patron 
Eubulus, Philocrates, Demades,? and Deinarchus, and a number 
of less known demagogues. In selecting some names from this 
list for special notice, we may take the criterion of the Alex- 
andrian canon of the ten orators, which ranks Iszeus, Lycurgus, 
Hypereides, Aischines, and Deinarchus, with Antiphon, Lysias, 
Tsocrates, and Demosthenes. We shall thus have to discuss 
the teacher of Demosthenes, the two chief orators of his party, 
and his two principal antagonists. 

§ 2. Very little is known of the biography of Is#us, and we 
cannot even fix with accuracy the dates of his birth and death. 
All that we know is, that he flourished between the goth and 
108th Olympiads, B.c..420—348 : that either he or his father, 
Diagoras, was a native of Chalcis, in Eubcea ;* that he came to 
Athens at an early age, received instruction from Lysias and 
Isocrates,° and gained both reputation and profitable employ- 
ment as a teacher of rhetoric, and as a composer of speeches for 
the law courts. His chief distinction is the circumstance 
referred to in the preceding chapter, that he was the instructor 
of Demosthenes, and probably his counsel in the action against 
his guardians. Whether he may claim the additional merit of 
having trained this great pupil without receiving any remune- 
ration, or whether he exacted a very exorbitant fee for his 
lessons, is an open question in the ancient authors.° 

Iszeus left behind him 64 orations, and of these 50 were 





βύλος. The speeches about the Halonnesus, and on. the treaty with Alexander, 
which are included in the collection of the orations of Demosthenes, were probably 
by him : above, chapter XLI. § 2, p. 329 [169]. 

1 Diophantus is mentioned by Demosthenes as a very eminent orator (Fals. Leg. 
pp- 368, 403, 436; Περί. p. 498). 

2 This unprincipled demagogue was a man of brilliant abilities, and generally 
spoke extempore. The fragment of the speech, περὶ δωδεκαετίας, which is printed 
in the more recent collections of the Attic orators, is considered to be of doubtful 
authenticity. 

3 Dionys. Hal. de Isceo judicium, p. 586. Plut. p. 839. 

4 Harpocration s.v.*Icaios. Suidas 8, nm. Anonym. ap. Reisk. Dionys. p. 586. 

* Phot. cod. CCLXITII. 

§ Plutarch de glor. Athen. p. 350 c. Phot. uw. s. Plut. p. 839. Cf. 837 D. 
Suidas 8. x. : οὗτος ἐπαινεῖται καὶ ὡς ῥήτωρ καὶ ws Δημοσθένην ἀμισθὶ προαγαγών. 


850 ORATORS CONTEMPORARY WITH DEMOSTHENES. 


recognized as genuine.’ We have still the titles of 56, in- 
cluding the eleven which have come down to 8.5 All these 
extant speeches were composed for suits relating to inheritances 
(περὶ κλήρου), and they are interesting chiefly as contributions 
to our knowledge of the old Attic law on these points. Until 
the end of the last century we had only ten of the orations of 
Iszeus, and the speech about the inheritance of Cleonymus wanted 
more than half. The number of eleven speeches was made up 
by the discovery in the Laurentine library of the speech about 
the inheritance of Menicles,in 1785,‘ and the Cleonymus was 
completed by the publication, in 1815, of the greater part of 
this speech, which was found by Mai in the Ambrosian library 
at Milan.’ In addition to his speeches, Iseeus wrote a τέχνη, 
or methodical treatise on rhetoric, in which he has the credit 
of bemg the first to distinguish rightly the different figures, 
and to give a political turn to oratory.’ 

The style and characteristics of Iszeus have been accurately 
discussed by Dionysius of Halicarnassus in a special tract on 
the subject, in which he compares Iszeus with his teacher 
Lysias. He says’ that the diction of Iseus is more artificial 
and accurate than that of Lysias, the composition is more 
elaborate, the figures more varied, and it excels the style of 
his master in the power and weight of its phraseology as much 
as it falls short in ease and gracefulness. The style of Iszeus 
is in fact the fountain of the power of Demosthenes. In the 
subject-matter of Iszeus, the eritic finds a great deal of artifice. 
Dionysius remarks,’ that ‘he deals unfairly with his adversary, 





1 Plut. p. 839. 

2 See Westermann, Geschichte der Beredtsamkeit in Griechenland und Rom. p.293, 
Leipzig, 1833. 

3 With this view they were translated by Sir W. Jones. 

4 It was edited by Thomas Tyrwhitt, Lond. 1785. 

5 It was published at Milan in 1815. 

6 Plut. p. 839 F., quoted by Spengel, συναγωγὴ τεχνῶν, p. 181: καταλέλοιπε... 
καὶ ἰδίας τέχνας. “πρῶτος δὲ καὶ σχηματίζειν ἤρξατο καὶ τρέπειν ἐπὶ τὸ πολιτικὸν τὴν 
διάνοιαν, ὃ μάλιστα μεμίμηται Δημοσθένης. 

7 De Iso judicium, p. 590, Reiske: ἡ δὲ ᾿Ισαίου λέξις τεχνικωτέρα δόξειεν ἂν 
εἶναι καὶ ἀκριβεστέρα τῆς Λυσίου, τήν τε σύνθεσιν περιεργοτέρα τις καὶ σχηματι- 
σμοῖς διειλημμένη ποικίλοις" ὅσον τε ἀπολείπεται τῆς χάριτος ἐκείνης, τοσοῦτον ὑπερέχει 
τῇ δεινότητι THs κατασκευῆς" καὶ πηγή τις ὄντως ἐστὶ τῆς Δημοσθένους δυνάμεως. 

8 Tbid.1, 18: πρὸς μὲν τὸν ἀντίδικον διαπονηρεύεται" τοὺς δὲ δικάστας καταστρα- 


τηγεῖ. 


LYCURGUS. 351 


and out-manceuvres the jurymen.? And he informs us,’ that 
‘his contemporaries had conceived a suspicion of his cheatery 
and imposition, as though he were a man skilful in the artful 
perversion of arguments to the worst purposes, and he was 
inculpated on this account.’ The sort of deception practised 
by Iszeus, as contrasted with the elegant simplicity of Lysias, 
is illustrated by a very ingenious analogy. The style of Lysias 
is compared to the ancient paintings which have accurate 
drawing, but very little shading and colouring, whereas Iszeus 
is like the more modern pictures, which are not so well 
finished in the outline as their predecessors, but have a greater 
mixture of light and shade, and are more highly coloured. 
In proof of these discriminations, Dionysius gives us a number 
of examples.’ 

§ 3. Next to Demosthenes, the most honest, consistent, and 
efficient of the anti-Macedonian party was Lycureus. He was, 
indeed, rather a minister of finance than a parliamentary 
speaker ; but, by his incorruptible and scrupulous accuracy in 
his administration of the revenues, he gave new life to the 
resources of Athens, and rendered possible the execution of 
those vigorous measures which were recommended by the 
eloquence of his great contemporary. It was he, too, who, 
more than any, co-operated with Demosthenes in preventing the 
revenues, which were needed for the defence of the country, 
from being squandered on the amusement of the people ; and 
he, like Demosthenes, stood in constant opposition to reckless — 
and profligate demagogues, like their common enemy, Demades. 

No one could bring against Lycurgus the reproach so often 
flung against Demosthenes, that he was but half Athenian. 
His father, Lycophron, belonged to the deme of Butade, and 
to the priestly house of the Eteobutade, or genuine stock of 





1 De Isceo judicium, p. 591: ἣν περὶ αὐτοῦ δόξα τοῖς τότε γοητείας καὶ ἀπάτης, ὡς 
δεινὸς ἀνὴρ τεχνιτεῦσαι λόγους ἐπὶ τὰ πονηρότερα. 

2 Tbid..: εὔγραμμοι μὲν ἧττον ἐξειργασμέναι δὲ μᾶλλον σκίᾳ τε καὶ φωτὶ ποικιλλό- 
μεναι καὶ ἐν τῷ πλήθει τῶν μιγμάτων τὴν ἰσχὺν ἔχουσαι. 

8 It may be worth while ‘to mention that Juvenal’s ‘sermo promptus et Iseo 
torrentior’ (ITI. 73, 74) does not refer to our Attic orator, but ἐο ἃ later rhetorician 
from Assyria, who-was a contemporary of the Roman satirist. See Philostr. Vit. 
Sophist. I. 20; Plin. Epist. II. 3. : 


352 ORATORS CONTEMPORARY WITH DEMOSTHENES. 


Butes,' and traced back their descent to the national hero 
Erechtheus, probably another form of Poseidon or Neptune, to 
whom Lycurgus and his family were devoted as hereditary priests. - 
The walls of the Cella in the beautiful Erechtheum, or temple of 
Erechtheus-Poseidon, were adorned with pictures of the 
_ Butadz who had held the priestly office. Lycurgus left this 
priesthood to his son Abron, who resigned it to his brother 
Lycophron, and there was a highly finished picture by 
Ismenias in the Erechtheum, which represented Abron handing 
the trident or symbol of priestly power to his brother. The 
conduct of his ancestors was worthy of their origin. One of 
them, Lycomedes, had been buried at the public expense, and 
the orator’s grandfather, Lycophron, was one of the victims of 
the thirty tyrants. The birth-year of Lycurgus is not known. 
He was older than Demosthenes,’ and it is inferred that he 
was born in the 96th Olympiad, B.c. 396—393. He enjoyed 
au education corresponding to his birth and fortune. ‘ Lycurgus,’ 
says the most eloquent of his panegyrists,‘ ‘ had studied in the 
schools both of Plato and Isocrates, but had not learned from 
the one to withdraw from active life into a visionary world, nor 
from the other to cultivate empty rhetoric at the expense of 
truth, and of his country.’ Of the earlier part of his life we 
know nothing. There is insufficient evidence for the state- 
ment, not improbable in itself, that he was the colleague of 
Demosthenes and Polyeuctus in their embassy to the Pelopon- 
nesus, Ol. 109, 2, B.c. 3243. As we have already intimated, the 
public activity of Lycurgus was chiefly directed to the adminis- 
tration of the finances at home. Towards the end of Philip’s 





1 Butes, the Argonaut, who succeeded Pandion as priest of Athena and of 
Erechtheus Poseidon, is generally distinguished from his Thracian namesake ; but 
there are many points of contact between the Erechtheide and the house of 
Boreas, and we must not neglect the fact that the name Lycurgus, so common in 
the Butade, is that of the step-brother of the Thracian Butes. 

2 See F. Thiersch, diber das Erechtheum, Erste Abhandlung, p. 145 (Munich 
Transactions, vol. IIT). 

3 Liban. Arg. Orat. c. Aristogit. See Clinton, Fasti Hell. II. p. 151. 

4 Dr. Thirlwall, who has introduced into his History of Greece (VIII. pp. t40— 
148), an admirably written episode on the life of Lycurgus. 

5 Plutarch, Vit. Lyc. p. 841 Ἐπ Thisis probably borrowed from Dem. Phil, III. 
Ῥ. 129, 19, where the names of Clitomachus and Lycurgus are omitted in the best 
MSS. 





LYCURGUS. 353 


reign, he became ‘treasurer of the public revenue’ (ταμίας τῆς 
κοινῆς προσόδου), an office tenable only for a pentaeteris, or 
four years,’ but held by Lycurgus, under the names of other 
persons, for three successive pentaeterids, or twelve years.’ 
The period occupied by this financial administration has been 
made the subject of discussion among scholars.* If he was 
ambassador in B.c. 343, the most probable interval, as he died 
before B.c. 326, would be Ol. 109, 3—112, 3, B.C. 341-420. 
In this period 1400c, or as some say, 19000 talents passed 
through his hands, and he raised the regular revenue of Athens 
from 600 to 1200 talents. At the end of each quadriennial period 
he gave in an account of his receipts and expenditure, and no flaw 
was found in it. Not satisfied with this, he had his accounts en- 
graved on stone, and set up the inscription in the Palestra, which 
he had recently erected. It seems probable that a fragment of this 
inscription is still extant.‘ Just before his death he had himself 
carried into the Metroum or Council-chamber, and challenged a 
scrutiny of his whole administration ; and when Meneseechmus, 
whom he had once prosecuted, attempted to make exceptions, he 
at once refuted all his charges.’ Of his measures for nursing the 
reyenue we have no account. With regard to the expenditure 
which he directed, we learn that, besides building four hundred 
triremes, and forming a great magazine of arms, he erected a 
theatre, a gymnasium, a palestra, and a stadium. He also, in 
imitation of Pericles, filled the store-room in the citadel with a 
number of gold and silver ornaments and utensils, which were in 
effect a reserved fund for emergencies. 

Plutarch enumerates five laws of which Lycurgus was the pro- 





1 Bickh, Public Econ. of Athens, ΤΙ. ὃ 6. p. 165, Lewis. . 

5 Plut. p. 852 B, quotes a decree in which Lycurgus is described as γενόμενος 
τῆς κοινῆς προσόδου ταμίας τῇ πόλει ἐπὶ τρεῖς wevraernplias, Diod. XVI. 88, 
Says: δώδεκα ἔτη τὰς προσόδους τῆς πόλεως διοικήσας. 

3 See Bickh, Staatshaushaltung, II. p. 245, orig. ed. and the authors cited by 
Westermann, Geschichte d. Beredtsamkeit, p. 101, and in Pauly’s Real-Encyclopddie, 
vol. IV. p. 1269. See also Dr. Thirlwall’s note, p. 146. 

* Bickh, Corpus Inscriptionwm, no. 157. It refers to the years of Ctesicles and 
Nicocrates, Ol. 111. 3, 4, B.C. 334, 333, Which fell within the administration of 
Lycurgus, and mentions particularly the δερματικόν, for which Harpocration cites 
the defence of Lycurgus against the cavils of Meneseachmus, 

5. Plutarch, p. 842 F, 

Vou. II. AA 


354 ORATORS CONTEMPORARY WITH DEMOSTHENES. 


poser: (I.) To revive the obsolete contest of the comedians at the 
Chytri, on the third day of the Anthesteria, with the additional re- 
gulation that the victor should, without any further trial (ἄκριτος), 
be admitted to the competition at the great Dionysia.’ (II.) That 
bronze statues should be erected to the three great tragedians, 
fEschylus, Sophocles, and Euripides; and that authenticated 
copies of their plays should be laid up in the public archives, 
and strictly followed in the public representations. Ptolemy 
Euergetes dishonestly possessed himself of these original manu- 
scripts, for which, however, he had to forfeit a deposit of 
fifteen talents? If it had not been for this enactment of 
Lycurgus, it is probable that the text of the Greek dramatists 
would have been much more corrupt than it is. (III.) That, 
to prevent the kidnapping of free citizens; no one should buy a 
slave without the warranty and authorization of a former 
master.’ (IV.) To establish in honour of his family god, 
Poseidon, at least three cyclical choruses in the Peirzeus ; and to 
give to the victors not less than ten minz as a prize, besides 
second and third prizes of eight and six mine. (V.) To punish 
with a penalty of six thousand drachmee any woman who drove 
to the Eleusinian festival in a chariot and pair :* it appears 
that his own wife, Callisto, transgressed this law, and was fined 
accordingly.’ If we understand the notice in Plutarch, he held 
some office analogous to that of a police magistrate,’ and in 
this capacity exhibited no little vigour and severity. As a 
public accuser, too, he often appeared in the courts; and at 





1 There is some obscurity in the short notice of Plutarch [?], p. 841 F: τὸν περὶ 
τῶν κωμῳδῶν ἀγῶνα Tots Χύτροις ἐπιτελεῖν ἐφάμιλλον ἐν τῷ θεάτρῳ καὶ τὸν νικήσαντα 
εἰς ἄστυ καταλέγεσθαι πρότερον οὐκ ἐξόν, ἀναλαμβάνων τὸν ἀγῶνα ἐκλελοιπότα. By 
ἄστυ he must mean τὰ ἐν ἄστει Διονύσια. The practice referred to is probably 
that explained explained in Photius, Suidas, Hesychius, s.v. νεμήσεις ὑποκριτῶν. 

2 See Béckh, Gr. Trag. Princ. pp. 12, 13. 

3 This must be the meaning of the words of Plutarch, which again are somewhat 
obscure from their brevity (p. 842 A): μηδενὶ ἐξεῖναι ᾿Αθηναίων μηδὲ τῶν οἰκούντων 
᾿Αθήνησιν ἐλεύθερον σῶμα πρίασθαι ἐπὶ δουλείᾳ ἐκ τῶν ἁλισκομένων ἄνευ τῆς τοῦ 
προτέρου δεσπότου γνώμης. 

4 In illustration of this see Dem. σ, Mid.p. 565. 

5 Alian, V. H. XIII. 24. 

8 p. 841 D: ἔσχε δὲ καὶ τοῦ ἄστεος τὴν φυλακὴν Kal τῶν κακούργων Thy σύλληψιψ 
ods ἐξήλασεν ἅπαντας, ὡς καὶ τῶν σοφιστῶν ἐνίους λέγειν Λυκοῦργον οὐ μέλανι ἀλλὰ 
θανάτῳ χρίοντα τὸν κάλαμον κατὰ τῶν πονηρῶν οὕτω συγγράφειν. 


LYCURGUS. 355 


least in two cases—those of Leocrates and Diphilus—he ob- 
tained a sentence of death against notorious offenders. He 
was sufficiently known as a member of the anti-Macedonian 
party to obtain the perilous honour of being included with 
Demosthenes in Alexander’s demand for the extradition of 
certain orators, a danger which the firmness of his coun- 
trymen enabled him to escape.’ The year of his death is not 
known, but he did not survive the downfal of the patriotic party. 
For Plutarch tells us that he was not alive when Hypereides 
accused Demosthenes in the business of Harpalus,’ and it seems 
extremely probable that Lycurgus died soon after the termina- 
tion of his third quadriennial service as public treasurer—i. e. 
in B.c. 329 or 328. He was buried at the public expense on 
the road to the Academy, on the spot which was afterwards 
occupied by the garden of the philosopher Melanthius.* In 
his lifetime he had often been honoured with crowns, statues, 
and a seat in the town-hall, and the last privilege was made 
hereditary in his family. He left three sons, Abron, Lycurgus, 
and Lycophron, of whom the first two died without issue, but 
the third was represented by lineal descendants to a later 
period.” A statue in honour of Lycurgus was erected some 
time after his death (in B.c. 307) near those of the ten Eponymi 
in the market-place.® 

Of the twenty speeches of this eminent statesman, of which 
the titles are preserved, we have only one complete oration, 
that against the fugitive Leocrates, who had returned to Athens 
eight years after the battle of Cheroneia, when he had forsaken 
his country, although by a law, passed immediately after the 
battle, emigration was forbidden under pain of death. This 
speech is in strict accordance with all that we know of the 
character and habits of Lycurgus. We are told’ that he was 
very diligent in preparing his speeches, and not able to express 
himself extempore ; and so anxious was he to note his thoughts 





1 Arrian, I. το, 4; Diodor. XVII, 15. 

2 Plut. Vita Hyperid. p. 848 F. 

3 See Plut. Vita Lyc. p. 842 F. It is inferred also that as his sons were released 
from prison on the intercession of Demosthenes who was then in exile, that 
Lycurgus must have been dead some little time. 

4 Plut. p. 842 E. 5 Td. p. 843 A. 

6 Td. p. 852 B; Pausan. I. 8, 2. 7 Plutarch, p. 842 C. 

AA 2 


356. ORATORS CONTEMPORARY WITH DEMOSTHENES. 


as they occurred to him that his writing materials were always 
placed by his bed-side. We see the traces of this elaborate 
preparation in the speech against Leocrates, which is full of 
historical reading and poetical quotations, the latter sometimes 
running to a considerable length.’ And we have no doubt that 
Hermogenes was justified in saying of all his speeches that he 
often indulges in a frequency of digressions to fables, histories, - 
and poems.? One of the most pleasing of his references to old 
stories is the anecdote which he tells of the young man who 
stayed behind to carry off his old father during an eruption of 
Mount AXtna, and round whom the lava flowed innocuously, 
while it destroyed the other fugitives.* There is almost a 
Demosthenic vigour in the passage in which he describes the 
trembling inquiries of the women and the old men preparing 
for the defence of the city after the disaster of Chzeroneia,* and 
that in which he checks any appeal to pity on the part of the 
accused.” On the whole, although we cannot place Lycurgus 
in the first rank of orators, we may regret that we have not a 
few more specimens of the compositions of such an eminent 
and popular statesman. 

§ 4. Closely connected in his general policy with Lycurgus 
and Demosthenes, though occasionally opposed to one or the 
other, Hyreripes, or Hyrererpss,’ the son of Glaucippus,’ of — 
















1 There are fifty-five lines of Euripides quoted in p. 161, and thirty-two of Tyr- 
teus in p. 163. The quotation from the unknown poet in p. 159, belongs to a 
numerous class of passages embodying the sentiment quem Deus vult perdere 
dementat prius. See Wyttenb. on Plut. de audiendis poetis, p. 17 B; Ruhnken on 
Vell. Patere. IT. 57. 

2 περὶ ἰδεῶν, ΤΙ. 11, p. 389, Walz: χρῆται δὲ πολλαῖς πολλάκις Kal ταῖς παρεκ- 
βάσεσιν ἐπὶ μύθους καὶ ἱστορίας καὶ ποιήματα. Lycurgus is quite conscious of this 
tendency. In one passage, he begins a lengthened reference to the old mythology 
of Athens, by saying: καί τοι σκέψασθε, ὦ ἄνδρες" οὐ γὰρ ἀποστήσομαι τῶν παλαιῶν. 
οπδιονωδα Hoes abo. 3 p. 159. 

4 p. 153, ὃ 40. There is something very vivid in the picture of the veterans ἐπὶ 
γήρως 609 περιφθειρομένους, διπλᾶ τὰ ἱμάτια ἐμπεπορπημένους. ᾿ 

5 p. 168, § 147. 

6 The name is written Ὑπερείδης in some of the best MSS. of Demosthenes, de 
Corond, p. 302, 26 ; Fals. Leg. 376, 17. The grammarians give us both ‘Ywrepidns 
from Ὕπερος, like Ὑλλίδης from Ὕλλος (Etym. M. s.v.), and Ὑπερείδης from 
Ὑπερεύς, like Πηλείδης from ἸΤηλεύς (Phrynichus, p. 454, Lobeck). Both as 
common word and as a proper name Uzepos is the more common. 

7 Hypereides had a son, Glaucippus, who obtained some reputation as a ἀν speaker, 





HYPEREIDES. 3857 


the demus Collytus, was one of the active leaders in that anti- 
Macedonian patriotism, to which he was ultimately a martyr. 
The year of his birth is not known, but it is probable that he 
was not much younger than Lycurgus. Plutarch indeed says 
that he was a hearer (axpoarnc) of Lycurgus, but this must be 
-a mistake, unless he means that he heard him speak in public, 
for that great financier was not a teacher of rhetoric. There is 
every reason, however, to believe that he was a fellow-pupil of 
Lycurgus as a disciple of Plato and Isocrates.' He seems to have 
belonged to the more opulent class, for he not only enjoyed the 
best education, but appears to have been able to contribute in the 
most munificent manner to the public expenditure of his country. 
For example, in the year B.c. 358 he got up, by public sub- 
scription, an equipment of forty triremes for the war against 
Philip in Eubcea, and undertook himself the fitting out of two 
of these ships, one in his own name, the other in that of his 
son ;* and when he served as trierarch at Byzantium in B.c. 
340, he bore the expenses of the Choragia in his absence.’ 
Notwithstanding his opulence, he was for some years en 
gaged as a writer of speeches in private causes. His public 
services were as follows :—In B.c. 351 he undertook an embassy 
to Rhodes ;* in B.c. 346 he successfully prosecuted the venal 
and traitorous Philocrates;° when Philip occupied Elatea in 
B.C. 338 he was one of the ambassadors who persuaded the 
Thebans to join with Athens against the invader ;° and after 
the battle of Chzeroneia he proposed the high-spirited decree to 
give the franchise to the resident aliens, to restore the degraded, 
to manumit the slaves, and send down the women, children, and 
sacred objects to the Peirzeus.’ This decree was not carried out, 
but was so far approved as to give the sycophant Aristogeiton a 
pretext for indicting him for unconstitutional proceedings (7apa- 
νόμων). He was acquitted; and it was on this occasion that, 





1 The statement of Plutarch will simply amount to this, if we read (p. 848 D): 
ἀκροατὴς δὲ Ἡλάτωνος γενόμενος τοῦ φιλοσόφου ἅμα Λυκούργῳ (for Λυκούργου), καὶ 
᾿Ισοκράτους τοῦ ῥήτορος. ᾿ 

2 Plutarch, p. 849 F. 3 Td. p. 848-E. 4 Id. p. 850 A. 

5 Demosth. de Falsdé Leg. p. 376, 17. 6 Id. de Corond, p. 291, 6. 


7 Lycurg. c. Leocratem, ὃ 41; Plut. p. 848 F, 849 A; Pseudo-Dem. c. Aristog. 
II. p. 803. 


358 ORATORS CONTEMPORARY WITH DEMOSTHENES. 


being charged with having overlooked many of the established 
laws, he said, ‘My eyes were darkened with the shadow of the 
Macedonian arms; it was not I who wrote the decree, but the 
battle at Cheroneia.’’ His active opposition to Macedon never 
ceased, and he was one of the orators demanded by Alexander 
after the capture of Thebes. This peril, which he narrowly 
escaped, did not damp his patriotic ardour, for we find that he 
opposed Alexander’s demand for an Athenian fleet to help him 
against the Persians.?, The unfortunate affair of Harpalus seems 
to have obliged Hypereides to come forward as the accuser of 
Demosthenes, for whom he had once obtained a golden crown.’ 
We do not know all the circumstances. Plutarch imtimates 
that he was publicly appointed to this invidious office, because 
he was the only orator not suspected of being bribed.* As 
Demosthenes was allowed to escape, it is not impossible that 
the whole proceeding was a collusion devised by the patriots to 
enable them to temporize with Macedon. Be this as it may, 
we find Hypereides warmly united with Demosthenes in the 
prosecution of the Lamian war.’ He was one of the most 
active agents in stimulating that hopeful insurrection against 
the Macedonian domination, and was selected to deliver the 
funeral oration in honour of those who fell with the valiant 
Leosthenes.° _ When the battle of Crannon, in B. ©. 322, over- 
threw the last hopes of Athenian independence, Hypereides was 
obliged to fly from Athens with the other proscribed orators. 
He took refuge with Aristonicus and Himereeus, in the shrine 
of Aiacus in Aigina, whence he was torn by Archias and sent as a 
prisoner to Antipater, by whom he was put to death with cir- 
cumstances of great cruelty and brutality.’ 

The titles of sixty-one orations, attributed to Hypereides, 
were preserved by the ancient authorities, who tell us that of 
seventy-seven speeches which bore his name, fifty-two were 





1 Plut. p. 849 A: ‘ ἐπεσκότει,᾽ ἔφη “μοι τὰ Μακεδόνων ὅπλα᾽ καὶ οὐκ ἐγὼ τὸ 


ψήφισμα ἔγραψα, ἡ δ᾽ ἐν Χαιρωνείᾳ μάχη. 
2 Plut. p. 848 D; cf. 847 C. 3 See Dem. de Corond, p. 302. 
4 p. 848 E: μόνος yap ἔμεινεν ἀδωροδόκητος. 
5 Plut. Phocion, c. 23; X. Orat. p. 848 Εἰ, 849 F; Justin, XIII. 5. 
6. Diodor. XVIII. 3. 
7 Plut. Dem. c. 28; Phocion, 29; X. Orat. 849 C; Photius, p. 496; <a 
Hist. of Greece, XII. p. 440. 


HYPEREIDES. 359 


genuine.’ Till within the last few years, fortune had dealt 
more roughly with his remains than with those of any one of 
the ten orators; for while even Lycurgus and Deinarchus are 
represented by one or more complete harangues, Hypereides 
was lost altogether, with the exception of a number of frag- 
ments which were individually of little importance.? The 
present generation has been permitted to rehabilitate him in 
Greek literature. In the spring of 1847, Mr. A. C. Harris of 
Alexandria found some fragments of papyrus, written over with 
Greek characters, at Thebes in Upper Egypt, and published 
them in a lithographed facsimile in the autumn of 1848. An . 
arrangement and translation of these fragments was communi- 
cated to the London Philological Society in February, 1849, 
by Mr. Samuel Sharpe ;* but though Mr. Harris had suggested 
that the fragments probably belonged to the speech of Hype- 
reides against Demosthenes in the matter of Harpalus, Mr. 
Sharpe seemed rather to think that they belonged to some rhe- 
torical exercise on the subject. Mr. Churchill Babington, in 
November, 1849, made a communication to the Royal Society 
of Literature, in which he showed that these fragments were 
quoted by Harpocration, Photius, and Suidas, and that they 
must. be considered as belonging to the genuine oration of 
Hypereides; and at the beginning of 1850 she published a 
learned edition of these remains, with an introduction and com- 
mentary.’ They had been previously edited, but without Mr. 
Babington’s knowledge, by Bockh and Sauppe. These pieces 
of papyrus, though interesting in themselves, were chiefly 
valuable because they led to the publication of another manu- 
script of the same kind, which Mr. Joseph Arden had procured 
at the same place in January, 1847. Some of the fragments 
discovered by Mr. Harris evidently did not belong to the 
speech against Demosthenes, and it turned out that they were 





1 Plutarch, p. 849 D; Phot. p. 495 B; Westermann, Gesch. d. Beredtsamkeit, 
p- 307, gives a list of all the titles. 

2 See Kiessling, De Hyperide Comment. II. Hildburgh. 1837. 

3 Proceedings of the Philological Society, vol. IV. no. 79. 

4 The Oration of Hyperides against Demosthenes respecting the treaswre of Har- 
palus; with a preliminary Dissertation and Notes, and a facsimile of a portion of 
the MS. By Churchill Babington, M.A., Fellow of St. John’s College, Cam- 
bridge, 1850. 


360 ORATORS CONTEMPORARY WITH DEMOSTHENES. 


a portion of the speech of Hypereides for Lycophron, of which 
Mr. Arden secured fifteen continuous columns. And the 
same papyrus contained the complete oration of Hypereides for 
Euxenippus. These remains were published by Mr. Churchill 
Babington, with a facsimile of the original manuscript and a 
learned commentary, in the spring of 1853 ;' shortly after- 
wards the late Professor Schneidewin of Gottingen edited them 
in a revised text, with critical notes, and prefixed the Harrisian 
fragments of the apology for Lycophron ;* and since then Mr. 
Babington has discovered the funeral oration of Hypereides, 
nearly complete, among some papyri lately purchased by the 
British Museum.* We are thus enabled to deal with Hyper- 
eides as an extant Greek author, and to estimate his title to 
a place among the ten orators. . 

The fragments of the speech against Demosthenes are not 
sufficiently complete to furnish the materials of a literary criti- 
cism, but the other fragments, published by Mr. Babington, 
furnish a good example of the style of Hypereides, and quite 





1 The Orations of Hyperides for Lycophron and Euxenippus, now first printed in 
facsimile; with a short account of the discovery of the original MS. at Western 
Thebes, in Upper Egypt, in 1847, by Joseph Arden, Esq.: the text edited, with 
Notes and Illustrations, by the Rev. Churchill Babington, Cambridge, 1853. 

2 Hyperidis Orationes due ex papyro Ardeniano edite ; post Ch. Babingtonem, 
emendavit et scholia adjecit F. G. Schneidewin, Gotting., 1853. 

3 The papyrus was brought from Egypt by Mr. Stodart, in 1856. Mr. Babing- 
ton has given an account of it in the Cambridge Journal of Classical and Sacred 
Philology, No. X. p. 81, and he has favoured us with the following notice of the 
rediscovered speech, which he is about to edit:—‘The ἐπιτάφιος was delivered 
towards the close of the year 323 B.c. over Leosthenes and his comrades who fell 
in the Lamian war. Hyperides was appointed as the orator on this occasion by a 
public vote. Not only is a long fragment of his speech preserved by Stobzeus, but 
a considerable part, possibly the greater part, exists in MS. in the British 
Museum, written on a very early papyrus, apparently of the second or third cen- 
tury after Christ, and brought from Egypt in 1856. The topics of praise in his 
oration are threefold: the city, the deceased warriors, and their general Leosthenes. 
He enlarges much on the bravery, tactics and policy of Leosthenes, and introduces, 
in the course of his remarks, various historical allusions to the Lamian war. 
Further on he apostrophizes the deceased soldiers, who have filled all Greece with 
their glory, and whose memory will be recalled by every scene of public and social 
life. The epilogus (preserved by Stobeus) is designed to comfort the survivors, 
and expresses a hope, though neither sure nor certain, that the departed warriors 
are still in being and in enjoyment of a blessed immortality. This oration was 
considered by the ancients to be one of the happiest productions of Hyperides,’ 


HYPEREIDES. 361 


justify the account which the ancients have given us of his 
peculiar characteristics. 

The accuser of Lycophron was no less a person than Lycurgus, 
who brought an εἰσαγγελία, or special impeachment,’ against him, 
for adultery and other crimes, and fragments are still extant of 
his two orations on the subject; the first, to which answer is 
made in the speech which Hypereides composed to be spoken 
by the defendant, and which procured a conviction; and the 
second, in which the damages were discussed. From the men- 
tion of Dioxippus,’ the celebrated wrestler, who died in B.c. 326,° 
but was in the prime of life when this oration was delivered, it 
is inferred that it was written quite at the beginning of Alex- 
ander’s reign. 

In the oration for Euxenippus, which is probably of about the 
same date as that for Lycophron,* Hypereides speaks in his own 
person, and as the second advocate for the defendant, who has 
also two accusers, Polyeuctus of Cydantidee—not the well-known 
orator of Sphettus, but a man of some consideration at Athens’ 
—and Lycurgus. In this case also Hypereides had to answer 
an εἰσαγγελία, and one of his arguments is, that this form of 
proceeding is not applicable to such a frivolous charge brought 
against a private individual.’ The case arose out of the assign- 
ment to Athens, after the battle of Cheroneia, of the territory 
of Oropus. ‘This territory consisted of five hills (ὄρη), of which 
each was assigned by lot to two Athenian tribes. The hill which 
thus fell to the tribes Acamantis and Hippothoontis was claimed 





1 The εἰσαγγελία was adopted in the case of undefined and extraordinary offences 
against the public (κυρίως ἡ περὶ καινῶν καὶ δημοσίων ἀδικημάτων εἰσωγομένη δίκη 
ὑπὸ τῶν ἸΤρυτανέων, Suidas), It was a favourite mode of proceeding with Lycurgus, 
who adopted it against Leocrates, and was recommended by the advantage that it 
did not bring any penalty on the unsuccessful prosecutor. Hypereides himself 
availed himself of this process in his impeachment of Philocrates and Diopeithes 
(pro Euxenipp. col. 39). 

2 Col. 5. 

8 Athenzus, VI. c. 57 (I. p. 546, Dindorf.), Curtius, IX. 29, quoted by Babing- 
ton, p. XIV. 

4 The manner, in which Olympias and Alexander are mentioned together (col. 
31), points to the beginning of Alexander’s reign. 

® Schneidewin p. 34. In col. 27 Polyeuctus is addressed as ὃς οὐ μόνον ὑπὲρ 
σεαυτοῦ δύνασαι εἰπεῖν ἀλλὰ Kal ὅλῃ πόλει πράγματα παρέχειν ἱκανὸς el. 

§ Col. 18. 


362 ORATORS CONTEMPORARY WITH DEMOSTHENES. 


for the hero Amphiaraus ; and, to quiet all doubts on the subject, 
Euxenippus and two others were deputed to sleep in the temple 
of Amphiaraus at Oropus, in the hope of being favoured with a 
dream in reference to the claims of the oracular hero. It seems 
that they reported a vision unfavourable to the occupation of the 
consecrated hill by the two tribes. Whereupon Polyeuctus pro- 
posed that the other eight tribes should make compensation 
for the loss. This proposition was rejected, and its proposer 
fined twenty-five drachme. Polyeuctus endeavoured to avenge 
himself on the reporter of the dream by indicting him for a false 
and suborned account of his vision, and, as usual in such cases, 
he rakes up a number of other matters against him, especially 
with reference to some dealings in the silver mines. The co- 
operation of Lycurgus was probably secured by the charge of 
Macedonizing, which is brought against Euxenippus, because he 
had aided Olympias in the dedication of a patera in the temple 
of health at Athens. 

If we compare these orations with the criticisms of the 
ancients, we shall find that they justify the favourable expecta- 
tions which we were induced to form respecting this orator. 
Cicero calls him a highly finished speaker,’ and says that he 
was acute,’ subtle,* and facetious.’ Quintilian’ defines him as 
pleasant and acute, but better suited to conduct causes of 
inferior importance. Dionysius declares® that in cunning irony 
he was unrivalled, that he sticks to the necessary points before 
him, that he is full of pleasantness, and that while he seems to 
be simple he is not deficient in power; and his chief pecu- 
liarities are said to be’ strength of diction, simplicity of com- 





1 De Oratore, I. 13, 58: ‘ perfectus in dicendo et perpolitus.’ 

2 Ibid. III. 7, 28: ‘acumen habuit.’ 

ὁ. Brutus, τῇ, 67: ‘delectantur e& subtilitate quam Atticam sppolland-+ii ie 
ride volunt esse et βαρεῖ Laudo.’ 

4 Orator. 26, 90: ‘satis in orationibus facetus.’ 

5 J. O. X. 1, 77: ‘dulcis in primis et acutus Hyperides, sed minoribus causis ut 
non dixerim utilior, magis par.’ 

6 De vet. Script. cens. Ὁ. 434, Reiske: τῇ τῆς εἰρωνείας πανουργίᾳ πάντας (ὑπερ- 
npka@s), ἔτι δὲ τοῦ κρινομένου διαπαντὸς ἔχεται, καὶ ταῖς ἀνάγκαις τοῦ πράγματος 
ἐμπέφυκε καὶ συνέσει πολλῇ κεχορήγηται, καὶ χαριτὸς μεστός ἐστιν" καὶ δοκῶν ἁπλοῦς 
οὐκ ἀπήλλακται δεινότητος. 

7 Id. ibid. p. 643: τὰ μέγιστα ἴδια τῆς μὲν λέξεως τὸ ἰσχυρόν, τῆς δὲ συνθέσεως τὸ 
ἁπλοῦν, τῶν δὲ πραγμάτων τὸ εὔκαιρον, τῆς δὲ κατασκευῆς τὸ μὴ τραγικὸν μηδὲ ὀγκῶδες, 








ZESCHINES. 363 


position, propriety in the selection of his subject-matter, and 
the absence of all pomposity in his language. And Longinus 
dwells' emphatically on his mastery of sarcasm, irony, and well- 
bred facetiousness. All these characteristics may be exemplified 
-in the orations. For example, there could not be ἃ better 
instance of sarcasm than his rebuff to Polyeuctus: ‘ If you had 
been acquitted, my client would not have given a false report 
about the god; but since it so happened that you were con- 
victed, Euxenippus must needs be ruined!” The private cha- 
racter of Hypereides was by no means irreproachable. His 
love for the beautiful was by no means abstract or Platonic, 
and the most famous hetere of the day counted the orator 
amoung their lovers.* There is a story that when his eloquence 
failed to defend the beautiful Phryne from a charge of impiety, 
he moved the hearts of the heliastz by an appeal to her charms.* 
He was also a noted epicure, and the comic poets ridiculed his 
fondness for expensive dishes of fish.’ 

ὃ 5. By far the most eminent of the Macedonian party was 
ZEscHineEs, who, in some qualifications, did not fall far short of 
his great rival Demosthenes.’ He was born B.c. 389.’ His 
origin and early history are presented to us under very different 
aspects by Demosthenes and himself. The former, in a burst 
of invective, to which we have already referred,* declares that 
the father of Aischines, originally called Tromes, but styled 
Atrometus by his son, was the worthless slave of a poor school- 
master, and afterwards kept a small school himself; and that 
his mother, originally called Empusa, the hobgoblin, but digni- 





1 De Sublim. 34, p. 284, Spengel: ἄφατοι rept αὐτόν εἰσιν doretcpol. μυκτὴρ πολι- 
τικώτατος, εὐγένεια, TO κατὰ τὰς εἰρωνείας εὐπάλαιστρον, σκώμματα οὐκ ἄμουσα, δια- 
συρμός τε ἐπιδέξιος, καὶ πολὺ τὸ κωμικὸν, καὶ, μετὰ παιδιᾶς εὐστόχου κέντρον, ἀμίμητον 
δὲ εἰπεῖν τὸ ἐν πᾶσι τούτοις ἐπαφρόδιτον. 

2 Col. 30: εἶτ᾽ εἰ μὲν ἀπέφυγες τὴν γραφήν, οὐκ ἂν μὐδιϑύοῤσατο οὗτος τοῦ θεοῦ, 
ἐπειδὴ δὲ συνέβη σοι ἁλῶναι, Εὐξένιππον δεῖ ἀπολωλέναι. 

8. Alciphron Ep. I. 30—32. 

4 This story is best told in the supplement to Barthélémy’s Anacharse, entitled 
Fétes et Courtisanes de la Gréce, Paris, 1801, vol. LV. p. 188. 

5 Timocles, apud Athen. VIII. 341 F, 342 A. 

® Dionys. Hal. De adm. vi dic. in Dem. p. 1063. Cic. Orat. 9, 29. ὁ 

7 In his speech against Timarchus, p. 78, which was delivered in B.0. 345, he 
says that he was then in his forty-fifth year. 

8 De Corond, p. 270, above, chapter X LI. § 6. 


364 ORATORS CONTEMPORARY WITH DEMOSTHENES. 


fied by her son with the majestic name Glaucothea, was the 
cast-off concubine of a galley-piper, who afterwards became a 
Bacchanalian priestess of the lowest class ; and we are told that 
Zschines in his early life assisted in the humble and degrading 
occupations of both his parents.’ In his speech on the Embassy,’ 
“Eschines lays claim to the most creditable antecedents in all 
respects. Pointing to his father, who was present, as nearly 
the oldest of the Athenian citizens, having attained the advanced 
age of ninety-four years, he tells his hearers that Atrometus, 
before he lost his property, was an athlete or competitor in the 
public games; and that after his banishment by the Thirty he 
served as a mercenary soldier in Asia. He asserts that the 
family belonged to the clan of the Eteobutade, which counted 
Lycurgus among its members, and that his father enjoyed the 
more substantial credit of assisting Thrasybulus to restore the 
democracy at Athens. His mother, too, who had shared in 
her husband’s exile, was originally and properly called Glaucis 
or Glaucothea,’ being the daughter of a respectable Athenian 
citizen, Glaucias of Acharne. The respectability of the family 
is farther attested by the fact that his brothers, Philochares 
and Aphobetus—whose name, by the way, seems to show that 
‘the father was really called Atrometus, and not Tromes‘—had 
filled very eminent positions in the military and civil service 
of their country. The former had served with distinction under 
Iphicrates, and had been thrice elected to the office of general, 
i.e. one of the ten commissioners for ‘managing the war 
ministry at Athens. The latter had gone as ambassador to 
Persia, and had held some financial appointment at Athens.’ 
With regard to himself, Aischines tells us that he served in 
the army from his earliest youth, first as one of the περίπολοι 
or patrols, who guarded the frontiers, and afterwards as a pro- 
bationary or supplementary soldier in foreign expeditions.’ In 





1 De Corond, p. 313. 3. p.47. 

3 Libanius calls her Leucothea. See Taylor, Pref. ad Asch. Epist. p. 653 sq. 

4 In his speech on the Embassy, p. 431 Demosthenes is content to define his 
opponent as τὸν ᾿Ατρομήτου τοῦ γραμματιστοῦ καὶ Τλαυκοθέας τῆς τοὺς θιάσους cuva- 
γούσης. 

5. Asch. De F. Leg. p. 48. 

5 Id. ibid. p. 50: πρώτην δ᾽ ἐξελθὼν στρατείαν τὴν ἐν τοῖς μέρεσι καλουμένην... 








. ZESCHINES. 365 


this way he fought at Phlius in B.c. 368, and at Mantincia in 
B.c. 362. And in the battle of Tamyne in Eubeea, in B.c. 349, 
he exhibited such conspicuous valour that he was crowned on 
the field by Phocion, and sent to announce the victory at 
Athens. With all this, his means were very limited, and he 
was obliged to maintain himself by turning his natural advan- 
tages to the best. account. Having a robust and active frame,’ 
he was employed to assist in the exercises of the gymnasia ;? and 
as his voice was powerful and harmonious, he found employment 
as a tragic actor, though he did not rise to the highest rank in 
the histrionic art,* and on one occasion was hissed off the 
stage in the character of Ginomaus.* Having acquired, either 
in his father’s writing-school or elsewhere, a great command of 
his pen, he was employed as a public clerk or secretary, and in 
this capacity he served first Aristophon,’ and afterwards Eubulus,° 
to whose party he was afterwards attached as an orator. So 
far as this, there may have been sufficient foundation for the 
personalities of Demosthenes. But there can scarcely be any 
doubt that the aspersions in the oration on the Crown, which 
go much farther than those in the speech on the Embassy, are 





καὶ ras ἄλλας τὰς ἐκ διαδοχῆς ἐξόδους τὰς ἐν rots ἐπωνύμοις καὶ τοῖς μέρεσιν ἐξῆλθον. 
The phrase ἐν τοῖς μέρεσιν is explained to mean ‘in the safe parts of the battle,’ 
ὦ. 6., in the rear ranks of the phalanx. Suidas, s. v., rep@pela: ὅτι ἔθος ἣν τοὺς 
ἐφήβους μετὰ τὸ γενέσθαι περιπόλους τῆς χώρας στρατεύεσθαι μὲν εἰ συμβαίη πόλεμος, 
μὴ μέντοι μετὰ τῶν ἄλλων, ἀλλ᾽ ἰδίᾳ ἐν μέρεσι τοῖς ἀκινδύνοις τῆς μάχης. The 
στρατεία ἐν τοῖς ἐπωνύμοις refers to the practice of counting the years of military 
service from eighteen to sixty by the names of the ἄρχοντες ἐπώνυμοι of the forty- 
two years, and then selecting soldiers for special expeditions from a certain num- 
ber of years. This appears from the passage of Aristotle quoted by Suidas, s. νυ. 
στρατεία ἐν τοῖς ἐπωνύμοις (p. 3416 B. Gaisford) : ὅταν ἡλικίαν ἐκπέμπωσιν, προσ- 
γράφουσιν ἀπὸ τίνος "Αρχοντος ᾿Επωνύμου μέχρι τίνος δεῖ στρατεύεσθαι. 

1 He seems, however, to have been of short stature. Demosthenes calls him 
καλὸς ἀνδριάς, which implies a doll or puppet (see our note on the Theatre of the 
Greeks, ed. 6, p. 161), and the phrase ἔσα βαίνων Ἰτυθοκλεῖ (Dem. Fals. Leg. p. 442) 
has more point, if we understand it of a diminutive person walking stride for stride 
with one much taller. Ulpian says expressly that Auschines was a little man (ad 
Or. de Cor. 1. 1.). 

2 Plut. p. 840 A: νέος δὲ ὧν καὶ ἐῤῥωμένος τῷ σώματι περὶ ra γυμνάσια ἐπόνει. 

3 He was generally τριταγωνιστής. Dem, De Corond, pp. 270, 315. 

4 Dem. De Corond, pp. 288, 314, 315. 

5 Anonym. Vita. dischinis, p. 245. 

6 Photius Cod. LXI. For the intimacy between Auschines and Eubulus, and 
the relations of the former to Aristophon, see Dem. Fals. Leg. p. 434. 


366 ORATORS CONTEMPORARY WITH DEMOSTHENES. 


grossly exaggerated, perhaps wantonly invented by an exaspe- 
rated enemy, who was confident of success, and knew that he 
would have the last word. 

The first appearance of Aischines as a public speaker was 
two years before his military distinctions at Tamyne.’ He had 
stored his mind with legal and political knowledge acquired 
in his intimate relations with Aristophon and Eubulus, and 
very soon became an influential statesman. In the spring of 
B.c. 347, he was sent to the Peloponnesus as one of the 
ambassadors, appointed, on the motion of Eubulus, after the — 
fall of Olynthus, and he spoke before the Ten Thousand at 
Megalopolis in opposition to the envoys of Philip, but without 
success.” Soon after this, he seems to have despaired of 
resisting the power and policy of the Macedonian king, and we 
find him among the warmest advocates for peace at any price. 
He was one of those who were sent to negociate with Philip at 
the end of B.c. 347. His intercourse with the wily monarch 
seems to have ended in the sacrifice of his character as a 
patriot and an honest man. And there can be little doubt 
that from this time he employed his influence and talents 
mainly in recommending measures opposed to the best interests 
of his country. Notwithstanding his somewhat narrow escape® 
from the prosecution brought against him by Demosthenes for 
his corrupt misconduct in the embassy, we find him persisting 
in the same course, and it was he who was the main cause of 
the second Phocian war,‘ which led to the battle of Cheroneia 
and the downfal of Greek independence. Always opposed 
and in many cases thwarted by Demosthenes, his political and 
personal animosity against that statesman finally exploded in 
his prosecution of Ctesiphon; and his signal defeat in that 
attempt to ruin his antagonist induced him, as we have already 
mentioned,’ to retire from Athens and seek the support of his 





1 Aisch. Fpist. XII. 

2 Dem. Fals. Leg. pp. 344—438. Asch. Fals. Leg. p. 38. 

3 Plut. p.840 C: τριάκοντα ψήφοις ἀπέφυγεν. Vita Dem. c. 15, on the authority 
of Idomeneus. 

4 He gives his own account of the proceedings, in a most vivid description, in 
his speech against Ctesiphon, pp. 69, sqq. See Thirlwall VI. p. 55. Grote XI. 
p. 650. 5 Above, chapter XLI. § 4. 





ZESCHINES. 367 


foreign friends. The death of Alexander prevented his in- 
tended journey to the court of that monarch." He became 
a teacher of rhetoric in Ionia, Caria, and Rhodes, and may be 
regarded as the founder of the Rhodian school of eloquence, 
which occupied a middle place between the old Attic and the 
more recent Asiatic schools. Towards the end of his life he 
removed to Samos, where he died in B.c. 314.° 

Of the numerous speeches which Aischines must have 
delivered,* only three have come down to us. One other was 
known to the ancient critics, but rejected by them as not 
genuine.” The paucity of his public speeches is accounted for 
by the fact that he was regarded as almost the imventor of 
extempore speaking, and prided himself on his unpremeditated 
fluency.’ We have also twelve epistles attributed to him, of 
which nine were known to Photius, who calls them the Muses, 
as he also termed the three speeches of Aischines the Graces.’ 
Modern scholars are agreed that the epistles are not genuine. 
His erotic poems, which would have illustrated a passage in his 
speech against Timarchus,’ are entirely lost, together with the 
ancient commentaries on his writings.” The three extant 
speeches are that against Timarchus, which-he delivered in 8.0. 
345; that on the Embassy, which is supposed not to have been 
spoken as we have it, in B.c. 343, but to have been written 
and published as a defence of his policy and character ;" and 





1 Plutarch, p. 840 D.: καὶ ἐλθεῖν εἰς Ἔφεσον ὡς Αλέξανδρον᾽ τοῦ δὲ τελευτήσαντος 
ταραχῆς οὔσης ἀπάρας εἰς τὴν Ῥόδον ἐνταῦθα σχολὴν καταστησάμενος ἐδίδασκεν. 
Phot. Vit. Soph. p. 509. 

2 See Westermann, Gesch. ἃ. Beredtsamkeit I. ὃ 81. 

3 Plutarch, p. 840 E. Photius, Cod. LXI. Clinton, 7. H. p. 171. 

4 Dem. De Fals. Leg. p. 344. 

5 It was called ὁ Δηλιακὸς νόμος. See Plut. p. 840 E. - Philostr. I. 18. Apollon. 
Vit. p. 248. Photius, Cod. LXI. attributes it to a contemporary of the same name. 

6 Philostr. Vit. Soph. p. 482: οἱ δὲ Αἰσχίνου φασι τὸ αὐτοσχεδιάζειν εὕρημα, p. 
509: ἀπ᾽ Αἰσχίνου δ᾽ ἤρξατο θεοφορήτῳ ὁρμῇ αὐτοσχεδιάζοντος. 

7 Phot. Cod. LXI. 

8 See Taylor (pref. p. 651), and Markland (ibid. p. 666, 679), who speaks 
favourably, however, of the third Epistle, 

Βυρίίχο. 

10 He was made the subject of special discussion by Cecilius, by Didymus, and 
by Aspasius. 

1 Plut. Vit. Dem. c. 15 ; Hermogenes, περὶ τῶν στασέων, p. 28, ed. Walz. 


368 ORATORS CONTEMPORARY WITH DEMOSTHENES. 


that against Ctesiphon, spoken in 8.c. 330. All these are 
extremely lively, and full of interesting details. He seems, 
indeed, to have been quite a master of narrative. For example, 
there are few better specimens of description than the picture 
which he gives us of the offended gravity of Autolycus, the 
Areopagite, in the speech against Timarchus,' or his account, 
whether true or false, of the failure of Demosthenes before 
Philip in the speech on the Embassy,’ or that in the speech 
against Ctesiphon,’ in which he depicts the religious phrensy of 
the Amphictyons. Aischines is well characterized by Dionysius 
as less distinguished by art than by natural facility—our first 
impression is, that he is merely graceful and elegant, but we 
find on examination that he is full of spirit and vigour.’ 
Hermogenes says that he combines grandeur with rhetorical 
elegance.’ Cicero opposes his noisy declamation (sonitus) to 
the power (vis) of Demosthenes,’ but attributes to him, as 
special characteristics, a smoothness of diction and a brilliancy of 
style,’ and not only paid him the compliment of translating 
his speech against Ctesiphon,* but twice imitated, by an almost 
literal adoption of the passage, the well-known description of 
the torments of the guilty in the speech against Timarchus? 
Quintilian, indeed, intimates by a strong metaphor that 
Aischines is distinguished rather by turgid verbosity than by 
solidity of argument. But most of those who have 
read his remains will share the regret, expressed by Dionysius, 
that Aischines had so little occasion to compose formal speeches, 
and that he could say with truth, in his speech against Timarchus, 





1 p, 12. 2p, 32. 3 p. 70. 

4 De Vet. Script. Cens. p. 434: οὐ πάνυ μὲν ἔντεχνος, τῇ δὲ παρὰ τῆς φύσεως 
εὐχερείᾳ κεχορηγημένος ... . καὶ ἡδὺς μὲν αὐτόθεν ἐντυχόντι, σφοδρὸς δ᾽ ἐξετα- 
σθείς. ‘ 


5 περὶ ἰδεῶν p. 384, Walz: τῷ μεγέθει μετὰ τοῦ κατὰ σχῆμα κάλλους πλεονάζων. 

6 De Oratore, III. 7. 

7 Orator.: ‘levitas et splendor verborum.’ 

8 Hieron. Zp. τοι ; Sidon. Zp, II. 9. 

9 p. 27. The imitations are in the speeches pro Sexto Roscio Amerino, and in 
L. Calp. Pisonem; see Lord Brougham’s Inaugural Discourse, Works, vol. VII. 

. 121. 
r 10 J, 0. X. 1, 77: ‘plenior Aischines et magis fusus et grandiori similis, quo 
minus strictus est: carnis tamen plus habet, minus lacertorum.’ 


DEINARCHUS. | 869 


that he had not previously indicted or called to account any of 
his fellow-citizens.’ 

§ 6. Detnarcuvs, the latest in point of time, and the lowest 
in point of eminence, among the ten orators of the canon, was 
born at Corinth somewhere about Ol. 104, 4, B.c. 361. He 
came to Athens at a very early age, and devoted himself to the 
study of rhetoric, which was then flourishing more than at any 
previous time. His principal teacher was Theophrastus, but 
he also enjoyed instructive intercourse with Demetrius of 
Phalerum.* Being excluded from the debates of the assembly 
by his imperfect citizenship, he employed himself as a speech- 
writer for the public courts, and seems to have made a consider- 
able fortune in this way.‘ As far as he was allowed to enter 
on the field of politics, he attached himself to the Macedonian 
party. Dionysius’ and Plutarch’ agree in fixing the commence- 
ment of Alexander’s reign as the time when Deinarchus first 
appeared as an orator. We find him taking an active part in 
the prosecution of Demosthenes, which was occasioned by the 
disputes about Harpalus and his treasure in B.c. 324; and when 
the issue of the Lamian war had deprived Athens of its 
greatest orators, Deinarchus remained without a rival, and 
from the death of Demades, in B.c. 318, to the expulsion of 
Demetrius of Phalerum, by his namesake, the Poliorcetes, in 
B.C. 307, he was the chief, if not the only representative of 
Attic eloquence; but his inferiority to his great models was 
generally felt, and he was called ‘the rustic Demosthenes,” and 
designated as one who bore the same relation to his predecessor 
that beer does to wine.* On leaving Athens, he fled, like 
Aristotle, to Chalcis, where he resided till B.c. 292, when the 





1 Photius, Cod. LXTI. 

2 Dionys. Hal. De Dinarcho judicium, p. 638, Reiske. Suidas s.v. says: vids 
τίνος ἐστιν οὐχ ἱστόρηται, and Plutarch states (p. 850 B), that his father was 
Socrates or Sostratus. Dionysius mentions the latter only. * | 

3 Dionys. p. 633; Plut. p. 850 C. 4 Plut. iid. 

5 Dionys. p. 638. 6 Plut. p. 850 B. C.; see Clinton, F. H. p. 151. 

7 Dionys. p. 647: ἄγροικόν τινες Δημοσθένην ἔφασαν εἶναι. 

8 Hermogenes, περὶ ἰδεῶν, II. 5, p. 384, Walz: ὥστ᾽ ἤδη τινες καὶ προσπαίζοντες 
αὐτὸν οὐκ ἀχαρίτως κρίθινον Δημοσθένην εἰρήκασι. The scholiast understands this 
as οὐ σίτινον (vol. V. p. 560, Walz), and the phrase hordearius rhetor, applied to 
L. Plotius by Suetonius, De Clar. Rhet. 2, is generally understood in a similar 

Vou. 11. BB 


3870 ORATORS CONTEMPORARY WITH DEMOSTHENES. 


friendly exertions of Theophrastus obtained permission for him 
to return.’ One of the last efforts of his oratory was a speech 
against his faithless friend Proxenus, who had taken advantage 
of his failing sight to rob him of some money while lodging 
in his house in the country.? It is stated that this was not 
only his last speech, but his first appearance in a law court.® 
The year of his death is not known. ὁ 

The number of orations ascribed to Deinarchus varies in the 
different lists which have come down to us. Demetrius, of 
Magnesia, claimed for him no less than 160 ;* in Plutarch’ and 
Photius’ we read of 64 genuine speeches; and Dionysius, of 
Halicarnassus,’ admits the authenticity of 60 out of the 87 
which bore his name. The three, still extant as his, refer to 
the business of Harpalus, and were spoken against Demo- 
sthenes, Philocles, and Aristogeiton. To these we must in all 
probability add the ἔνδειξις against Theocrines, printed among 
the orations of Demosthenes, but distinctly attributed to 
Deinarchus by Dionysius, and quoted as his by Harpocration.* 
As this speech is referred to B.c. 333, it must have been one 
of the earliest works of this orator. 

We have little reason to regret the loss of so many speeches 
of Deinarchus. Even Dionysius, who has paid him the com- 
pliment of writing a special treatise on his characteristics, 
admits that he was neither the inventor of a special style, nor 
the perfecter of that which was invented by others,’ and declares. 
that his position cannot be easily defined, because he has 
neither anything in common with the other orators, nor any- 
_ thing peculiar to himself.” In fact he was neither an original 





sense: but surely the opposition must be that between beer and wine, as in Ausch. 
Suppl. 930, 1: 
ἀλλ᾽ ἄρσενάς τοι τῆσδε γῆς οἰκήτορας 
εὑρήσετ᾽ οὐ πίνοντας ἐκ κριθῶν μέθυ, 
and in the Epigram ef Julian, Anthol. Pal. IX. 368, II. p. 128. 
1 Dionys. p. 634; Plut. p. 850 D; Phot. Cod. CCLXVII. 3 Dionys. <bid. 
3 Dionys. p. 635. 4 Dionys. p. 632. 5 p. 850 Ε΄. 
6 Cod. CCLXVII. 7 pp. 651 sqq. 8 Above, p. 334 [174]. 
9 p. 629: διὰ τὸ μήτε εὑρετὴν ἰδίου γεγονέναι χαρακτῆρος τὸν ἄνδρα μήτε τῶν 
εὑρημένων ἑτέροις τελειωτήν. 


10 p. 630: καιρὸς ἤδη καὶ περὶ τοῦ χαρακτῆρος αὐτοῦ λέγειν. ἔστι δὲ δυσέριστον. 
οὐδὲν γὰρ οὔτε κοινὸν οὔτ᾽ ἴδιον ἔσχεν" 


DEINARCHUS. 371 


man nor a good imitator;’ and although Didymus and Heron 
did not disdain to write commentaries on him,’ he was treated 
with neglect by the grammarians of Alexandria and Pergamus,' 
and some of the critics left him out of the canon of the ten 
orators.‘ It is admitted by his most favourable critics that 
his style is rugged, careless, and monotonous.’ And we can 
see this in the few remains which have come down to us. There 
is a wearisome recurrence of the same rhetorical artifices. For 
example, he endeavours to produce an impression by repetitions 
of the same word,’ which is the favourite figure with young 
composers. On the whole he must be regarded as a second- 
rate rhetorician, who would have obtained no distinction at 
Athens, if the military power of Macedon had not succeeded in 
stiflmg the political freedom of the city, and in removing from 
the stage of public life all those whose eloquence was calculated 
to rouse and guide the energies of the people. 





1 Dionysius calls him however the best of the imitators of Demosthenes (p. 646). 

® Harpocrat. s.v. ματρυλεῖον ; Suid. s.v. Ἥρων. 

3 Dionys. p. 630. 4 Bibl. Coislin. p. 597. 

5 Hermogenes calls him τραχὺς thrice in his short notice (vol. III. p. 384, 
Walz) ; so also in p. 236, where this quality is also predicated of Aristogeiton. In 
the scholia on Hermogenes Deinarchus is called τραχὺς καὶ μονοειδής (vol. VI. p. 
319, Walz), and it is said that his style, like that of Thucydides, σκληρὸς dv καὶ 
τραχὺς ἀποκναίει τὴν αἴσθησιν. 

6 Thus, in the speech against Demosthenes we have, at the beginning of different 
paragraphs, such tame repetitions as: δίκαια μὲν οὖν δίκαια τρόπον ye Twa 
πάσχει τὸ συνέδριον (p. 91, 18); μισθωτὸς οὗτος, ὦ ᾿Αθηναῖοι, μισθωτὸς οὗτός 
ἐστι παλαίος (p. 93, 37); πολλοί, ὦ ἄνδρες, πολλοὶ τῶν πολιτῶν. 


372 


CHAPTER XLIII. 


RHETORICAL HISTORIANS AND PROVINCIAL ANTIQUARIES. 


§ 1. Connexion between rhetoric and history. School of Isocrates. § 2. Ephorus. 
§ 3. Theopompus. ὃ 4. Sicilian School: Antiochus. § 5. Philistus. ὃ 6. 
Writers of the Atthides. , 


§ 1. HERE is no doubt that the first beginnings of history 

among the Greeks were connected with the literary 
efforts of the epic rhapsodists.’ While the Ionic dialect, which 
was the conventional language of the epos, was also adopted by 
the historian, even though he might belong to the Doric town of 
Halicarnassus’ or Cnidus,*? we know that these prose narratives 
of facts, mixed up with fables, were publicly recited or acted— 
for this word is used—just in the same way as the rhapsodes 
delivered the poems of Homer and the other poets of that 
school.‘ In the course of time, the rhapsodist was represented 
by the sophist, as the regular type of the professional author 
and teacher,’ the dramatic element was superseded by an effort 
of rhetoric, and the historian was no longer a writer of prose 
epics, but a finished product of the schools of rhetoric and 
sophistry. ‘Thus we have seen that Thucydides was emphatically 
a rhetorical historian. His style was not formed on the model 
of the old epic poets and annalists, but directly derived from 
his teacher Antiphon.’ And the elaborate speeches, which he 
incorporates with his narrative, are in fact the soul of his 
history.’ It was not, therefore, without reason that Demo- 
sthenes made Thucydides the subject of his special study,® and — 





1 See chapter XVIII. : 3 Chapter XIX. 8 7. 

3 Chapter XX XVIII. § 9. 

4 See the passages which we have quoted in the Theatre of the Greeks, ed. 6, 

P 40. Ἢ 
5 Above, chapter ΧΙ ΧΎΤΙ, § 2. 6 Chapter XXXIV. §§ το, τι. 
7 Ibid. §§ 8, 9. 8 Above, p. 343 [183]. 





SCHOOL OF ISOCRATES. 373 


formed on this model his own simple and energetic style. The 
᾿ connexion, however, between rhetoric and history was never 
more distinctly and formally acknowledged than in the relations 
which connected Isocrates with the historians who were formed 
in his school. That rhetorician was not merely a professed 
artist of language, but he studiously abstained from the more 
immediately practical exhibitions of his art in the law-courts 
and public assemblies, and wrote elaborate pamphlets on sub- 
jects of general and political interest.’ To him, therefore, it 
Was a more congenial occupation to educate the philosophical 
historian, than to form the style of the forensic or parliamentary 
speaker. Accordingly, we find that Isocrates not only trained 
professed rhetoricians, like Naucrates and Theodectes, and 
orators like Isceus, Lycurgus, and Hypereides, but also writers, 
who, like Ephorus and Theopompus, employed the facilities of 
composition which they had acquired under his teaching in the 
compilation of elaborate and artistic narratives of past events ; 
and so, in the felicitous language of Cicero, from. the school of 
Isocrates, as from the Trojan horse, none but princes of Greece 
issued forth, some of whom, however, were resolved to become 
illustrious only on the parade, while others sought distinction 
in the field of battle We are told that Isocrates not only 
formed the style and regulated the character of Ephorus and 
Theopompus, applying, as Cicero says in several passages, the 
spurs to the former, who was bashful and hesitating, and 
curbing Theopompus, who was apt to overleap all bounds in the 
extravagances of his diction,* but that he even selected for them 
the departments of historical investigation which were best 
suited to their different abilities, advising the former to confine 





1 Above, chapter XXXVI. § 6. 

2 De Oratore, 11. 22, ὃ 94: ‘ecce tibi exortus est jee magister istorum 
omnium, cujus [v. qui ‘ius e ludo tamquam ex equo Trojano meri principes exie- 
runt: sed eorum partim in pomp4, partim in acie illustres esse voluerunt.’ 

8 De Oratore, III. 9, ὃ 36: ‘quod dicebat Isocrates, doctor singularis: se cal- 
caribus in Ephoro, contra autem in Theopompo frenis utisolere. Alterum enim 
exsultantem verborum audacia reprimebat, alterum cunctantem et quasi verecun- 
dantem incitabat.’ Cf. Brut. 56, ὃ 204; ad Atticum, VI. 1, 12; Suidas, s.v. 
"Ἔφορος : ὁ γοῦν Ἰσοκράτης τὸν μὲν [Θεόπομπον] ἔφη ἰχαλινοῦ δεῖσθαι, τὸν δὲ "Ἔφορον 
κέντρου. 


3874 RHETORICAL HISTORIANS AND ANTIQUARIES. 


himself to the annals of early times, and the latter to under- 
take the more recent and exciting periods.’ 

§ 2. Ernorus, of Cume, or Cyme, the chief city of AMolis 
in Asia Minor, was the son of Demophilus,? and was born in 
Ol. 93, 4. B.c. 407. He was sent to Chios, where Isocrates 
had opened a school, in order to learn rhetoric with a view to 
its practical applications. But when he returned to his native 
city, it was found that he had- made but little progress in 
oratory, and that his natural abilities held out no prospect of 
distinction as a public speaker. Accordingly he went back to 
his teacher, and endeavoured to supply his natural defects by 
renewed diligence, and was so far successful that he was crowned 
along with Theopompus, as one of the best pupils of the Chian 
school.’ It is inferred from a passage in Seneca‘ that Ephorus 
actually engaged in forensic employments, and was induced to 
withdraw from this by the advice of Isocrates, who saw that 
his talents were better fitted for a literary life. With the 
exception of Plutarch’s statement, that Ephorus declined an 
invitation to visit the court of Alexander the Great, perhaps to 
accompany him to the East, we know nothing more of the life 
of this historian. 

The works of Ephorus were the following. (1) A 
general history of Greece in thirty books, from the return of 





1 Phot. Cod. CCLX.: γεγόνασιν αὐτοῦ [Ἰσοκράτους] ἀκροαταὶ Θεόπομπος ὁ 
Xtos καὶ "Ε φορος ὁ Κυμαῖος οἷς καὶ ταῖς ἱστορικαῖς συγγραφαῖς προὐτρέψατο χρήσα- 
σθαι πρὸς τὴν ἑκάστου φύσιν ἀναλόγως καὶ τὰς ὑποθέσεις τῆς ἱστορίας αὐτοῖς διανει- 
pdpevos. Cod. CLXXVI: καὶ τὰς ἱστορικὰς δὲ ὑποθέσεις τὸν διδάσκοντα αὐτοῖς 
[Ἐφόρῳ καὶ Θεοπόμπῳ] προβαλεῖν τὰς μὲν ἄνω τῶν χρόνων "Eddpy, Θεοπόμπῳ δὲ τὰς 
μετὰ Θουκυδίδην "Ἑλληνικάς, πρὸς τὴν ἑκατέρου φύσιν καὶ τὸ ἔργον ἁρμοσάμενον. 

3 Suidas, s.n., mentions Antiochus as, according to some accounts, the name of 
his father: but this may have arisen from some confusion with the Sicilian 
historian of that name, and C. Miiller, to whom we are indebted for most of the 
materials of this sketch, has reasonably inferred that Demophilus was really his 
name, because Plutarch states this, and because it was the name of his son (frag- 
menta Historicorum Grecorum, ed. C. et T. Miiller, Paris, 1841, p. LVIL.). 

3 Menander, περὶ ἐπιδεικτικῶν, p. 262, Walz: ὥσπερ “Eqopos ἐστεφανοῦτο καὶ 
Θεόπομπος of μαθηταὶ Ἰσοκράτους ws διαφέροντες τῶν ἄλλων. 

4 De tranquill. Anim. ο. 6: ‘Isocrates Ephorum injecté manu a foro subduxit, 
utiliorem componendis monumentis historiarum ratus.’ 

5 Plut. De Stoic. repugn. c. 20: Καλλισθέζει τινες ἐγκαλοῦσιν ὅτι πρὸς ᾿Αλέξαν- 
dpov ἔπλευσεν . . . « Ἕφορον δὲ καὶ Zevoxpdrny καὶ Μενέδημον ἐπαινοῦσι, παραιτη- 
σαμένους τὸν ᾿Αλέξανδρον. 


Ee .... . , 


EPHORUS. 375 


the Heracleid' to the taking of Perinthus, in B.c. 341.2 This 
work was completed by his son, Demophilus,’ and continued by 
Diyllus down to the death of Philip.* It appears that each 
book was complete in itself, and had a special title; for 
example, the fourth book was called Europa.’ The titles of 
the other books cannot be fixed with certainty, but the 
numerous fragments and references enable us to see that the 
first three books discussed the early migrations and settlements 
of the Greeks; that the fifth book was devoted to Asia and 
Africa ; that the sixth and seventh books treated of the Pelopon- 
nesus and Sicily; the eighth and ninth contained the history 
of Creesus, Cyrus, and Darius; the tenth and eleventh gave 
the history of Athens from Marathon to Salamis; the twelfth 
and thirteenth carried on the general history of Greece to the 
87th Olympiad; the fourteenth narrated the Peloponnesian 
war ; the fifteenth and sixteenth contained Hannibal’s invasion 
of Sicily, and the domination of the thirty tyrants at Athens ; 
the seventeenth was devoted to the expedition of Cyrus the 
younger; the eighteenth described the campaigns of Thimbron, 
Dercyllidas, and Agesilaus, in Asia Minor; the nineteenth 
contained the events from the Corinthian war to the peace of 
Antalcidas ; and in books 20—29 the history was carried down 
to the beginning of the Sacred War. We have already men- 
tioned that the thirtieth book, describing that war, was written 
by Demophilus, after the death of his father. : 

(IL.) A treatise on discoveries (περὶ εὑρημάτων) in two books. 
It has been supposed’ that this work may have been extracted 





1 Diodor. IV. τ: τὰ ἀπὸ τῆς Ἡρακλειδῶν καθόδου συνταξάμενος, ταύτην ἀρχὴν 
ἐποιήσατο τῆς ἱστορίας. 

2 Id. XVI. 26: Ἔφορος τὴν ἱστορίαν ἐνθάδε κατέστροφεν ἐς τὴν Περίνθου πολι- 
ορκίαν. é 

3 Id. XVI. 14: Anuddiros ὁ Ἑφόρου τοῦ ἱστοριογράφου vids τὸν παραλειφθέντα 
πόλεμον ὑπὸ τοῦ πατρὸς ὀνομασθέντα δὲ ἱερὸν συντεταγμένος. 

4 Id. ibid.: Δίυλλος δὲ ὁ ᾿Αθηναῖος ἦρκται τῆς ἱστορίας ἀπὸ τὴς ἱεροσυλήσεως καὶ 
γέγραφε βιβλίους εἴκοσι καὶ ἕπτα, συμπεριλαβὼν πάσας τὰς ἐν τοῖς χρόνοις τούτοις 
γενομένας πράξεις. Diyllus was continued in thirty books by Psaon, of Platza ; 
Creuzer, Histor. Kunst. p. 322. 

δ᾽ Strabo, I. p. 59: Ἔφορος ἐν τῷ περὶ τῆς Evpwrns λόγῳ. 

® ©.Miiller, Pragmenta Historicorwm Grecorum, p. LXI.: ‘sed videas an non 
postea aliquis hc inventa ex historiarum libris excerpserit eique compendio 
Ephori nomen preefixerit.’ 


876 RHETORICAL HISTORIANS AND ANTIQUARIES. 


by some later author from the history of Ephorns, but it is more 
probable that it was a supplementary collection of antiquarian 
investigations. 

(III.) An essay on domestic matters (σύνταγμα ἐπιχώριον). 
In this book he seems to have collected a good deal of in- 
formation respecting the native celebrities of Cume, mixed up 
with particulars relating to the literary history of Greece in 
general. 

(IV.) A treatise on diction (περὶ λέξεως). This was one of 
the many treatises on rhetoric which were superseded by the 
more methodical work of Aristotle. The title shows that it was 
confined to a mere department of the subject,’ and the refe- 
rences to the work by Cicero? and Quintilian® tell us only 
that he laid down specific rules for the rhythmical structure of 
sentences. 

(V.) A collection, in twenty-four books, of pantech 
respecting good and evil things (περὶ ἀγαθῶν καὶ κακῶν βιβλία 
KO), attributed to him by Suidas, is supposed to have been a 
series of extracts from his history. 

(VI.) An account of the remarkable things in different 
countries, in fifteen books (περὶ τῶν ἑκασταχοῦ παραδόξων 
βιβλία cé), was either a work preparatory to his history, or a 
supplement to the geographical portion of it.* 

The numerous fragments of Ephorus, and the frequent 
references to him in the pages of ancient writers, especially in 
the accurate and judicious work of the geographer Strabo, 
enable us to form a sufficient estimate of the loss which we 
have sustained in him. Strabo says’ that he makes great use 
of Ephorus on account of his careful investigation of local par- 
ticulars, and that he is a writer of considerable authority. 
And Polybius, whom Strabo quotes, attributes to Ephorus a 
᾿ς marked superiority over Eudoxus, and admits his excellence as 
a describer of the foundations of cities, the affinities of nations, 





1 See above, chapter XL. § 5. 2 Cic. Orator. 57. 

3 Quintil. IX. 4, 87. 

4 See Marx (apud Miller, Fragm. p. LXI.), who compares the παραδόξων ἐθῶν 
συναγωγῇ of Nicolaus Damascenus. 

5 p. 422: Ἔφορος ᾧ τὸ πλεῖστον χρώμεθα διὰ τὴν περὶ ταῦτα ἐπιμέλειαν καθάπερ 
καὶ Πολύβιος μαρτυρῶν τυγχάνει, ἀνὴρ ἀξιόλογος. 





THEOPOMPUS. 377 


their emigrations, and their ancient worthies.' Polybius also 
concedes to Ephorus the honour of being the first writer of 
universal history,? and Strabo gives him the credit of being 
the first to separate the historical element from the purely 
geographical, and of having made the latter depend on real in- 
vestigations.» Some of his descriptions, such as that of Beeotia,* 
or that of Crete,® fully justify the praises bestowed upon him 
as a geographer, and it is clear that, in drawing up his details 
of historical events, he availed himself of all the best authorities, 
not neglecting inscriptions and other authentic documents,’ and 
correcting many errors of his predecessors.’ This diligence has 
rendered him liable to a charge of plagiarism,* but there seems 
to be no reason for believing that he intentionally concealed his 
obligations to older writers. From the more general accu- 
sations of Timzus he is formally vindicated by Polybius ;’ and 
though not free from errors,” Ephorus has furnished us, espe- 
cially through compilers like Diodorus Siculus, with very much 
of our knowledge of Greek history. His style, as might have 
been expected from his rhetorical training, was highly coloured 
and artificial," and, according to Dionysius,” only he and 
Theopompus among all the historical writers wrote in a 
perfectly accurate and finished diction. This, at least, seems a 
more probable judgment than the harsh statement of Duris of 
Samos,” that both Ephorus and Theopompus were entirely 
inferior to their predecessors, having no power of imitation 
or beauty of language, and being anxious only about their 
style. 

§ 3. Turoromrvs, who is generally regarded as the pendant 
to Ephorus in the portrait gallery of Greek literary history, 
was born at Chios in Ol. 100, 3, B.c. 378. His father, 





1 Polyb. XXXIV. 1, 3; Strabo, p. 425. 


aN. 3252s 8 p. 332. 4 Strabo, pp. 400, sqq. 
5 pp. 479, 564. δ». 463. 

7 e.g. of Hellanicus, Joseph. 6. Apion. I. 3. 

8 Porphyr. ap. Euseb. Prep. Evang. X. 2. 9. XII. 23. 


10 Diodor. I. 39 ; Strabo, pp. 303, 422, 464. 

Ἢ Polyb. XII. 28; Dion. Hal. De Iseo judic. p..626; Dio Chrys. XVIII. 
p- 256, Mor. ; Philostr. Vit. Soph. I. 17; Cie. Orat. 51. 

15 Dion. Hal. De Comp. Verb. p. 173. 

13 Phot. Cod. CLXXVI. p. 393, Hoeschel. 


378 RHETORICAL HISTORIANS AND ANTIQUARIES. 


Damasistratus, was expelled from Chios by the Lacedzemonians 
while the future historian was still a child, perhaps an infant.’ 
It is quite impossible, then, that Theopompus could have 
received instruction from Isocrates in his native island of 
Chios,’ and it is probable that the travels of his earlier years 
included a visit to Athens, where he enjoyed a lengthened 
intercourse with the great rhetorician. Having received a 
complete training in this school, aud being relieved by his 
ample patrimony from the necessity of writing for the law 
courts, he devoted himself to the composition of set speeches 
(ἐπιδείξεις), in imitation of his master, which he delivered in 
every considerable city, and obtained great renown by these 
displays,* especially in B.c. 352, when he won the prize, against 
Naucrates and Isocrates, in the competition instituted by Arte- 
misia for the best speech in honour of her deceased husband, 
Mausolus.* Satisfied with the applause which he had gained by 
these oratorical efforts, he followed the advice of Isocrates, 
and applied himself to the composition of history,’ a task for 
which he was especially qualified by the knowledge which he 
acquired in his travels, and by his political experience. For 
it appears that on his return to Chios, in consequence of the 
letters of Alexander the Great, calling on the people of that 
island to restore their exiles, and probably written in B.c. 333, 
Theopompus took the lead in the government of his native city. 
As long as Alexander lived he was maintained at the head 
of the aristocratic party, in spite of his overbearing and 
haughty temper, and the bitter and formidable attacks of the 
eminent rhetorician Theocritus.° On the death of his protector 
he was again banished from Chios, and took refuge in Egypt, 
where, however, he did not obtain a friendly reception from 
Ptolemy, who would have put him to death as a meddlesome 
and dangerous character, had not Theopompus been. protected 





1 It is supposed that this expulsion took place in Ol. 100, 4; see Diodor. XV. 
28. 

2 This is stated, however, by the author of the Vite X. Oratorwm, p. 837 C., 
and by Photius, Cod. CCLX. 

3 Phot. Cod. CLXXVI.; Quintil. X. 1; Dionys. Hal. ad. Pomp. p. 131. 

4 A. Gellius, N. A. X. 18; Vit. X. Orat. p. 838 B; Euseb. Prep. Evang. 
ws 2; 
5 Phot. Cod. CCLX. & Strabo, p. 955. 


| 


THEOPOMPUS. 379 


by the intervention of powerful friends.’ Ptolemy did not 
assume the title of king till B.c. 306, and if the story that he 
fled to king Ptolemy is to be understood as indicating a period 
subsequent to this, Theopompus must have been very much 
advanced in years when he finally left his native city. Of the 
remainder of his life, and of his death, which probably followed 
soon after this banishment, we have no account. 

The works of Theopompus, which are all lost, were chiefly 
historical, and we are informed that he had devoted a con- 
siderable part of his ample fortune towards procuring accurate 
information in regard to the particulars which he commemo- 
rated. His diligence and trustworthiness are attested by many 
of the ancient critics,’ and his style is said to have been lucid, 
ornate, and elegant, though deficient in vigour.’ His greatest 
fault, according to the ancient writers, was attributable to the 
vehemence of his temper. They intimate that neither in praise 
nor in vituperation could he keep his language within due bounds. 
And he has been classed with Timzeus as conspicuously given 
to defamation.* On the other hand he has been defended by 
an eminent modern scholar, who says :° ‘ Theopompus has been 
described as censorious for having painted from the life the 
dissolute manners of a corrupt age; for most people are in- 
clined to look at every thing on its fairest side, especially if 
they view it from a distance, when all the passions are silent, and 
the benevolent feeling which is implanted in the heart of man 
is not contradicted by immediate and personal experience ; but 
honour is due to the historian who knows how to distinguish 
the covering from the surface, and, like the judge of the 
infernal regions, drags the soul before his judgment-seat, naked 
and stripped of all pomp and pageantry.’ 





1 Phot. Cod. CLXXVI.: Πτολεμαῖον δὲ οὐ προσίεσθαι τὸν ἄνδρα, ἀλλὰ καὶ ὡς 
πολυπράγμονα ἀνελεῖν ἐθελῆσαι, εἰ μή τινες τῶν φίλων παραιτησάμενοι διεσώσαντο. 

2 Athenzus, III. 18 ; Suidas, 5. ν. Ἔφορος. 

8 Dionys. Hal. Epist. ad Pomp., p. 132: καθαρὰ ἡ λέξις καὶ κοινὴ καὶ σαφής, 
ὑψηλή τε καὶ μεγαλοπρεπὴς καὶ τὸ πομπικὸν ἔχουσα πολύ, συγκειμένη τε κατὰ τὴν 
μέσην ἁρμονίαν, ἡδέως καὶ μαλακῶς ῥέουσα. 

* Corn. Nepos. Alcib. c. 11 ; Clem. Alex. Strom. I. p. 316; Lucian, Quomodo 
hist. consevib. c. 59. Polyb. VIII. 12 ; Athenzus VI. p. 254 PB. 

5 Béckh, Public Economy of Athens, book II. chapter XXIV. p. 293, 
Eng. Tr. 


3880 RHETORICAL HISTORIANS AND ANTIQUARIES. 


The following is the list of his writings. 

(1) An abridgment of Herodotus (ἐπιτομὴ τῶν Ἡροδότου 
ἱστοριῶν, which certain modern scholars’ have attributed to 
some later writer. 

(II.) A History of Greece in twelve books, in continuation 
of Thucydides (Σύνταξις Ἑλληνικῶν), which contained a period 
of seventeen years from the battle of Cynossema to that of 
Cnidus. Of this work very few fragments remain.’ 

(III.) His history specially so called (Ioropiat κατ᾽ ἐξοχήν), 
also designated as his Philippica (Φιλιππικά), which in fifty- 
eight books contained an elaborate history of Philip of Macedon, 
with frequent digressions, recounting the contemporary events 
in different countries.* The first book gave the earlier years of 
Philip; the second, his Illyrian, Peeonian, and Thracian wars ; 
the third book discussed the war with Amphipolis, and took 
occasion to digress into the history of Sesostris and the 
Scythians ; in the eighth book he described the social war, with 
many digressions on wonderful occurrences of various kinds ; 
the ninth gave Philip’s Thessalian campaign, with much sup- 
plementary information about the scene of action; the tenth 
prepared the way for the war between Philip and the Athenians, 
by an account of the early history of Attica and of the old 
Athenian statesmen ; the eleventh book probably brought down 
the history of Philip to his attempt on Thermopyle in B.c. 352 ; 
books 12 to 18 seem to have contained an account of the wars 
waged by the Persians against Cyprus, Phoenicia, and Egypt ; 
the nineteenth and twentieth books returned to the affairs of 
Philip, with especial reference to his dealings with Thessaly and 
Thrace ; in the twenty-first book there was a discussion about 
Dionysius and the affairs of Sicily, and this subject was renewed 
in the thirty-ninth, fortieth, and forty-first books; in books 
22—38, 42—51, the history of Philip was carried down to the 
battle of Chzeroneia, which was described in book 53; the 
fifty-second book contained the expedition of Archidamus in 
aid of the Tarentines; and the remainder of the work com- 





1 E. g. Vossius (De Hist. Gr. p. 16, 31.) 

2 In the eleventh book he borrowed Xenophon’s lively account of the interview 
between Agesilaus and Pharnabazus (Apollonius apud Euseb. Prep. Evang. p. 465). 

8 Diodor. XVI. 3, Phot. Cod. CLXXYVI, 


1 
[ 


THEOPOMPUS. 3881 


pleted the history of Philip down to his death.' From this 
sketch of the contents, we may see that the Philippica of 
Theopompus was a very miscellaneous compilation, not much 
distinguished by method or unity of purpose. It has been 
supposed that this work, together with the twelve books of the 
Syntazxis, made up a continuous history in seventy books ;? but 
this view has been sufficiently refuted by Mr. Fynes Clinton.’ 
The digressions, which formed so large a part of the book, were 
omitted at an early period by those who were chiefly interested 
in the history of the king of Macedon; and Philip III. in this 
way reduced the number of books from fifty-eight to sixteen.’ 
In the time of Photius, however—that is, in the ninth century 
of our wra—there were still extant all the fifty-eight books, 
except the sixth, seventh, ninth, twentieth, and thirtieth; and 
the same five books in all probability were wanting in the time 
of Diodorus Siculus. Of the original extent of this work and 
the Syntaxis we may form some idea from the statement of 
Photius, on the authority of Theopompus himself, that the two 
together contained 150,000 lines.’ 

(IV.) Orations, chiefly Panegyrical and Deliberative, in- 
cluding, besides the eulogium on Mausolus, the panegyrics on 
Philip and Alexander, and the address to Alexander on the 
affairs of Chios. : 

(V.) An attack on Plato (κατὰ Πλάτωνος διατριβή). 

(VI.) On religiousness (περὶ εὐσεβείας). It is supposed that 
these two may have been extracts from his great work on 
Philip. 





1 There is a full analysis of the Philippica of Theopompus, as far as the frag- 
ments supply the necessary data, in Miiller’s Pragm. Hist. Gr. pp. LXX.—LX XIII. 

2 Suidas, 5. v. Θεόπομπος. 8 Fasti Hellenici II., pp. 374, 375+ 

4 Phot. Cod .CLXXVI.: πλείσταις μὲν οὖν παρεκβάσεσι παντοδαπῆς ἱστορίας τοὺς 
ἱστορικοὺς αὐτοῦ λόγους Θέοπομπος παρατείνει. διὸ καὶ Φίλιππος ὁ πρὸς Ῥωμαίους 
πολεμήσας ἐξελὼν ταύτας καὶ τὰς Φιλίππου συνταξάμενος πράξεις at σκοπός εἶσι Θεο- 
πόμπῳ εἰς ἑκκαίδεκα βίβλους μόνας μηδὲν παρ᾽ ἑαυτοῦ προσθεὶς ἢ ἀφελὼν πλὴν ὡς 
εἴρηται τῶν παρεκτροπῶν, τὰς πάσας ἀπήρτισεν. 

5 Phot. ibid.: οὐκ ἐλαττόνων μὲν ἢ δισμυρίων ἐπῶν τοὺς ἐπιδεικτικοὺς τῶν λόγων 
συγγραψαμένῳ πλείους δὲ ἢ πεντεκαίδεκα μυριάδας ἐν οἷς τάς τε τῶν Ἑβλλήνων καὶ 
βαρβάρων πράξεις μέχρι νῦν ἀπαγγελλομένας ἔστι λαβεῖν. 

§ Miiller, u. s., p. LXXIII. Ruhnken (Hist. Cr. Gr. Or. p. 371) conjectured 
that, in the case of No. VI. the name of Theopompus has been substituted for that 
of Theophrastus, who wrote a book περὶ εὐσεβείας (Diog. Laért. V. p. 126). 


382 RHETORICAL HISTORIANS AND ANTIQUARIES. 


Anaximenes published a work entitled Τρικάρανος or Tpuro- 


λιτικός,, under the name of Theopompus, in order to injure the 
character of the rival rhetorician. 

§ 4. The Sicilian School of Corax, Tisias, and Gorgias, of 
which Isocrates may be regarded as the Attic representative,’ 
gave rise to an historical school of its own, the most important 
member of which, Philistus, was a contemporary of the Athenian 
rhetorician. At one time, indeed, it was a common opinion 
that Philistus had been, like Ephorus and Theopompus, a pupil 
of Isocrates. This belief was derived from a passage in Cicero, 
where Theopompus, Ephorus, Philistus, and Naucrates, are 
mentioned together as having proceeded from the school of 
Isocrates, just as the Greek captains came forth from the 
wooden horse at Troy.“ But as Cicero himself, in another 
passage of the same work, seems to distinguish between 
Philistus and the scholars of Isocrates,’ it has been judiciously 
suggested’ that we ought to read Philiscus instead of Philistus 
in the former reference to the Isocratean historians. For there 
was a Philiscus of Miletus among the scholars of Isocrates, and 
he, though not himself an eminent historian, was the teacher of 
Timeus, a later historian of the same school as Philistus; and 
in two separate notices Suidas has confounded the two writers.’ 
It is also interesting to observe, with reference to the notice in 
Cicero, who immediately after Philiscus mentions the eminent 


rhetorician Naucrates, the competitor with Theopompus for the 





1 Pausan. VI. 18. The three cities referred to were Athens, Sparta, and Thebes. 

2 Above, ch. XXXII. § 3. 3 Above, ch. XXXVI. § 1. 

4 De Oratore, II. 23, 94: ‘itaque et illi Theopompi, Ephori, Philisti, Naucrate, 
multique alii naturis differunt.’ 

5 Ibid. II. 13, 57: ‘ hunc consecutus est Syracusius Philistus, qui, quum Dionysii 
tyranni familiarissimus esset, otium suum consumpsit in historia scribend&, maxi- 
meque Thucydidem est, sicut mihi videtur, imitatus. Postea vero, quasi ex 
clarissim4& rhetoris officinaé duo prestantes ingenio, Theopompus et Ephorus, ab 
Tsocrate magistro impulsi, se ad historiam contulerunt.’ 

6 By Giller, De situ Syracusarwm, pp. 1o8—118. 

7 The following are the corresponding parts of the two notices in Suidas :— 


Φιλίσκος } Φίλιστος, Συρακούσιος, Φίλιστος Ναυκρατίτης ἢ Συρακούσιος, 


ἱστορικός. ἣν δὲ συγγενὴς Διονυσίου τοῦ ᾿Αρχωνίδου vids, μαθητὴς δὲ ἣν Ἑὐήνου 


τυράννου Σικελίας καὶ ἐν τῇ πρὸς τοὺς τοῦ ἐλεγειοποιοῦ ὃς πρῶτος κατὰ ῥητορι- 
Καρχηδονίους ναυμαχίᾳ ἐτελεύτησε. μα- κὴῚν τέχνην ἱστορίαν ἔγραψε. 
θητὴς δὲ ἣν Εὐήνου τοῦ ἐλεγειοποιοῦ. 


ee ea 1 Δ... Δ. 








ANTIOCHUS. 383 


Mausolean prize, that Suidas not only seems to interchange 
‘ Naucrates the Erythrean’ with ‘ Erythrzeus the Naucratite,’? 
but really says of Philistus that he was ‘either a Naucratite or 
a Syracusan, having no doubt found Philiscus and Naucrates 
mentioned together, as Cicero mentions them, among the 
scholars of Isocrates. Admitting, then, the connexion between 
Tsocrates and the rhetoricians of Sicily, and between his pupil 
Philiscus and Timzeus, we must consider the Sicilian historians 
Antiochus and Philistus as belonging to a manifestation of 
Greek historiography, which stands entirely by itself. 

Of Antiocnus we have very scanty remains, and the loss of 
his writings is much to be deplored, for it cannot be doubted 
that he was well acquainted with the traditions of his own 
eountry and Italy, and that he gave many details, which are 
now transmitted to us, if at all, in merely a secondary form. 
For example, the particulars into which Thucydides enters at 
the beginning of his sixth book are most probably derived from 
Antiochus, and to the same source Aristotle was indebted for 
his references to Sicilian history.” How far Diodorus has 
copied or abridged Antiochus cannot be determined; but he 
sometimes quotes him by name.* The Syracusan historian 
was also one of the authorities of Dionysius of Halicarnassus* 
and Strabo,’ and he is quoted by a late writer for the curious 
statement that Rome was founded before the Trojan war in the 
time of King Morges, the successor of Italus, and the mythical 
representative of the Sicilian Morgetes.° We know nothing 
about Antiochus, except that he was the son of Xenophanes of 
Syracuse; that although of Dorian extraction, like Herodotus, 
he followed the old fashion and wrote in the Ionic dialect ;? and 





1 Suidas, 5, v. ᾿Ισοκράτης : οὗτος καὶ Θεοδέκτῃ καὶ Θεοπόμπῳ ἅμα τῷ ’EpvOpaly 
Ναυκρατίτῃ διηγωνίσατο ; οἷ. 5. ν. Θεοδέκτης : οὗτος καὶ ὁ Ἔρυθραῖος Ναυκράτης. It is 
clear from the position of the article that we have only an error of the copyist in 
the former passage. 

3 Niebuhr, Hist. of Rome, vol. I. pp. 16, 17, Engl. Tr. 

% e.g. XIL 7x. 41, 4o. et al. 5 p. 391. et al. 

- δ Syneell. p. 364, Dind.: ᾿Αντίοχος δὲ ὁ Συρακόσιος καὶ πρὸ Τρωικῶν φησὶ τὴν 
“Ῥώμην ἔκτισθαι βασιλεύοντος Μόργητος ᾿Ιταλίας ἀπὸ Τάραντος ἄχρι ἸΠοσειδωνίας 
μετὰ τὸν πρῶτον λεγόμενον Ἴταλον βασιλέα καταγεγηρακότα. 

7 The commencement of his work is thus cited by Dionysius, I. 12: ᾿Αντίοχος 
Ξιενοφάνεος τάδε συνέγραψε περὶ Ἰταλίας ἐκ τῶν ἀρχαίων λόγων τὰ πιστότατα Kal 
σαφέστατα. τὴν γῆν ταύτην, ἥτις νῦν ᾿Ιταλία καλεῖται, τὸ παλαιὸν εἶχον Οἰνωτροί. 


884 RHETORICAL HISTORIANS AND ANTIQUARIES. 


that his Sicilian history, which was comprised in nine books, 
was carried down to the year 423 B.C.’ 

§ 5. Like Thucydides, whom he selected as his model, 
Puizistus was a man of consideration in his own country, and 
took an active part in public affairs. The year of his birth is 
not stated, and it is even uncertain whether his father’s name 
was Archonides, as Suidas says,’ or Archimenides, as Pausanias® 
tells us. As he was a very old man at the time of his death, 
in B.c. 556,‘ as he had been an eye-witness of the arrival of 
Gylippus at Syracuse in B.c. 415,7 and made a prominent public 
appearance in B.c. 406,° he was probably born not later than 
the commencement of the Peloponnesian war in B.c. 432. His 
apparent connexion with Hermocrates, who, aided by Gylippus, 
had enabled his countrymen to repel triumphantly the formid- 
able invasion of the Athenians, led him to espouse the cause of 
Dionysius, when that daring adventurer came forward as the 
representative and successor of the anti-popular chieftain. 
When the conduct of the Syracusan generals at Agrigentum, in 
B.c. 406, excited the bitter indignation of their fellow-citizens, 
and Dionysius was fined for the intemperance with which he 
attacked them in the assembly, Philistus at once paid the fine, 
and urged Dionysius to pursue his invectives in the same strain, 
promising to meet all the penalties which might be imposed 
upon him.’ Having thus contributed not only to the restora- 
tion of the Hermocratean party, but also to the establishment 
of Dionysius as despotical ruler of Syracuse, Philistus naturally 
occupied a prominent place in the new administration of affairs. 
For a long time he was the confidential friend and lieutenant of 
the tyrant, insomuch that he was intrusted with the command 
of the citadel, on which the safety of Dionysius depended. At 
length, however, he excited the jealousy of that ruler by 
privately marrying one of the two daughters of his brother 





1 Diod. u.s.; Clinton, Fasti Hellenici, p. 69. 

2 See above, p. 382 [222], note 7. 3 X. 23. 

4 Plut. Dion. c. 35. 5 Id. Nic. c. 19. 

6 Diod. XIII. gt. 

7 Diodorus, XIII. 91: τῶν δ᾽ ἀρχόντων ζημιόύντων τὸν Διονύσιον κατὰ τοὺς 
νόμους ὡς θορυβοῦντα, Φίλιστος ὁ τὰς ἱστορίας ὕστερον συγγράψας οὐσίαν ἔχων μεγά- 
λην ἐξέτισε τὰ πρόστιμα, καί τῷ Διονυσίῳ παρεκελεύετο λέγειν ὅσα προῃρεῖτο, 
K.T.A. 











PHILISTUS 385 


Leptines, and was in consequence banished from Syracuse 
about B.c. 386.' He settled first at Thurii, for so many years 
the residence of Herodotus, and afterwards removed to Adria. 
Here his enforced leisure furnished to him, as it had done to 
Thucydides, the opportunity and the inducement to compose 
his historical work. At the same time he continually endea- 
youred to procure his recal from exile, and sometimes, it is 
said, had recourse to flatteries unworthy of his character, in the 
hope of inducing Dionysius to relent.? But as long as the 
elder tyrant lived, he pleaded in vain. On the accession of the 
younger Dionysius in B.c. 367, a cabal was formed against 
Dion and his friend Plato, and, to counterbalance their influence, 
Philistus was invited to Syracuse. Here he resumed all his 
authority, and became the chief minister of the tyrant, whom 
he induced to dismiss Plato, and banish Dion. Till the year 
B.C. 357, he enjoyed a position at Syracuse scarcely second to 
that of Dionysius himself, and by his military experience and 
vigorous character sustained that feeble despot on his throne. 
Unfortunately for him and Dionysius, Dion did not take the 
usual course when he sailed from Zacynthus to Sicily ; 
Philistus, who was waiting to intercept him in the waters of 
Tarentum, had no opportunity of meeting him at sea, and 
Dionysius had foolishly absented himself from the capital, so 
that Dion was enabled to possess himself of Achradina and a 
great part of Syracuse; and Heracleides having come with a 
fleet to his assistance, all the hopes of the dynasty were centred 





1 Diodorus merely says (XV. 7), that Philistus and Leptines were among the 
number of his friends whom Dionysius was led ἐπὶ ψεύδεσιν αἰτίαις ἀνελεῖν, He 
implies, too, that Philistus and Leptines were both reconciled to the elder Diony- 
sius and restored to his favour. But Plutarch, in his life of Dion (c. 11), distinctly 
says, that Philistus was banished because Leptines had ‘given him one of his 
daughters in marriage μηδὲ φράσας πρὸς Διονύσιον ; that Dionysius imprisoned his 
niece, and banished his old supporter, who did not return τοῦ πρεσβυτέρου ζῶντος. 
Tt is also clear, from what Philistus said of his wife’s degradation (apud Plut. 
Timol. 15), that Leptines also must have remained a long time in banishment, 

2 Pausan. I. 13, ὃ 9. 

8 Corn. Nepos, Dion, 3: ‘quumque Dion non desineret obsecrare Dionysium, 
ut Platonem Athenis arcesseret et ejus consiliis uteretur, ille, qui in aliqua re 
vellet patrem imitari, Philistum historicum Syracusas reduxit, hominem amicum 
non magis tyranno quam tyrannidi.’ Plutarch (Dion, 36), says, that Philistus was 
φιλοτυραννότατος ἀνθρώπων. 


Vou. II. ¢ ¢ 


386 RHETORICAL HISTORIANS AND ANTIQUARIES. 


in Philistus, who, after undertaking an expedition against the 
revolted Leontini, and after several skirmishes with the enemy 
at Syracuse, engaged Heracleides in the great harbour, was de- 
feated, and had his ship driven ashore.’ To escape imprisonment, 
he stabbed himself; but the wound was not mortal, and he 
fell into the hands of the enemy, who stripped him, and, after 
insulting him, cut off his head, dragged him by the leg through 
the streets of Syracuse, and finally flung his body into the 
Latomiz.” Such was the miserable end of this courageous and 
energetic supporter of the Sicilian usurpers. As he was nearly 
eighty years old, he could not have engaged in active life for 
many years longer, and if he had escaped with his life from 
the troubles of the counter-revolution, he must have encoun- 
tered again the banishment which he bore with so much impa- 
tience. Mr. Grote has well remarked* that ‘ the last hopes of 
the Dionysian dynasty perished with Philistus, the ablest and 
most faithful of its servants. He had been an actor in its first 
day of usurpation—its eighteenth Brumaire: his timely, though 
miserable, death, saved him from sharing in its last day of 
exile—its St. Helena.’ 

In his confused and blundering notice of Philistus, the 
lexicographer Suidas mentions a number of works which must, in 
all probability, be divided between him, Philiscus, Naucrates, and 
perhaps several other writers.“ There is no reason to believe 
that he wrote anything himself, except the great Sicilian history, 
on which his literary reputation depends. This was divided 
into two distinct portions. The first part, in seven books, 
comprised the history from the earliest times to the capture of 
Agrigentum, in B.c. 406, a period of more than 800 years. The 
second part, in four books, contained the history of the reign of 





1 Diodor. XVI. 9-11, 16; Plutarch, Dion, 25, 35. σι Steph. ΒυΖ. s.v. Δύμη 
from the fortieth book of Phécpoitpta: 

2 According to Plutarch, Dion, 35, Ephorus stated ὡς ἁλισκομένης τῆς νεὼς 
ἑαυτὸν ἀνέλοι, but Timonides, an eye-witness, gave the account which is repeated 
in the text. 

5. XT. Ὁ, 130. 

4 Of the works which Suidas attributes to Philistus, it may be concluded that 
the τέχνη ῥητορική and δημηγορίαι should be assigned to Philiscus, who was also, — 
perhaps, the author of the reply to the Ἰϊρικάρανος of Anaximenes. The treatise 
περὶ Φοινίκης was probably written by Philinus of Agrigentum, who fiourished in 
the time of the first Punic war. 


PHILISTUS. 387 


the elder Dionysius. In a supplement of two books he nar- 
rated the events of the first five years of Dionysius the younger, 
thus carrying down his contemporary memoirs to within seven 
years of his death. The remainder of the reign of Dionysius 
the younger was written by Arnanis' of Syracuse. 

_ The contents of the eleven books, which Philistus wrote 
before he returned from exile, are thus assigned by a modern 
scholar :°-—The first book contained the history of Cocalus ;* the 
second described the foundation of the various Greek colonies ;* 
the third carried down the history to the times of Gelo;* the 
fourth probably contained the reigns of Thero and Thrasybulus ;° 
the fifth comprised the most flourishing period of Sicily, after 
the expulsion of the tyrants ;’ the sixth following closely in the 
steps of Thucydides*® narrated the war with Athens; the seventh 
was devoted to the legislation of Diocles and the wars with the 
Carthaginians ;° the eighth book described the rise of Dionysius 
and his operations against Carthage ;” the ninth the establish- 
ment of the tyranny and the peace with the Carthaginians ;” 
the tenth the second Carthaginian war ;” and the eleventh the 
third war with Carthage, that with Rhegium, and the death 
and funeral of Dionysius the elder.” 

All the ancient critics are agreed that Philistus was an 
imitator of Thucydides, and was very inferior to his model." 
The attempt, however, to rival the Attic historian led at least 
to one consequence, the adoption of the Attic dialect, which 
was becoming more and more the literary language of Greece. 
It may be inferred from several circumstances that the literary 
talents of Philistus were not eminent, and that his merits con- 





1 This seems to be the true spelling of the name, which is sometimes corrupted 
into “Adavs, ᾿Αθάνης, ᾿Αθάνας. Cf. Diod. XV. 94; Plut. Timol. ec. 23, 37; 
Athen. IIT. 98 D; and see Creuzer, Histor. Kunst. d. Griechen, 2nd ed. p. 308, 

2 Goller, De situ Syracusarum, pp. 125-132. 

3 Diod. V. 2-6. 4 Strabo, VI. p. 409. 

5 Diod. IX. § Id. XI, 38-68. 

7 Id, XI. 67, 68 ; ΧΤΙ. 82. 

8 Theo, Progymn. p. 9: τὸν ᾿Αττικὸν ὅλον πόλεμον “ἐν τοῖς Σικελικοῖς ἐκ τοῦ 
Θουκυδίδου μετενήνοχε. Cf. Plut. Nic. c. 1. 

9 Diod. XIII. 34-96. 10 Td. ibid. 91-108, 

ἢ Jd. ibid. 108 ; XIV. το. 12 74, XIV. 14-76, 

1S Td. XIV. 76; XV. 74. 

14 Quintil. X. 1; Dionys. Hal. vol. V. p. 427; VI. p. 779 sqq. 

Ce 2’ 


388 RHETORICAL HISTORIANS AND ANTIQUARIES. 


sisted in the accuracy of his facts, and in the soundness of his 
practical judgment, rather than in the form or style of his 
narratives. These last qualities he must have possessed in a 
considerable degree, for Cicero not only calls him ‘a miniature 
Thucydides,’ but designates him by epithets which, if they do 
not all convey definite ideas, are at least significant of no little 
praise ;' and the history of Philistus was included in the select 
list of books which Harpalus sent to Alexander the Great while 
he was in Asia2 On the other hand, we are told that his 
works were neglected at an early period,*® and perhaps were not 
finally included in the Alexandrian canon ;* that his narratives, 
and the speeches introduced into his history, were dull and 
monotonous; and that he did not diversify the regular parade 
of his facts by any of those amusing digressions which were 
found in the histories of his predecessors and contemporaries.’ 
The compilations of Diodorus, however, cannot stand in the place 
of authentic contemporary history like that of Philistus, and we 
must, therefore, regret that the rhetorical fancies of the Alex- 
andrian school have prevented us from possessing at least the 
latter half of his Sicilian annals. 

§ 6. By the side of the rhetorical historians, who made 
the narration of events an excuse for displaying their skill in 
the construction of periods, a different class of writers sprung 
up, whose object it was rather to preserve and exhibit the 
authentic materials of history, namely, the old traditions which 
were interwoven with the social and political usages of a nation, 
and the documents contained in inscriptions and other records. 
These monographies, or special treatises on history and an- 
tiquities, were generally confined to the discussion of the affairs 





1 Cicero says (ad Quint, fr. IL 13): ‘itaque ad Callisthenem et ad Philistum 
redeo, in quibus te video volutatum. Callisthenes quidem vulgare et notum ne- 
gotium, quemadmodum Greci aliquot locuti sunt. Siculus ille capitalis, creber, 
acutus, brevis, peene pusillus Thucydides.’ The meaning of this passage is fully 
discussed by Muretus (var. lect. II. 5) who shows, against Ρ, Manutius, that capi- — 
talis is a synonym for ingeniosus, See also Creuzer, wu. 8. p. 310. 

2 Plut. Alex. c. 8, 8 Cicero, Brut. 6. 17. 

4 C, Miller (Fr. Hist. Gr. p. XLIX.) expressly states—‘ Philistus in Alexan- 
drinum historicorum canonem non est receptus.’ On the other hand, Creuzer (u. 8. 
p- 304) says: ‘was nun den Philistos betrifft, so gehirt er allerdings unter die 
kanonischen Historiker.’ 

5 Theo, Progymn. p. 44: 


THE ATTHIDES. 389 


of Attica, and every one of the writers of this class composed 
an Atthis (Ar@ic),—an adjective which denotes ‘an Attic 
history’ (Aric συγγραφή). This was the name which, at a 
later period, Pausanias gave to the particular section of his 
Periegesis in which he treated of Attica, and it is supposed 
that the Atthis of Melesagoras, or Amelesagoras of Chalcedon, 
was a similar compilation, by a writer of the Alexandrian 
school, from the older works of which we are now speaking.’ 
These older Atthides may be compared with works like those 
of John Stow, William Camden, and Sir William Dugdale, and 
the modern county histories which have.succeeded them. The 
nature of the original Atthides has been described and imitated 
by ancient and modern writers. Dionysius of Halicarnassus 
says that he has not endeavoured to give his work a form ‘like 
those mere annals, which the writers of the Atthides have 
elaborated, for these are very monotonous, and soon offend the 
hearers.’? Niebuhr thought that the writers of the Afthides, 
‘who wrote the history of the oldest times diplomatically, with 
reference to laws and public decrees, and in chronological order,’ 
would have been of inestimable value to us.* And C. O. 
Miiller considered Béckh’s Public Economy of Athens as a 
specimen of ‘ what an Afthis would be, according to the style 
of the old writers of the Atthides, who treated as an essential 
part of history all that is most important in political and 
religious antiquities, if it were carried out with the enlarged 
views and comprehensive learning of modern times.’ * 

Of these special chroniclers and antiquaries, eight are known to 
us by name—Cleidemus or Cleitodemus,’ Phanodemus, Demon, 
Androtion, Philochorus, Ister, Andron, and Melanthius. The 
last two are merely cited once or twice, and we know nothing 
about them. The other six have left fragments more or less 





1 Miiller, Fr. Hist. Gr. p. LX Χ ΧΤ, 

2 Antig. Rom. I. 8, p. 23, Reiske: σχῆμα δὲ ἀποδίδωμι τῇ mpayuarela.... 
οὔτε Tats χρονικαῖς παραπλήσιον ἃς ἐξέδωκαν οἱ ras ᾿Ατθίδας πραγματευόμενοι" μονοει- 
δεῖς γὰρ ἐκεῖναί τε καὶ ταχὺ προσιστάμεναι τοῖς ἀκούουσιν. 

3 Kleine Schriften, I. p. 225. 

* Orchomenos und die Minyer, p. 13. 

5 Both names occur, and are both represented under the corrupt readings καὶ 
Δῆμος and καὶ ὁ Δῆμος, which appear in citations from this writer ; but the balance 
of authority is rather in favour of the shorter form. 


890 RHETORICAL HISTORIANS AND ANTIQUARIES. 


numerous in the works of ancient historians, scholiasts, and 
lexicographers. 

Ciripemus, the most ancient writer of an Althis, was a 
native of Athens,’ and seems to have been a contemporary of 
Isocrates and Plato. We learn at least that he spoke as an 
eye-witness of the expedition to Sicily,’ and that his Althis 
referred in the third book to the Symmorie at Athens,’ which 
were not instituted till the archonship of Nausinicus, in 8.0, 
378, the year of the death of Lysias. It does not, however, 
result from this that the whole work was first published after 
the year of Nausinicus. If we adopt the reasonable inference 
that the book called Protogony (Ipwroyovia) was really the 
first part of the Atthis,* which in its complete form consisted of 
at least twelve books,’ we may conclude that this at least was 
published by itself, and probably at an earlier period. We are 
almost disposed to think that Plato, in his Phedrus, makes a 
direct reference to the first book of this Protogony, or first 
part of the Aithis, of Cleidemus.° If so, and if, as we have 
suggested, the Phedrus was published soon after Plato’s 
ransom from bondage in 8.0. 387,’ the Protogony was a new 
book about that time. Besides his Atthis, Cleidemus is said 
to have written an ‘ Exposition’ or ‘ Rationale’ (᾿Εξηγητικόν), 
in verse, of the old customs of the Athenians, and a book 





1 He is mentioned among Athenians only in Plutarch De glor. Athen. II. p. 345, 
and he is quoted for the word πρύξ, which is said to occur only in Attic writers. 
Harpocr. 8. v. Πνυκί, 

2 Pausan. X. 15. 

3 Photius s. v. Navxpapla. The writer of the article Cleidemus, in Smith’s 
Dictionary of Biography, &c., I. p. 782, says: ‘We cannot fix the exact period at 
which Cleidemus flourished, but it must have been subsequently to Β.0, 479, since 
Plutarch refers to his account of the battle of Platea (Plut. Arist. 19)!’ : 

* Creuzer (Hist. kunst. d. Gr. p. 353) says: ‘Protogonia, héchst wahrscheinlich 
keine besondere Schrift, sondern das erste Buch der Atthis.’ But there were three 
books of the Protogony (Harpocr. s. v. IIvux(), and it is in the third book of the 
Atthis that we find the reference to the Symmorie. We presume then that the 
Protogony in three books was published first, and that additions were made when 
the work was completed at a subsequent period. 

5 Hesych.’Ayaueuvévera φρέατα. Κλείδημος ἐν τῇ ιβ' τῆς ᾿Ατθίδος. 

6 Cleidemus is quoted in the first book of his Atthis (Pausan. Grammat. ap, 
Bekker. Anecd. p. 326 sq.) for some information about the site mentioned in the 
Phedrus, p. 229 0. 

7 Above, ch, XXXIX, § 6, p. 221 [61]. 


PHANODEMUS, DEMON, ANDROTION. 391 


called ‘The Returns’ (Νόστοι), in which the vicissitudes of 
Peisistratus were narrated at length. There can be little 
doubt that Cleidemus was a careful and accurate antiquarian. 
He is praised by Plutarch for the originality and ingenuity 
with which he treated the old legends, and the same writer 
attributes to him the wish to investigate every particular with 
the minutest diligence. We can recognize these qualities in 
the fragments which have come down to us, and can discern 
in him that faculty of reconstructive rationalism which traces 
the foundation of fact under the most elaborate superstructure 
of mythology. 

Puanopemvus, who was probably a native of Icus, one of the 
Cyclades, seems to have been a contemporary of Theopompus, 
who is said to have written against him.’ Besides an Aéthis 
in at least nine books,’ he wrote special treatises on the islands 
of Delos (Δηλιακά) and Icus (Ἰκιακά). We infer from the 
references to him that he was distinguished by considerable 
learning and critical acuteness. In giving an account of 
Cimon’s victory in Cyprus, he estimates the Persian fleet at 
600 ships instead of 350, the number given by Ephorus ;* but 
this does not prove, as has been rather hastily assumed,* that he 
was guilty of patriotic exaggeration. 

Demon was a contemporary of Philochorus, who wrote his 
own Aithis to correct or oppose that of Demon.’ This author 
does not seem to have enjoyed much reputation for judgment, 
_and even his good faith has been doubted. For example, what 
he says about the oracular kettles at Dodona® is regarded as 
a wilful fable.” Demon’s AZthis was at least in four books,® 
and the few fragments which remain are chiefly references to 
mythology and religious observances. Besides the Atthis, he 
wrote a book on Proverbs (περὶ παροιμιῶν) and another on 
Sacrifices (περὶ θυσιῶν). 

It seems to be an almost general opinion that ANpRoTIoN, 
the writer of the Atthis, was not the same person as the orator 





1 Proclus ad Platonis Timeum, p. 30. 

® The ninth book is quoted by Harpocration, 5. v. Λεωκόρειον. 

3 Plut. Cimon, 12. 4 By Miiller, p. LX XX VII. 

5 Harpocration, 5. ν. ᾿Ηετιωνία, 6. Fragm. 17, 18. 

7 Miller, p, LXXXVII. 8 Δήμων ἐν τετάρτῳ Ατθίδος. Athen. p..96 D. 


392 RHETORICAL HISTORIANS AND ANTIQUARIES. 


of that name, for whose impeachment Demosthenes wrote an 
oration.’ But the biography of Isocrates’ identifies the orator 
with the historian, and the school of Isocrates, to which the 
orator Androtion belonged, was also, as we have seen, a school 
for historical writers. And not only is there no antecedent 
improbability in this identification, but it tends to explain the 
fact mentioned by Plutarch, that among the eminent writers 
who composed their histories in exile, Androtion, the Athenian, 
wrote his at Megara.’ For, from the writers mentioned along 
with him, we should infer that Androtion the historian was a 
man of some political eminence, like the pupil of Isocrates, to 
whom Demosthenes was opposed. If he was the same person, 
we have a very unfavourable record of his character and con- 
duct in the speeches of Demosthenes against him and his par- 
tizan Timocrates. The Atthis of Androtion, which comprised at 
least twelve books,‘ and was carried down to the 96th Olympiad,’ 
if not to a later year, did not differ in kind from the other 
works of this class. He is classed with Philochorus as having 
written very completely (ἐντελέστατα) about the municipal 
scrutinies (διαψηφίσεις)." His authority is cited doubtfully by 
fflian’ and Pausanias,* and he indulges in speculative mythology 
like the rest of his school. It appears that he arranged his 
history according to the archons at Athens.’ 

PuitocHorvs, who was perhaps the most eminent writer of 
his class, was a native of Athens,” and took an active part in 
the political affairs of that city from B.c. 306, when, in his 





1 Above, ch. XLI. § 3. 2 p. XI. Dindorf. 

3 De Exilio, p. 605 C, Ὁ. p. 439 Wyttenb.: καὶ γὰρ τοῖς παλαιοῖς ὡς ἔοικεν αἱ 
Μοῦσαι τὰ κάλλιστα τῶν συνταγμάτων Kal δοκιμώτατα φυγὴν λαβοῦσαι συνεργὸν 
ἐπετέλεσαν. And after mentioning that Thucydides of Athens wrote his history 
at Scaptesyle, Xenophon at Scillus, Philistus in Epirus, Timeus at Athens, he 
adds: ᾿Ανδροτίων ᾿Αθηναῖος ἐν Μεγάροις. 

4 ws ᾿Ανδροτίων ἐν δωδεκάτῃ Ατθίδοςς. Harpocr. 5. v. ᾿Αμφίπολις. 

5 He is quoted by Harpocration, 5. v. Ξενικὸν ἐν Κορίνθῳ, for a fact which is 
referred to Ol. 96, 3. 

6 Harpocr. s. v. διαψηφίσεις. 

7 V.H. VIII. 6: ταῦτα ᾿Ανδροτίων λέγει, ef rw πιστός. 

8 VI. 7: ef δὲ τὸν ὄντα εἶπεν ᾿Ανδροτίων λόγον. 

9. Schol. Aristoph. Nubes, 540. 

10 The notice in Suidas is; Φιλόχορος, Κ ύκνου, ᾿Αθηναῖος, μάντις καὶ ἱεροσκόπος. 


PHILOCHORUS. 393 


capacity as a public seer, he interpreted the appearance of a 
dog in the Parthenon as indicating the return of the exiles,’ 
‘down to the year 8.0. 260, when Antigonus Gonatas took 
possession of Athens, and had Philochorus put to death as an 
adherent of Ptolemy Philadelphus, who had aided the city in 
its opposition to the Macedonians? From these scanty par- 
ticulars we can infer that Philochorus belonged to a priestly 
family, that he was, as far as the times admitted, a zealous 
patriot, directly opposed to the tyranny which Demetrius 
Poliorcetes exercised under the cloak of freedom, and that he 
fell a sacrifice to his anti-Macedonian efforts when Antigonus 
Gonatas restored his father’s influence in the city. 

We have a long list of the writings of Philochorus. They 
were as follows : 

(I.) His Atthis (Aric, also called ᾿Ατθίδες and ‘Ieropiat), a 
history of Attica from the first beginnings of the human race 
to the time of Antiochus Theus, in seventeen books.* The 
first two books are devoted to mythology, and the explanation 
of religious observances ; the next four carry down the history 
to the author’s times, and Béckh has conjectured that these 

first six books formed a separate work, published originally by 
itself. The remaining eleven books are occupied with contem- 
porary history. Philochorus enjoyed the highest reputation 
for laborious accuracy and sound critical judgment, and the 
numerous fragments, which are still extant, show that he 





γυνὴ δὲ ἣν αὐτῷ ᾿Αρχεστράτη. κατὰ δὲ τοὺς χρόνους γέγονεν ὁ ᾧ. ᾿Ερατοσθένους ὡς 
ἐπιβαλεῖν πρεσβυτῇ νέον ὄντα ᾿Ερατοσθένει. It is clear that this statement of the 
relative ages of Philochorus and Eratosthenes must be wrong; for the event 
referred to is the occupation of Athens by Antigonus Gonatas, in Β.0. 262, and 
Eratosthenes died an old man in B.c. 196. It is, therefore, proposed to read in 
Suidas; κατὰ τοὺς χρόνους yéy. ᾧ. ᾿Ερατοσθένους, ws ἐπιβαλεῖν πρεσβύτῃ νεανίαν or 
νέον ὄντα ᾿Ερατοσθένην. 

. 7 Apud Dionys. Hal. De Dinarcho judicium, p. 637, Reiske: ἡμεῖς δ᾽ ἐρωτη- 
θέντες ὑπέρ Te τοῦ σημεῖου Kal τοῦ φαντάσματος εἰς ὃ φέρει, φυγάδων κάθοδον ἔφαμεν 
προσημαίνειν ἀμφότερα. . ,. καὶ τὴν κρίσιν ἐπιτελεσθῆναι συνέβη. 

2 Suidas: ἐτελεύτησε δὲ ἐνιδρευθεὶς ὑπὸ ᾿Αντιγόνου ὅτι διεβλήθη προσκεκλικέναι 
τῇ Πτολεμαίου βασιλείᾳ. 

3 Τῇ Schol. Vict. ad Hom. Il. =. 370, we read: ἡ δὲ κατὰ Λίνον ἱστορία παρὰ 
Φιλοχόρῳ ἱστορεῖται ἐν τῇ ιθ΄. But Béckh (De Philochoro, Berol. 1832), proposes 
to read ἐν τῇ ᾿Ατθίδι. And this may be a reference to the treatise περὶ εὑρημάτων, 
perhaps an appendix to the Atthis. . 


394 RHETORICAL HISTORIANS AND ANTIQUARIES. 


spared no pains in the collection of his facts, and that he 
expressed himself in elegant and unaffected language. 

(II.) An abridgment of his Aéthis (ἐπιτομὴ τῆς ἰδίας ᾿Ατθίδος). 
It may be doubted whether this is not the same book as the 
epitome of Philochorus drawn up by Asinius Pollio of Tralles, 
probably a learned freedman of the celebrated Roman of the 
same name.’ Some have accounted for the existence of two 
abridgments by supposing that one was made by Philochorus 
himself for the use of his countrymen, the other by the later 
Greek writer for the use of the Romans. But it seems to us 
very unlikely that Philochorus would think it worth his while 
to engage in a work, which would probably have superseded 
his more elaborate book, as Justin’s epitome has superseded the 
longer history of Trogus Pompeius; and it is clear that our 
fragments are taken from the fullest form of the Atthis, which 
must therefore have been in the hands of the comparatively 
recent writers to whom we owe these citations. And, on the 
whole, we are inclined to think that the only epitome was that 

of Asinius Trallianus. 

(III.) A confutation of the Atthis of Demon (πρὸς τὴν Δήμω- 
νος ᾿Ατθίδα, or ἡ πρὸς Δήμωνα avTvypapn),” which was probably 
criticism of the rival history, and not another name for the 
elaborate Atihis of Philochorus. 

(IV.) On the Athenian Archons from Socratides (B.c. 374) to 
Apollodorus (B.c. 350 or B.c. 319, probably the latter) (περὶ 
τῶν ᾿Αθήνησι ἀρξάντων ἀπὸ Σωκρατίδου μεχρὶ ᾿Απολλοδώρου). 
This was, perhaps, one of the accessary labours of his Aéthis, 
If it went down to the time of the later Apollodorus, it was 
probably the introduction to the last eleven books, which were 
devoted to his contemporary history, and may have followed 
the publication of the six preceding books.’ 

(V.) On the Olympiads (Ὀλυμπιάδες ev βιβλίοις β΄). It 
seems that Philochorus, who paid great attention to chronology, 
was not satisfied with the dates as given by the years of the 
Archons, but afterwards, perhaps following the example of 





1 Suidas, ἸΤωλίων, ὁ ᾿Ασίνιος χρηματίσας, Τραλλιανός, σοφιστὴς καὶ φιλόσοφος" 
σοφιστεύσας ἐν Ῥώμῃ ἐπὶ Πομπηΐου τοῦ μεγάλου καὶ διαδεξάμενος τὴν σχολὴν τοῦ 
Τιμαγένους, ἔγραψεν ἐπιτομὴν τῆς Φιλοχόρου ᾿Ατθίδος, κ.τ.λ. “ἢ 

2 Harpocration, s.v. ᾿ ετιωνία, 3 Miiller, p. LXXXIX, ~ 








ISTER. 395 


Timeeus, investigated the succession of the Olympiads, and 
published the results of his researches in these two books.’ 

(VI.) On the four cities, (ποθ, Marathon, Probalinthus, and 
Trycorythus (περὶ τῆς τετραπόλεως), a monograph on the 
mythology and religious observances of these places, which 
may, after all, have been an extract from the first two eke 
of his Atthis.? 

(VII.) A collection of Attic inscriptions (ἐπιγράμματα ve 
Tika), intended most probably as a documentary appendix to his 
great work, and forming the first collection of the kind which 
had appeared in Greece. From the nature of the case, it is not 
probable that these were ‘ only poetical inscriptions,’ as Bockh 
once supposed,* and as those of Polemo appear to have been. It 
is more likely that they were decrees and treaties, and, as Bockh 
now says, ‘ varii generis inscriptiones.’ * 

The other sixteen titles of works attributed to Philochorus 
refer to-publications, partly of an antiquarian description,’ 
partly belonging to his professional occupation as a priest and 
soothsayer,’ partly treating of subjects of literary criticism and 
biography.’ From this brief survey we can see that Philo- 
chorus was a most important writer, and it is perhaps impos- 
sible to estimate the amount of information which we have 
received at second-hand from him. 

_ To complete the list of these writers, we must mention IsTER, 
who belongs, however, to the Alexandrian school. He was a 
native of Cyrene, the slave and afterwards the friend of 





1 Miiller, iid.; Creuzer, Histor. Kunst. p. 357. 

2 We have a specimen of this book in Suidas, s.v. Tcravlda γῆν, where Attica is 
said to have been the abode of Titenius, the only Titan who did not make war on 
the Gods. ; 

3 Public Economy of Athens, book II. c. 8, p. 197, Lewis’ Transl. Suidas says, 
8.0. ἐπίγραμμα" πάντα τὰ ἐπιγραφόμενά τισι κἂν μὴ ἐν μέτροις εἰρημένα, ἐπιγράμ- 
para λέγεται. 

4 Corpus Inscript. pref. p. VIII. 

5 As the six works, ᾿Ηπειρωτικά, Δηλιακά 6’, περὶ τῶν ᾿Αθήνησι ἀγώνων ιζ΄, περὶ 
ἑορτῶν, περὶ ἡμερῶν, Σαλαμῖνος κτίσις. 

6 As the six works, περὶ θυσιῶν, περὶ μαντικῆς 5’, περὶ καθαρμῶν, περὶ μυστηρίων 
τῶν ᾿Αθήνησι, ἡ πρὸς "Αλυπον ἐπιστολή, ἐπιτομὴ τῆς Διονυσίου πραγματείας περὶ 
ἱερῶν. 

7 As the four treatises, περὲ ᾿Αλκμᾶνος, περὶ τῶν Σοφοκλέους μύθων βιβλία ἐ, 
περὶ Εὐριπίδου, συναγωγὴ ἩἩρωΐδων ἤτοι ἸΤυθαγορείων γυναικῶν. 


896 RHETORICAL HISTORIANS AND ANTIQUARIES. 


Callimachus, whom he accompanied to Alexandria. He lived 
there, or at Paphus in Cyprus, at that time part of the Egyptian 
monarchy, in the reign of Ptolemy Euergetes, between B.c. 250 
and 220. He was, like most of the Alexandrian writers, a 
poet and grammarian, as well as a compiler of histories. 
Besides an Afthis, in at least sixteen books,’ he wrote a variety 
of works on local history, religious traditions, and literary 
criticism. It was he who gave to the censorious Timzeus the 
appropriate nickname ‘Eztriuatoc.2 He was himself severely 
criticised by Polemo, the celebrated collector of inscriptions,* 
who said that he deserved to be immerged in the great river 
from which he derived his name.‘ 





1 Harpocration, s.v. Τραπεζοφόρος. 2 Atheneus, VI. p. 272 B. 

3 He was called στηλοκόπης, ‘the tablet picker,’ and was ‘a sort of Old Mor- 
tality, who used to go about copying the inscriptions on public monuments’ 
(Liddell and Scott, s.v.). 

4 Athenzus, IX. p. 387 F: Πολέμων ὁ περιηγητὴς Ἴστρον τὸν Καλλιμάχειον 
συγγραφέα els τὸν ὁμώνυμον κατεπόντου ποταμόν, 


397 


CHAPTER XLIV. 


MEDICAL LITERATURE—WRITINGS ATTRIBUTED TO 
HIPPOCRATES, 


§ 1. Life of Hippocrates. § 2. Origin and growth of medical literature among the 
Greeks. ὃ 3. Genuine works of Hippocrates. ὃ 4. Doubtful works. ὃ 5. 
Spurious works. ὃ 6. Publication of the Hippocratic collection, ὃ 7. Style 
and literary merits of Hippocrates. 


δι, J) EFORE we take leave of the classical period, we must 

go back to a contemporary of Socrates, who enjoys 
a reputation not unlike that of Homer; for while he represents 
acomplete department or school of Greek literature, his personal 
existence is very shadowy and unsubstantial, and his claim to 
the writings, which are attributed to him, must in many cases 
be rejected, and in others admitted with no little doubt and 
uncertainty." Among those who, with different objects, en- 
deavoured to improve or acquire a rhetorical style by attending 
the lectures of Gorgias, was Hrrrocratres, the son of 
Heracleides and Phzenarete,’ the hereditary chief of a renowned 
school of medicine, which had long been established in the 
island of Cos. One at least of his predecessors, and some 
three or four of his successors, bore the same name, and being 
the most eminent of the family and school, he has perhaps been 





1 The best modern authorities for the literary biography of Hippocrates, which 
are known to us, are the elaborate introduction to E. Littiré’s ures Completes 
@ Hippocrate, vol. I. Paris, 1839, and the excellent articles by Bahr, in Pauly’s 
Real-Encyclopidie, vol. III. Stuttgart, 1844, and by Dr. Greenhill, in Smith’s 
Dictionary of Greek and Roman Biography and Mythology, vol. II. Lond. 
1854. 

2 By one of those fortuitous coincidences, which amuse if they do not 
instruct, the mother of Socrates, the father of later Greek philosophy, and 
of Hippocrates, the founder of medical literature, bore the same name. Those 
who believe that talent is inherited from the mother, and that mother-wit 


is not an idle phrase, will perhaps think that both of the Phenarete’s justified 
their name. 


398 - MEDICAL LITERATURE. 


made responsible for the actions and writings of the whole race.’ 
The contemporary references to him are very scanty, and only 
sufficient to establish his existence, and we are left for all 
details to a late biography attributed to Soranus—a name 
belonging to many medical writers from the time of Trajan 
downwards,’—and to a number of legends which have sprung 
up in the various countries, where Hippocrates has been received 
as the father of the art of healing. 

The following particulars constitute the biography of the 
great Hippocrates. He was born Ol. 80, 1. B.c. 460, on the 
26th day of the month Agrianus, which the inhabitants of Cos 
celebrated as his natal day.’ He claimed descent from the two 
deities, who were regarded as the helpers and healers of man- 
kind, being the nineteenth, or, as some say, the seventeenth,’ 
in the direct line from Aisculapius, the god of medicine in 
general, and the twentieth from Hercules, the heroic cleanser of 
infested neighbourhoods,’ the maker of roads,° and the patron 





¥ The following table is given by Dr. Greenhill :— 








Nebrus 
| 

a 
Gnosidicus Chrysus 

, | 
| 

Hippocrates I. Podaleirius ®neius Elaphus 
Hippolochus, 


Pheenarete = Hippocrates 11. Cadmus 





Sosander Hrerocratess IT. = Uxor 





| | | 
Thessalus Filia = Polybus Dracon I. 





| ; 
| | Hippocrates IV.? 
Gorgias Hippocrates ITT, Dracon IT. 


Hippocrates IV.? 


Dracon ITI, 


2 Tzetzes (Chiliad. VII. c. 155) merely borrows from Soranus. The article in 
Suidas, which is more than usually distinct and consistent, seems also to be derived 
from Soranus, or from the same sources. The coincidences are pointed out in 
Kuster’s notes. 3 Soranus, p. 1297 ad fin. 

4 Soranus makes him the rgth, and Tzetzes, who gives his genealogy, the 17th. _ 

5 Hence the story of Augeas. 6 Aristot, περὶ θαυμασίων ἀκουσμάτων, 6. 85. 


ΓΙ ΨΥ Ν᾿ 





HIPPOCRATES. 899 


of medicinal springs.’ His professional education was, no doubt, 
conducted in the priestly college at Cos, his special instructors 
being his own father, and the celebrated Herodicus, of Selymbria, 
in Thrace, who combined gymnastic training with the medical 
treatment of his patients. It was probably in consequence of 
his literary tastes that he became a pupil of the great sophists, 
Prodicus and Gorgias. His intercourse with Democritus of 
Abdera, who was born in the same year with himself, is rather 
indicated than established by a fictitious correspondence, of 
which two letters, the production no doubt of a later sophist, 
are still extant; and it is clear that they were rather friends 
than related as teacher and pupil.? It is stated, and the state- 
ment is not improbable, that Hippocrates left Cos at an early 
period, and spent a great part of his life in travelling. His 
reputation among his contemporaries, and the familiar mention 
of his name by Athenian writers, seem to show that his 
activity was not confined to the little island off Halicarnassus. 
There is a familiar allusion to him in the Thesmophoriazuse of 
Aristophanes, which was acted in B.c. 411,° and Plato expressly 
mentions Hippocrates of Cos as the most eminent medical man 
of the day in the Protagoras, which, as we have seen, was pro- 
bably written a short time before the death of Socrates. There 
is also reason to believe that Plato was acquainted with the 
writings of this physician, to one of which there is a special 
reference in the Phedrus.2 On the whole, we cannot doubt 





1 Diodorus, V. 3. Schol. Soph. Trachin. 635. 

2 Suidas: οὗτος μαθητὴς γέγονε τὸ μὲν πρῶτον τοῦ πατρός, μετὰ δὲ ταῦτα ‘Hpodixov 
τοῦ Σηλυβριανοῦ καὶ Τοργίου τοῦ Λεοντίνου ῥήτορος καὶ φιλοσόφου" ὡς δέ τινες 
Δημοκρίτου τοῦ ᾿Αβδηρίτου (ἐπιβαλεῖν yap αὐτὸν νέῳ πρεσβυτήν [they were of the 
same age], ὡς δέ τινες καὶ ἸΤροδίκου. With the exception οἵ Prodicus all these 
names are mentioned by Soranus and Tzetzes, 

8 Thesmoph. 270: 

Eup. ὄμνυμι τοίνυν αἰθέρ᾽, οἴκησιν Διός. 
My. τί μᾶλλον ἢ τὴν Ἱπποκράτους ξυνοικίαν ; 
Εὐρ. ὄμνυμι τοίνυν πάντας ἄρδην τοὺς θεούς. 


This is obviously an allusion to the oath of the school of Hippocrates, which 
begins as follows (Hippocr. vol. IV. p. 632, Littré): ὄμνυμι ᾿Απόλλωνα ἰητρὸν καὶ 
᾿Ασκλήπιον καὶ ‘Yyceltav καὶ ἸΤανακείαν καὶ θεοὺς πάντας τε καὶ πάσας, ἵστορας ποιεύ- 
μενος ἐπιτελέα ποιήσειν κατὰ δύναμιν καὶ κρίσιν ἐμὴν ὅρκον τόνδε καὶ ξυγγραφὴν τήνδε. 

4 Protagoras, p. 311 B. See above, ch. XX ΧΤΧ, § 6, p. 222 [62]. 

5 Phedrus, p. 270 C. It had always been thought, on the authority of Galen 


400 MEDICAL LITERATURE. 


that Hippocrates aimed at and obtained a panhellenic reputation 
even in his lifetime; and the best way to effect this would be 
to make himself personally known to the leading communities. 
After a residence of many years in Thasos and at Abdera, he 
spent some time at Athens, and was honoured by an invitation 
to the Prytaneium, by the full franchise, and by initiation at 
Eleusis. It is stated that these honours were the rewards for 
his services during the great plague; but Thucydides, who 
gives such a minute account of that pestilence, makes no men- 
tion of Hippocrates, who says nothing of this disease in his 
writings. It is more likely that his residence at Athens com- 
menced after that time, and continued till- his country fell off 
from the Athenian alliance, some time after 8.0. 411. He 
then took up his abode in Thessaly, and was condemned, in his 
absence, on an indictment preferred against him by Antiphon.' 
Whether the professional and literary labours, which occupied 
the remainder of his long life, were carried on chiefly in Thes- 
saly, or in his native island of Cos, cannot be ascertained, It 
is stated, however, that he died and was buried at Larissa in 
Thessaly,’ and there are reasons, which do not seem to have 
occurred to any of those who have written about Hippocrates, 
for concluding that his connexion with that district was more 
than casual. The name of Hippocrates is more likely to have 





(Tom. V. pp. 2, 16 ed. Basil.), that Plato was here referring to the treatise by 
Hippocrates on the nature of man, or that the work to which he alludes is lost ; 
but Littré argues that the reference in the Phedrus should be ons a with two 
passages, one in the treatise ‘on regimen,’ and the other in that ‘on ancient 
medicine’ (Zuwvres d Hinpocrate, I. pp. 299 sqq-). 

1 Tn the text of the Vite X. Oratorum, p. 833 D, it seems uncertain whether 
we should read ‘Immoxpdrovs τοῦ ἰατροῦ, or τοῦ στρατηγοῦ : but Photius (Cod. 
CCLIX.) has ἰατροῦ only. 

2 The following extract from a recent number of the Medical Times shows that 
this fact in the necrology of Hippocrates is likely to be supported by documentary 
evidence of the best kind : 

‘A good deal of interest has been excited on the continent by the supposed dis- 
covery of the tomb of Hippocrates near Larissa in Thessalia. We have the au- 
thority of Soranus for the belief that Hippocrates died at Larissa, and that his 
tomb was shown between that town and Gyrton. It appears that in 1826 some 
peasants discovered a sarcophagus near Larissa, after an inundation; and two 
Greek gentlemen, named Andreades and (Economides, discovered an inscription on 
the lid, the letters ITIIIOKPAT being plainly visible. Nedjib-bey, the Turkish 
governor, had the tablet carried off, and some coins and a gold chain which were in 


HIPPOCRATES. AOL 


belonged to a noble Thessalian family than to an Asclepiad of 
Cos. We know, from Pindar, that Hippocleas, a very similar 
name, was borne by a wealthy young Thessalian of Pelinnzeum, 
whose victory at Delphi was celebrated at Larissa.!_ The lead- 
ing family in that place, the Aleuadz, boasted, like Hippo- 
crates, that they were Heracleide. Aisculapius himself was 
claimed by the Thessalians.* The principle, according to which 
the name of the son is the epithet of the father,’ gives a special 
value to the fact that the elder son of Hippocrates was called 
Thessalus, while his younger son, Draco, was called after the 
serpent of Aisculapius. From all these circumstances, we are 
disposed to infer that the family of Hippocrates properly 
belonged to Thessaly, and that their connexion with the medical 
school at Cos may have been originally a result of their choice 
of that celebrated seat of the worship of their hereditary god. 





the sarcophagus were stolen, This year Dr. Samartsides found the tablet in the 
house of the bey, and copied the following inscription in ordinary Greek characters :— 


PanMORPAD 4. ΚΩ, τὶ . « ATAAOS., 
> Se 5 ΣΝ ΤΠ ρεν ater eh! δ’, eh > 
Pee het, te oe eM OS 2 DAES, 
ΝΕ τὩἨἨῤ᾿ἰ λα - tAPH) ee ony co BNBEA.; % 

ΡΣ Ut A ae am: ΒΩ, 


* He says he concludes from the form of the letters that they are very ancient. 
There are traces of effaced letters in the spaces marked by dots. The sarcophagus 
remains perfect in the spot where it was found. It remains for some professed 
antiquary to restore the lost letters, and seek for their interpretation ; but nothing 
satisfactory can be done without an exact copy of the inscription either by pho- 
tography or a mould, as it is by the form of the letters and the mode in which they 
are cut, that the age of the inscription must be determined. The name Hippocrates 
is, and has been, a very common one in modern as in ancient Greece, and we want 
something more than the mere inscription of this name upon a stone before it can 
be decided whether the tomb found near Larissa is or is not that of the father of 
medicine.’ 

The copy of the inscription here given can hardly be quite correct. At least the 
words χρηστὲ χαῖρε should be written together as in Béckh, Corp. Inscr., No. 
554, 1, p. 491, pp. 866, 867, &c. The line before seems to have been ἀγαθῇ τύχῃ 
ἀρετῆς ἕνεκα. Aglaophon (’A7yAaogév), which seems to be implied in the first line, 
was a Thasian name, and may have referred to some Thasian friend of Hippocrates. 

1 Pind. Pyth. X. 

3 Pind. Pyth. III. 14, Apollodor. IIT. το, ὃ 3. Strabo, XIV. p. 647. Euseb. 
Prep. Ev. p. 124 A. 

3 Miiller, Dor. I. 3, ὃ το, note F. The fact that Cimon’s son was called Lace- 
demonius is the strictest parallel. 

Vou. 11, DD 


402 : MEDICAL LITERATURE. 


The year of his death is uncertain; it is fixed by different 
ancient writers at Ol. 100, 4. B.c. 377; Ol. 102, 1. B.c. 372; 
Ol. 104, 1. B.c. 364; Ol. 105, 2. B.c. 359; Mr. Clinton" adopts 
the year B.c. 357, which makes him 104 years old at the time 
of his death. The celebrity of Hippocrates had made him almost 
a mythological personage. His journeys to Llyria, Macedonia, 
and Persia,’ though possible in themselves, were probably sug- 
gested by incidents in the lives of Democedes and other famous 
physicians; and the well known story about his discovering 
the love-sickness of Perdiccas II. of Macedon is confuted by the 
chronology ; for the incident refers to a time when Alexander, 
the father of Perdiccas, was still on the throne, and Hippocrates 
was a mere child at the time of that prince’s death.’ 

§ 2. In order that we may appreciate the collection of 
writings attributed to Hippocrates, we must take a brief survey 
of the circumstances under which medical literature sprang up 
among the Greeks. 

There can be no doubt that medicine was at first regarded 
as a branch of the priestly or prophetic office. To ward off or 
alleviate disease was considered as something superhuman. At 
all events, an immediate appeal to heaven was generally pre- 
sumed and required, in order to impart sufficient confidence to 
the patient ; and the superior education and studious habits of 
the priests would naturally make them the first in this as in 
other branches of scientific research. Whatever knowledge the 
priests thus acquired, they communicated only to those who 
were initiated into the mysteries of their temples; and when a 
special deity had been introduced to preside over the relief of 
human ailments, his priests would constitute a medical college, 
in which only those who were connected with the same worship 
would be permitted to graduate. It is clear that these priestly 





BAT; ΤΟ τὰν; 

2 The letter of Artaxerxes about Hippocrates, which is found among the epistles 
of the latter, and is also given by Suidas, is interesting in itself, and may represent 
as genuine a tradition as the letter which Themistocles is said to have addressed to 
the great king. Otesias at all events received and accepted an invitation to the 
Persian court. 

3 It seems most probable that Alexander died about B.c. 454 (Clinten, 7. H. ΤΙ. 
p- 222), .6.,) only six years after the birth of Hippocrates. ; 


BEGINNINGS OF GREEK MEDICINE. 403 


physicians first appeared in Egypt.' The god of medicine 
originally belonged to the elementary worship of that country 
and Syria. He was the son of the god of light, and repre- 
sented the atmosphere necessary to the life and health of man.* 
At a very early period this divinity was adopted by the Greeks, 
who assigned to him a Thessalian origin, and gave him a Greek 
name indicating that he was a Prometheus, or god of fore- 
thought, the inventor of those mild remedies which preserved 
men from pining away in sickness.* His sons, Podaleirius and 
Machaon, whose names admit of a surgical interpretation,’ 
belonged to the heroes of the Trojan war. And though 
Aisculapius was slain by a thunderbolt for restoring a dead 
man to life,» he became himself a recognized divinity. 
Asclepeia, or temples of this divinity, were opened for the cure 
of diseases in many parts of Greece, especially at Epidaurus, in 
Rhodes, Cos, and Cnidos, and in the Libyan colony of Cyrene ; 
and the priest-physicians very soon found it convenient to 
claim descent from the god of healing himself. The mode of 
treatment adopted in these curative establishments was a 
mixture of science and imposture, and, like most medical 





1 The physicians formed a caste in Egypt, and were divided into as many sections 
as the medical men in a modern metropolis. See Herod. II. 84. 
2 Creuzer, Symbolik 11., pp. 558 sqq. 
8 Sickler, die Hieroglyphen in dem Mythus des dZisculap (apud Creuzer, u. 8. p. 
559). . 
4 Whatever may be the oriental affinities of the god of health, it is clear that the 
Greeks fabricated their name for him, and that its elements are contained in the 
well-known lines of Auschylus (Prom. 478 sqq.) : 


el τις els νόσον πέσοι, 
οὐκ ἣν ἀλέξημ᾽ οὐδὲν, οὔτε βρώσιμον, 
οὐ χριστὸν, οὔτε πιστόν, ἀλλὰ φαρμάκων 
χρείᾳ κατεσκέλλοντο, πρὶν ἔγὼ σφίσιν 
ἔδειξα κράσεις ἠπίων ἀκεσμάτων. 


The ancient grammarians saw in the accentuation of the word ᾿Ασκλήπιος a trace 
of its connexion with ἤπιος (see Bickh, Not. Crit. ad Pind. Pyth. III. 6), and the 
first part of the compound is ἀσκελής, an Homeric word, which contains the root of 
κατεσκέλλοντο in the passage just quoted, and is opposed to the Homeric διερός, 
“juicy, full of the sap of life.’ So also in Auschylus (Choeph. 294) the victim of 
wasting death is described as: κακῶς ταριχευθέντα παμφθάρτῳ μόρῳ. 

5 Podaleirius implies the ready aid, and Machaon the surgical knife of the 
Asclepiads. 

6 Pind. Pyth. III. 97. 


404 MEDICAL LITERATURE. 


quacks, the Asclepiads relied in part on influencing th 
imagination of their patients. The sick man, who made appli. 
cation for a cure of his disease at any one of the more cele 
brated temples of /Esculapius, was subjected to a prolongec 
regimen under the name of religious purification. A sort ὁ 
water-cure was combined with fasting, unction, and aperien 
medicine. When the head of the college thought that he wa: 
adequately prepared for the final remedy, the patient was 
admitted to the temple, where he passed the night, and the 
priests took care that the necessary treatment was prescribed tc 
him in the form of a well-arranged theophany.' The success 0 
the treatment adopted was generally aided by the locality choser 
for the Asclepeion, which was situated either on some healthy 
sea coast, or in some cool and sheltered grove, so that the 
change of air and other concomitants assisted in the cure 
Frequented as they were by invalids from all parts of Greece 
these priest-colleges gradually acquired a large amount o 
empirical science, which was duly committed ‘to writing anc 
preserved for the use of the corporation.” These records o: 
cases and their treatment furnished the physicians with ¢ 
sufficient induction for certain generalizations, which wer 
eventually published in the age immediately preceding Hippo. 
crates, in the form of aphorisms. To this class belonged ‘ The 
Cnidian Sentences’ (ai Κνίδιαι γνῶμαι), against which an im. 
portant treatise of Hippocrates is directed. This transference o: 
medical knowledge from the mysterious sanctity of the temple 
to the outer world of literature and science was farther assistec 
by the physical speculations of philosophers like Melissus. 
Parmenides, Empedocles, and others. One of these, Alemzor 
of Crotona, combined the speculative philosopher with the 
practical surgeon, and introduced the indispensable adjunct οἱ 





1 There is an elaborate caricature of one of these scenes in the Asclepeia in the 
Plutus of Aristophanes (vy. 660 foll.), First we have the priest sacking the cakes 
and dried figs from the altars (ταῦθ᾽ ἥγιζεν εἰς σάκταν τινά). Then the representa- 
tive of Aisculapius appears with his two daughters, Iaso and Panacea, and pre: 
pares remedies for the patients ; and the scene is closed by an apparition of the 
tame snakes, whose tongues are supposed to be the immediate agents in the cure. 

5 Pliny, H. N. XXIX. 1, §2; Tzetz. Ohil. VII. 150; Petersen, Hippoerati: 
nomine que circumferuntur scripta ad temporum rationem disposita, Hamburg, 
1839, p. 42, note. 


GREEK PHYSICIANS. 405 


all scientific anatomy—the dissection of animals.’ About the 
same time, the regular Asclepiads began to practise as travelling 
physiciaus (περιοδευταί), and without any reference to the 
sanitary establishments, with their hydropathy and incubations, 
at the temples of the god. As early as the time of Darius, a 
Greek physician, Democedes of Crotona, was in high favour at 
the Persian court, to the discomfiture of the Egyptians pre- 
viously established there,’ and the first foundations were laid of 
that fame of Greek physicians in the east which made Bokrdat, 
as the Arabic writers call Hippocrates, an oriental celebrity even 
in the middle ages. Then, again, Herodicus of Selymbria, the 
teacher of Hippocrates, introduced the curative treatment of 
the Asclepeia, so far as it depended on bodily exercises, into 
the regular gymnasia or places of training, and he is re- 
proached by Plato* as having introduced a system of nosotrophy 
for the benefit of feeble frames, to which a prolonged existence 
did not of right belong. Thus ventilated in every way—by the 
philosophical school, the travelling physician, and the palestra 
—medicine was certain to establish itself as a branch of lite- 
rature ; and the circumstance, which probably gave Hippocrates 
his epochal position, was simply the fact that he was the first 
regular Asclepiad who was enabled to get a complete literary 
and rhetorical training, and so to enlist the muses in the cause 
of his special profession. In the succeeding age, as we have 
seen,’ Aristotle, the greatest literary man of Greece, came forth 
from the schools of the Asclepiads, and starting with the 
physiological acquirements peculiar to his school, combined 
with this all the knowledge of his age, and sounded all the 
depths of natural and moral science. 

Hippocrates himself, though he professed to be a philosopher, 
never digressed from his own proper subject-matter, and being 
the first who gave medicine a recognized and important position 
in literature,’ it was not unnatural that he should in a sub- 





ΟἹ Littré, I. p. 14. 2 Herod. III. 130 sqq. 

3 Respublica, III. p. 406 A, sqq. 4 See above, chapter XL. § 1. 

® Cicero seems to consider elegance of style a not unusual characteristic of 
medical writers: ‘si, id quod multi, medicus de morbis diserte dixerit’ (De Ora- 
tore, Il. 9, ὃ 38). It was this acquisition of the literary franchise which may be 
especially attributed to Hippocrates. 


406 MEDICAL LITERATURE. 


sequent generation monopolize the credit due to a large body 
of fellow-workers in this department, and so become invested 
with the authorship of the principal works on disease and its 
remedies which were published in his time, or immediately 
before and after him. And this tendency would be increased 
by the wish of the library-collectors at Alexandria and Pergamus 
to get as many as possible of his works, a demand which of 
course increased the supply, when the only labour imposed 
upon the bookseller was an alteration of the title of the 
manuscript. 

§ 3. The Hippocratic collection of medical treatises is 
divided, according to the usual classification in such cases, into 
three classes—the genuine, the doubtful, and the spurious. 
The books belonging to the first and third of these classes are 
received or rejected with a certain amount of confidence; the 
doubtful works are those of which it can only be said that they 
were perhaps written by Hippocrates. It was necessary, even in 
early days, to draw up a canon distinguishing the authentic 
works of Hippocrates from those which were falsely or erro- 
neously attributed to him, and the critics of Alexandria had 
comprised the former in a little tablet (μικρὸν πινακίδιον). 
This list is unfortunately lost. Erotianus, who dedicates the 
work to Andromachus, Nero’s chief physician, drew up a cata- 
logue of the writings of Hippocrates, not exactly corresponding 
to those which have come down to us, and also compiled a 
glossary to the Hippocratic writings (τῶν παρ᾽ ᾿Ἱπποκράτει 
λέξεων συναγωγή). In the reign of Hadrian, two learned 
physicians, Artemidorus Capito, and Dioscorides, undertook 
a critical edition of the Hippocratic works, but this is 
known to us only by name. Galen, in the second century 
after Christ, announced a treatise on the subject, which is not 
found among his numerous writings. He was followed by 
Palladius, in the seventh century, who recognized only eleven 
works as genuine. The scholars who have written on the 
subject since the revival of learning have come to various con- 
clusions, according to the different principles by which they 
were guided in their discrimination of the genuine and spurious 





1 Galen, De Dific. Respir. II. Ὁ. 182. 


GENUINE WORKS OF HIPPOCRATES. 407 


works. Hieronymus Mercurialis' admitted nineteen works as 
having proceeded from Hippocrates himself, Haller? recognized 
fifteen genuine writings, Gruner* reduced this list to ten, and J. 
H. Fischer‘ to seven. According to the latest investigations, the 
following works may be accepted as those best entitled to bear 
the name of Hippocrates. 

(1.) The first and third books of the treatise ‘on epidemic 
affections’ (περὶ ἐπιδημιῶν), in which he describes the local 
diseases which he had observed in Thasos, Thessaly, and else- 
where. The division into chapters is due to Mnemon, who 
sold the third book to Ptolemy Euergetes. The remaining five 
books are recognized as genuine by Erotianus, and probably 
contain many germs of Hippocratic teaching, so that they have 
been sometimes attributed to Thessalus, whom Galen however 
expressly excludes from the authorship of the fifth and seventh 
books.’ 

(2.) The treatise ‘ on prognostics’ (προγνωστικά) is generally 
regarded as a genuine and early work of Hippocrates, though it 
is obviously subsequent to the two genuine books on epidemics. 

(3.) The treatise ‘on regimen in acute diseases’ (περὶ διαίτης 
ὀξέων) is accepted as genuine, with the exception of the last 
part, manifestly an interpolation. This book is sometimes 
styled ‘ against the Cnidian sentences’ (πρὸς rac Κνιδίας 
γνώμας), sometimes ‘ on barley-water’ (περὶ πτισάνης). 

(4.) The books ‘ on atmospheres, waters, and localities’ (περὶ 
ἀέρων, ὑδάτων, τύπων) is one of the most universally recognized 
works of Hippocrates. It seems to be alluded to in the Clouds 
of Aristophanes, which was acted in B.c. 423,’ and there is a 
resumé of its contents in Aristotle’s Politics. 

᾿(5.) The essay ‘ on wounds of the head’ (περὶ τῶν ἐν κεφαλῇ 





1 Censura Operum Hippocratis, Venet. 1583. 

2 Artis Medicine Principia, tom. IV. Pref. Lausanne, 1769-1784. 

3 Censwra librorum Hippocraticorum, qué vera a falsis, integri a suppositis 
segregantur, Vratisl. 1772. 

4 Dissertatio de Hippocrate ejusque scriptis, Coburg, 1777. 

5 Fabricius, Bibl. Gr. II. pp. 563 foll. 

5 Schol. ad Aristoph. Nub. 331: ἰατροτέχνας : καὶ ἰατροὶ wept ἀέρων καὶ ὕδατος 


συνέγραψαν. ὕδατα δέ εἰσι καὶ al νεφέλαι. σύνταγμα δέ ἐστιν Ἱπποκράτους περὶ 
ἀέρων, τόπων, καὶ ὑδάτων. 


7 4(VIL.), 7, 2; see Littré, I. p. 333. 


408 MEDICAL LITERATURE. 


τρωμάτων) is accepted by all the critics, except Grimm, as a 
genuine work of Hippocrates. 

(6.) The treatise ‘ on fractures’ (περὶ ἀγμῶν) is also generally 
accepted, though a modern critic’ supposes that only a part of 
the work actually proceeded from Hippocrates himself. 

(7.) ‘The aphorisms’ (ἀφορισμοί), perhaps the best known 
of all the Hippocratic books, are confidently placed in the first 
class. This work contains more than four hundred short sentences 
of a practical nature, either culled by Hippocrates himself at a 
late period of his life from his other works and from the 
memoranda of his medical practice, or formed by some writer of 
his school soon after his death. In this respect, the doubt is 
much the same as that which we have expressed regarding the 
epitomes attributed to certain historical writers,” though it is 
more likely that a practical physician would make a collection 
like ‘the aphorisms’ of Hippocrates, than that a writer of 
history would abridge the details which it was his professed 
intention to record. We are of opinion that this treatise, 
which contains the germs of all the doctrine of Hippocrates, 
and which is still not without its value in medicine, is a some- 
what interpolated edition of a work which the great physician 
committed to writing himself, and which he intended to bear 
the same relation to his practice that the temple-archives of the 
Asclepeia did to the experience acquired by the managers of 
those establishments. It was such a work as a modern phy- 
sician might compile from his case-book. 

ὃ 4. The doubtful works, or those which were perhaps 
written by Hippocrates or published from his materials, in- 
clude a number of treatises, which have been admitted into the 
first class by one or more critics. They are as follows :— 

(1.) ‘ The oath’ (ὅρκος) is recognized by Erotianus, and we 
have seen that it is manifestly referred to by Aristophanes.* 
Whether. it was drawn up by Hippocrates himself for the 
corporation to which he belonged, or was a later document 
formed on the same model, may be doubted. In its original 





. 1 Petersen, Hippoer. nomine que circumferuntur seripta ad tempp. ratt. dispo- 
sita, Hamburg, 1839, p. 13. 
2 For example, see above, chapter XLIII. ὃ 6, p. 394 [234]. 


3 Above, p. 399 [239]. 


DOUBTFUL WORKS OF HIPPOCRATES. 409 


form, at all events, it belonged to the oldest part of the 
Hippocratic collection. 

᾿ς (2) ‘The law’ (νόμος) has been admitted by Erotianus, and 
is maintained by Littré as a necessary supplement to ‘ the oath’ 
in the freemasonry of ancient medicine.’ Dr. Greenhill,’ on 
the contrary, thinks that ‘the oath’ and ‘the law’ belong to 
different periods, ‘ the former having all the simplicity, honesty, 
and religious feeling of antiquity, the latter somewhat of the 
affectation and declamatory grandiloquence of a sophist.’ 

(3.) ‘On ancient medicine’ (περὶ ἀρχαίης ἰητρικῆς). Most 
of the critics are agreed that this treatise was not written by 
Hippocrates; but Erotianus recognizes its genuineness, and 
Littré has entered upon a strenuous and elaborate vindication 
of its claim to a place in the first part of the Hippocratic 
collection. He relies very much on the fact, which he con- 
ceives he has discovered, that the reference to Hippocrates in 
the Phedrus of Plato can be verified in this treatise, in oppo- 
sition to the less tenable opinion of Galen that this reference 
applied to the treatise ‘on nature.’* The book ‘on ancient 
medicine’ is, at all events, an early and important treatise, and 
it is not at all improbable that it is a new edition of a work by 
Hippocrates. 

(4.) ‘On articulations’ (περὶ ἄρθρων). This treatise is ad- 
mitted by Erotian and Galen, it was commented on by 
Bacchius and Philinus, pupils of Herophilus, and is strenuously 
maintained by Littré.* Other critics reject it. 

(5.) ‘ On the instruments of reduction’ (μοχλικόν). This is 
directly admitted by Galen and others. Littré has shown that 
it was an abridgment of the book ‘on articulations.’ In the 
old collections it was combined with the fragment ‘on veins’ 
(περὶ φλεβῶν). ᾿ 

The remaining treatises of this class owe their position to 
the apparent admixture of genuine fragments with additions 
by the followers of Hippocrates: (6.) ‘On ulcers’ (περὶ ἑλκῶν) ; 





1 G@uvres @ Hippocrate,1. p. 344. 2 Smith’s Dictionary, ΤΙ. p. 487. 
3. @uwres d Hippocrate, I. p. 299 sqq., as cited above, p. 400 [240]. 
4 Ibid. p. 333 sqq. 5 Ibid. p. 340. 


ὁ Παραστάτας" ras ἐπιδιδυμίδας ἐν τῷ περὶ φλεβῶν ὃ πρόσκειται TE μοχλικῷ. 
Gloss. 8.0. παραστάτας, cited by Littré, p. 341. 


410 MEDICAL LITERATURE. 


(7.) ‘on fistulas’ (περὶ συρίγγων), and ‘hemorrhoids’ (περὲ 
αἱμοῤῥοΐδων) ; (8.) ‘on epilepsy’ (περὶ ἱερῆς νούσου) ; (9.) ‘on 
the surgery’ (κατ᾽ ἰητρεῖον), which is closely connected with 
the treatise ‘ on the instruments of reduction.’? 

§ 5. The spurious works of the Hippocratic collection have 
been subdivided by Dr. Greenhill’ according to the following 
classification. They are either (I.), older than the time of 
Hippocrates ; (II.), contemporary, or nearly so; (III.), later 
than Hippocrates. 

(I.) In the first of these subdivisions we have only two 
treatises; ‘the prognoses of Cos’ (Kwaxai προγνώσεις), and 
‘the predictions, Book I” (προῤῥητικὸν A). It has been sup- 
posed’ that these very ancient writings contain, in part at least, 
the notes taken by the Asclepiade in the temples, which fur- 
nished, as we have seen, a starting-point to the medical litera- 
ture of Greece. If so, they belong to the class of books to 
which Euripides makes reference in his Alcestis,‘ a tragi-comedy 
performed, according to a recently-discovered authority, in B.c. 
458." 

(II.) The works supposed to belong to the same age as Hip- 
pocrates are again distinguished, as (a) those whose authors 
may be assigned with some probability, and (Ὁ) those whose 
authors are altogether unknown. (a) The treatise ‘on the 
aston of man’ (περὶ φύσιος ἀνθρώπου), and its supplement 

‘on the healthy regimen’ (περὶ διαίτης ὑγιεινῆς), are attributed 
to Polybus, the son-in-law of Hippocrates, because a passage 
quoted from Polybus by Aristotle is found verbatim in the 





1 Littré, I. p. 367. 2 Smith’s Dictionary, II. p. 486. 
3 Grimm, German Translation of Hippocrates, II. p. 508; Littré, I. p. 351. 
4 vv. 962 sqq.: 

ἐγὼ καὶ διὰ μούσας 

καὶ μετάρσιος fia, καὶ 

πλείστων ἁψάμενος λόγων 

κρεῖσσον οὐδὲν ἀνάγκας 

εὗρον, οὐδέ τι φάρμακον 

Θρήσσαις ἐν σανίσιν, τὰς 

᾿Ορφεία κατέγραψεν 

yijpus, οὐδ᾽ ὅσα Φοῖβος ᾿Α- 

σκληπιάδαις ἔδωκεν 

φάρμακα πολυπόνοις ἀντιτεμὼν βροτοῖσιν. 


«5 See Dindorf, Pref. Ld. Oxon. 1834, p. 7. 


SPURIOUS WORKS ATTRIBUTED TO HIPPOCRATES. 41] 


former of these treatises.’ References by Galen and Soranus 
have led to the inference that the celebrated Euryphon of 
Cnidus was the author of the second and third books of the 
treatise ‘ concerning maladies’ (περὶ νούσων), and of the essay 
‘on the nature of women’ (περὶ γυναικείης φύσεως)," and Littré 
has conjectured,’ on the strength of a citation in Aristotle,*. 
that a certain unknown Leophanes or Cleophanes was the 
author of the treatise ‘ on superfetation’ (περὶ ἐπικυήσιος). (0) 
Among the works by unknown authors, which are supposed to 
have proceeded from the contemporaries of Hippocrates, that 
‘on diet’ is fixed to a period subsequent to B.c. 381 by a coin- 
cidence with the calendar of Eudoxus, to which Dr. Greenhill 
has directed attention.’ The other books of this class, such as 
the second, fourth, and sixth books of the Epidemia, and those 
‘on humours’ (περὶ χυμῶν), and ‘ the use of liquids’ (περὶ ὑγρῶν 
χρήσιος), are generally collections of notes and extracts, which 
have found a place in the Hippocratic collection, for the want 
of any definitely assigned authorship. 

(III.) The spurious works admitted to be later than Hippo- 
crates are sufficiently numerous, and are divided by the latest 
critics into three distinct classes: (a) those which are authentic 
but not genuine, 1.6. not wilful forgeries, and these again into 
(@,) works by the same author, or (a,) books by different 
authors ; and (6) those which are wilful forgeries. Of the first 
class of these (a,), Littré infers’ that they were anterior to Aris- 
totle, and were all the works of some one writer, who announces 
that he had also written ‘on peripneumony’ (περὶ περιπνευμο- 
vine), and ‘on the diseases of young women’ (περὶ παρθενιῶν 
νούσων), treatises which are quite lost. The essays which we 
have are ‘on generation’ (περὶ γονῆς) ; ‘on the nature of the 
infant’ (περὶ φύσιος παιδίου) ; the fourth book ‘on maladies’ 
(wept νούσων τὸ τέταρτον) ; ‘on the maladies of females’ (περὶ 





1 Aristot. Hist. Anim. III. 3: Πόλυβος δὲ ὧδε x.7.X., compared with Hippocr. 
περὶ φύσιος, p. 23, Froben. 

2 Galen, Comment. in Hippocr. de Morb. Vulg. V1.1. 29, Littré, I. pp. 47, 
363; Ermerius, De Rat. Vict. in Morb. acut. pp. 363, 9. 

% Guvres @ Hippocrate, I. p. 381. 

4 De Generat. Animalium, IV. ο. τ. 5 -Smith’s Dictionary, II. p. 487. 

6 Guvres ¢ Hippocrate, I. pp. 373—379. 


412 MEDICAL LITERATURE. 


γυναικείων a, 2’); ‘on the diseases of girls’ (περὶ παρθενίων) ; 
‘on barren women’ (περὶ ἀφόρων). In the second class (a,) we 
have the fifth and seventh books of the Epidemia, a second 
book of ‘the predictions,” and a number of minor treatises, 
including one ‘on the weeks’ (περὶ ἑβδομάδων), which exists 
only in a Latin translation, and one ‘on the nature of the 
bones’ (περὶ ὀστέων φύσιος), which is made up entirely of 
extracts from other works in the Hippocratic collection. In 
the last class (ὁ), we have epistles, speeches, and other non- 
medical works, which are obviously due to the ingenuity of 
Sophists. 

§ 6. A discussion of the time and manner of the publication 
of the Hippocratic books involves some questions of general 
interest in reference to a history of Greek literature. These 
questions have been adequately examined by Littré,’ and we 
shall here content ourselves with an exhibition of the general 
results. 

This collection, as far as the medical works are concerned, 
is authenticated, as consisting of treatises anterior to the year 
B.C, 300, by the fact that it was commented upon and cited by 
Hierophilus who flourished about that time, and by his imme- 
diate successors, Baccheius and Philinus. We have also seen 
that Aristotle quotes, by the name of Polybus, one of the 
works now included in this collection, and that we have, among 
these, others which can be assigned inferentially to persons who 
were contemporary with Hippocrates, or lived shortly after his 
time. It is also clear that we have in the collection some 
writings which are not entitled to be considered as independent 
or complete works, such as series of extracts and abridgments, 
notes and compilations. Finally, it is stated, that the Alexan- 
drian grammarians themselves did not accept, without discrimi- 
nation, the works presented to them as the productions of 
Hippocrates, but that ‘ the separators’ (οἱ χωρίζοντες), as they 
were called, placed only those, which appeared to them au- 
thentic, in a special class, under the name of ‘ the book of the 
little table’ (rd ἐκ τοῦ μικροῦ πινακιδίου)." From all these 
considerations, it may be inferred that the Hippocratic collec. 





1 ures d’ Hippocrate, 1. pp. 262—292. 
2 Galen, III. p. 181, ed. Basil. 


PUBLICATION OF THE HIPPOCRATIC COLLECTION. 413 


tion was formed at some time subsequent to Aristotle, and ante- 
rior to Ptolemy Euergetes; that at first it was regarded as 
made up of genuine works classed by themselves, and of other 
medical treatises brought to Alexandria at different times, and 
placed in the library beside Hippocrates; and that, ultimately, 
the line of demarcation, between the books of the little table 
and the rest of those medical works which a less critical or 
more ignorant age ceased to distinguish from them, was removed 
and forgotten. And the whole list of books came into the hands 
of the later critics and commentators, and was by them given 
forth to the world, under the great name of the father of medi- 
cine. There was nothing peculiar in this. The same thing has 
happened to all the great writers of antiquity, whose works were 
sufficiently famous and sufficiently voluminous to admit of this 
mixture of the genuine and the spurious. Aristotle, Demo- 
sthenes, and in a smaller degree Plato, have given their names 
to books or speeches included in the collections of their works, 
but certainly not written by them. And even the Canon of 
the New Testament is exhibited with an obliteration of the three 
distinctions known to Eusebius.’ In the case of Hippocrates, 
it is sufficient to know that we have an adequate sample of his 
genuine writings, and can gather from them what he was both 
as a literary man and as a medical philosopher. 

§ 7. It does not belong to our present business to discuss 
the medical science of Hippocrates; but we must not conclude 
without a few observations on his style, dialect, and literary 
merits. 

In many particulars we must regard Hippocrates as standing 
in a similar position to Herodotus. Both born in Dorian 
colonies,—for Cos and Halicarnassus are separated only by a 
few miles of sea,—they were both resident for a considerable 
time at Athens, or in communication with Athenians; and we 
find that both of them wrote a form of the Ionic dialect nearly 
approximating to the old Attic, and that both of them imitated 
some favourite Attic author, Herodotus taking some of his 





1 The three classes distinguished by Eusebius (Hist. Eccles. III. 25, pp. 244 sqq., 
Heinichen), namely, the ὁμολογούμενα, the ἀντιλεγόμενα, γνώριμα δ᾽ οὖν ὅμως τοῖς 
πολλοῖς, and the v6@a—might furnish names to the three classes of the Hippocratic 
works, 


414 MEDICAL LITERATURE. 


most striking passages from the great poet Sophocles,’ and 
Hippocrates selecting the great historian Thucydides as, in a 
certain sense, his pattern. With regard to the dialect of 
Hippocrates, it is clear that he adopted it as a conventional or 
fashionable idiom. Just as Herodotus wrote Ionic in imitation 
of the historians, who immediately preceded him, so Hippo- 
crates conformed to the practice of the natural philosophers, 
whom he emulated in his own particular branch of physiology. 
He was not influenced by any desire to please Democritus, 
but he wished to adopt a style common to him with Parme- 
nides, Anaxagoras, Melissus, and Diogenes of Apollonia. The 
manuscripts of Hippocrates, as they have come down to us, 
exhibit great inconsistencies in the orthography, but the 
general impression is that of an artificial and conventional 
Ionism, deliberately adopted as the most appropriate phraseo- 
logy of science. Whether Thucydides, during his exile at 
Scaptesyle in Thrace, had any immediate intercourse with 
Hippocrates, who is said to have been resident at the same time 
in the island of Thasos, immediately opposite to that part of 
Thrace, or at Abdera on the same coast, cannot be determined ; 
but it is more than probable that two such men would fall in 
with one another, and form the usual relations of literary inter- 
course. The account of the plague in Thucydides exhibits a 
minute detail of symptoms, which would almost persuade us 
that he had submitted his description to some medical man ;? 
and as he does not mention Hippocrates, who, on the other 
hand, does not refer to this epidemic, it is not altogether 
unnatural to conjecture that Hippocrates may have revised 
this account derived from a sufferer; and that having done so, 
he did not repeat elsewhere what was so graphically told in the 
contemporary history, and was known to himself only from this 
source. Be this as it may, Littré, who has studied Hippo- 





1 See Transactions of the Philological Society, vol. I. p. 161. 

2 The description of the plague in Thucydides is so minutely accurate and cir- 
cumstantial, that a modern physician has been able to infer from the words of the 
historian that the malady was in reality a very violent scarlatina, probably aggra- 
vated by the crowded state of the city, and other depressing circumstances ; see 
Dr. C. Collier’s History of the Plague of Athens, translated from Thucydides ; 
with remarks explanatory of its Pathology. London, 1857. 


STYLE OF HIPPOCRATES. 415 


crates with the most intelligent attention, recognizes a close 
affinity between his style and that of Thucydides,’ though he 
attributes it to the general law that writers of the same epoch 
naturally fall into the same mode of thinking and expressing 
their meaning. The extreme brevity, which Galen notices as a 
remarkable characteristic of Hippocrates, is also a conspicuous 
feature in Thucydides. It is in consequence of this that so 
many of the sententious phrases of Hippocrates have taken their 
place in the habitual language of civilized Europe. His state- 
ment at the beginning of his Aphorisms, that ‘ Life is short and 
art long, that time flies, that experience is deceitful, and that 
judgment is difficult,’* not only supplies rules for the medical prac- 
titioner, but furnishes common proverbs for every society ; and 
it is repeatedly quoted by the Greek rhetoricians as a specimen 
of pregnant brevity.* In his style, no less than in his medical 
system, Hippocrates acts on the principle which is expressed, in 
very Thucydidean language, in a well-known passage of the 
treatise ‘on articulations,’ and he regards affected verbiage 
with the same contempt which he expresses for medical 
quackery and charlatanism. ‘If it were possible, says he,’ 
‘to make men healthy in various ways, it would be best to 
choose that which is least troublesome; for this is both more 
honest and more scientific, unless one aims at vulgar imposition.’ 
We see in his style that complete appropriation of all the 
resources of language which marks the great writer, whatever 
his subject may be. Thus, a common verb is made to bear in 





1 Quvres d Hippocrate, I. p. 474: ‘plus j’ai medité sur le style de l'un et de 
l’autre, et cherché a pénétrer les procedés, la forme, et le sentiment, plus aussi je 
me suis conyaincu qu'il existait entre ces écrivains une é¢troite affinité—ainsi est-ce 
ἃ Thucydide qu’il faut comparer Hippocrate,’ &c. 

2 TV. p. τι, ed. Basil. : Ἱπποκράτης μὲν ἐν τοῖς πλείστοις τῶν ἑαυτοῦ συγγραμ- 
μάτων ἐσχάτως βραχύλογος ὦν. 

3 Aphor. I. ὃ 1: ὁ βιὸς βραχύς, ἡ δὲ τέχνη μακρή, ὁ δὲ καιρὸς ὀξύς, ἡ δὲ πεῖρα 
σφαλερή, ἡ δὲ κρίσις χαλεπή. 

4 See Demetr. περὶ ἑρμηνείας, vol. IX. p. 3, Walz.; Joann. Sicel. Schol. in 
Hermog. vol. VI. p. 236, Walz. 

5 De Articul. p. 837 F: εἰ δὲ πολλοῖσι τρόποισιν οἷόν τε εἴη ὑγιέας ποιεῖν, τὸν 
ἀοχλότατον χρὴ αἱρέεσθαι. καὶ γὰρ ἀνδραγαθικώτερον τοῦτο καὶ τεχνικώτερον, ὅστις 
μὴ ἐπιθυμέει δημοειδέος κιβδηλίης. ‘The word ἀνδραγαθικός, which seems to be 
peculiar to Hippocrates, reminds one of the Thucydidean verb, ἀνδραγαθίζομαι 
(II. 63, IIT. 40). 


416 MEDICAL LITERATURE. 


its varied inflexions the meanings of the technical noun which 
is derived from it.' He does not hesitate to give emphasis to a 
passage by the introduction of a new but appropriate compound.’ 
The technicalities of his subject are constantly relieved by an 
elegance of phraseology which is almost poetical. And there 
is scarcely a beauty of simple and emphatic Greek prose which 
may not be exemplified in the oldest writings of the Hippocratic 
collection. On the whole, it may be said, with truth, that 
whatever may be the value of these old medical books to modern 
disciples of Aisculapius, no student of Greek has seen’ all the 
varied excellences of that wonderful language, if he has never 
made acquaintance with the original text of Hippocrates. 





1 For example, κρίνομαι is used in the medical sense of κρίσις, Aphor. I. 20: 
τὰ κρινόμενα καὶ τὰ κεκριμένα ἀρτίως μὴ Kwéew, μηδὲ νεωτεροποιεῖν μήτε 
φαρμακείῃσι μήτ᾽ ἄλλοισιν ἐρεθισμοῖσιν ἀλλ᾽ ἐᾶν. II. 2, 3: τὰ ὀξέα τῶν νουσημάτων 
κρίνεται ἐν τεσσαρεσκαίδεκα ἡμέρῃσιν. 

2 Aphor. 11. 44: οἱ παχέες σφόδρα κατὰ φύσιν ταχυθάνατοι γίνονται μᾶλλον 
τῶν ἰσχνῶν. 

3 As in the use of the verb ξυναποθνήσκειν of an incurable complaint, Aphor. V. 
4, or of the verb λυμαίνεσθαι, to express the sufferings caused by a useless surgical 
operation, De Articul. vol. IV. p. 252, 1. 14, Littré; cf. the λυμανθὲν δέμας of 
ZEschylus, Choéph. 288. 


417 


THIRD PERIOD OF GREEK LITERATURE. 


l 





CHAPTER XLV. 


THE SCHOOL OF ALEXANDRIA—POETS. 


§ 1. Alexandria and the Ptolemies. ὃ 2. Alexandrian poets ; their proper classifi- 
cation and arrangement. § 3. Philetas in Alexandria, and Aratus in Macedonia, 
§ 4. Callimachus. § 5. Lycophron and the tragedians. § 6. The epic and 
didactic poets, Apollonius, Rhianus, Euphorion, and Nicander. § 7. The 
bucolic poets, Theocritus, Bion, and Moschus. § 8. The parodists and 
phlyacographers. 


οὐδῷ S the literary predominance of Athens, which gave a 

special character to the second period of Greek 
literature, was due mainly to the political importance of Attica, 
it was a natural consequence that the downfal of Athenian 
independence should bring with it first a deterioration, and 
ultimately an extinction of that intellectual centralization 
which had for more than a century sustained and directed the 
best efforts of Hellenic genius and culture. But while the 
living literature of Greece was thus dying away, an incidental 
result of the oriental conquests of Alexander prepared a new 
home for the Muses on the coast of that wonderful country, to 
which all the nations of antiquity had owed a part, at least, of 
their science and of their religious belief.’ In Egypt, as in 
other regions,’ Alexander gave directions for the foundation of 
a city, which was to be called after his own name. This new 
city of Alexandria, which soon filled all the space between the 
lake Mareotis and the sea at the Canopic mouth of the Nile, 





1 There is a very lively and interesting account of the foundation of Alexandria, 
and the character of its literature, in Mr. Kingsley’s Alexandria and her Schools, 
Cambridge, 1854. 

3 There were more than twenty cities named Alexandria, or Alewxandropolis, 
and of these Candahar and Scanderoun still bear traces of their Greek name, and 
Herat is still a place of considerable importance. 

WoL. if. EE 


418 THE SCHOOL OF ALEXANDRIA—POETS. 


and was connected with the island of Pharos by a great mole, 
on which the modern town has sprung up, was built by Cleo- 
menes of Naucratis,' after the plans of the architect Dinochares, 
and became not only the most magnificent city of the Hellenic 
world, but the capital of a Greek kingdom, and the residence of a 
family who attracted to their court all the living representatives 
of the literature of Greece, and stored up in their enormous 
library all the best works of the classical periods which we 
have hitherto discussed.? It was chiefly in the reigns of the 
first three of these Ptolemies that the city of Alexandria was 
made a new home of Greek literature. Soter, who ruled from 
B.c. 306 to B.c. 285, under the inspiration of Demetrius 
Phalereus, the last of the Athenian orators, laid the founda- 
tions of the library, which was kept partly in the temple of 
Serapis, and partly in the Brucheium adjoining the palace; 
and also instituted the Museum, or temple of the Muses, where 
the literary and scientific men of the age were maintained by 
endowments not unlike our fellowships or lay canonries, and 
where they enjoyed collectively the advantage of a reference to 





1 See the plan and description in Parthey’s valuable monograph entitled, Das 
Alexandrinische Museum, Berlin, 1838, pp. 18—34. 

2 The chief authority, or rather the most definite statement respecting the 
library at Alexandria, is a Latin scholium on Plautus, discovered by Professor 
Osann in 1830; see Welcker, Der Epischer Cyclus I. p. 8; Ritschl, Die Alex- 
andrinischen Bibliotheken, p. 3. The author quoted from is Cecius, and W. 
Dindorf has shown (Rhein. Mus. 1836, p. 232) that this must be a classical sub- 
stitute for Tzetzes, the Scholiast on Aristophanes, who sometimes calls himself 
Κέκος, or Kéxxos. The following is the statement concerning the library: ‘Nam 
rex ille [Philadelphus] philosophis affertissimus [Ritch] reads differtissimus, and 
Thiersch (De Pentat. Vers. Alex. p. 9), proposes affectissimus] et ceteris omni- 
bus auctoribus claris, disquisitis impensa regize munificentie ubique terrarum 
quantum valuit voluminibus opera Demetrii Phalerii phzxa senum [Ritschl reads 
prehensa secum, and Bernhardy: et LXX. senwm], duas bibliothecas fecit ; alteram 
extra Regiam, alteram autem in Regia. In exteriore autem fuerunt milia voluminum 
quadraginta duo et octingenta. In Regie autem bibliotheca voluminum quidem 
commixtorum volumina quadringenta milia, simplicium autem et digestorum milia 
nonaginta, sicuti refert Callimachus aulicus Regis bibliothecarius, qui etiam 
singulis voluminibus titulos inscripsit.’ From this statement we gather that the 
library contained—(qa) in the Bruchetwm, which was the primary place of deposit, 
400,000 rolls of duplicates and other unsorted books, and 90,000 separate works 
properly arranged ; and (6) in the Serapewm 42,800 volumes, probably the ultimate 
selection, or most valuable books in the whole collection. The value of this 
scholium consists mainly in the presumption that it was derived by Tzetzes from 
the genuine writings of Callimachus and Eratosthenes. | 


THE PTOLEMIES. 419 


books, which, as we have seen, Aristotle had provided for himself 
individually at a very great expense. This encouragement of 
literature was carried on with still greater earnestness by 
Philadelphus (B.c. 285—247), who had the celebrated Calli- 
machus for his librarian, and not only bought up the whole of 
Aristotle’s collection, but transferred the native annals of 
Egypt and Judea to the domain of Greek literature, by employ- 
ing the priest Manetho to translate the hieroglyphics of his 
own temple archives into the language of the court, and by 
procuring from the Sanhedrim at Jerusalem the first part of 
that celebrated version of the Hebrew sacred books which was 
completed after the time of Philometor, and was called the 
Version of the Seventy, from the number of the Council which 
sanctioned it. Euergetes (B.c. 247-222), whose literary circle 
boasted of the great name of Eratosthenes, increased the 
library, not only by fair means, but also by somewhat dis- 
honestly, though at a heavy cost to himself, depriving the 
Athenians of their authentic edition of the great dramatists, 
which Lycurgus had laid up in the public archives.’ One of 
the plans which he adopted was to require from all merchants 
and navigators, who came to Alexandria, the loan of any books 
which they happened to have with them. A copy was made 
and given to the proprietor, but the original was deposited in 
the library, with the inscription, ‘a book from the ships’ (τὸ ἐκ 
τῶν πλοίων). The tendency of all this hot-bed encouragement 
of literature was to produce a few eminent men of science, a 
reasonable supply of second-rate and artificial poets, and a host 
of grammarians and literary pedants, who indulged in specula- 
tions more or less intelligent on subjects of literary criticism, 
hermeneutics, and bibliography. This grammatical tendency 
began in the time of Philadelphus ; and Callimachus, Alexander 
the Δ πο απ, Lycophron, Zenodotus, Aristarchus, and Aristo- 
phanes of Byzantium, compiled editions, glossaries, grammars, 
and commentaries, which had the effect of fixing the Greek 
language in a generally intelligible and uniform state or con- 
dition. The process was much the same as that adopted by 





1 Above ch. XLII. ὃ 3, p. 354 [194]. 
2 Galen, vol. V. p. 412, ed. Basil.; F. A. Wolf, Prolegom. p. CLXXVIL. ; 
Littré, Hippocrates, vol. I. pp. 274 544. 
EE 2 


490 THE SCHOOL OF ALEXANDRIA—PORTS. 


the Jewish Masorethe after the return from exile,’ or by the 
grammarians of King Vicramdditya’s court in India.? The 
oldest writers suffered most under the Procrustean operation, 
and the Homer of Aristarchus appears in a modernized form, 
under which only the critical genius of Bentley could perceive - 
the original and obsolete forms, with their digammas and 
primitive assibilations. In the course of time, the library 
founded at Pergamus by Eumenes, which multiplied pergament 
or parchment copies in rivalry of the papyrus or paper books 
of Alexandria, was transferred to Egypt; and however little we 
may be indebted to Callimachus and his successors for their 
remodelling of ancient works, we must always thank the 
Ptolemies for preserving to our times, in a form more or less 
complete and authentic, all the best specimens of Greek litera- 
ture which have come down to us. 

§ 2. In speaking of the literary productions, which were 
fostered or forced in the hot-beds of Alexandrian learning, we 
naturally begin with the poets. And here it is scarcely possible 
to classify the writers according to the older divisions of Greek 
poetry. For some of the most eminent of the Alexandrian 
men of letters tried their strength in many, some in all these 
departments. Callimachus, indeed, who was the head of the 
school, was not only a writer of all kinds of poetry, but also 
a critic, grammarian, historian, and geographer—one, in fact, 
who was a living representative of the great library over which 
he presided.- It will be most in accordance then with the 
general objects of this work, and with the convenience of the 
reader, if we exhibit the Alexandrian poets in their distinct per- 
sonality as a portrait gallery, arranged rather in chronological 
order than according to the subject-matter of their writings.’ 
In this way we must begin with Philetas, who was the tutor, 
not only of the second Ptolemy but also of Theocritus, the 
most charming poet of the Alexandrian Court in the reign of 





1 Van der Hooght, Pref. in Bibl. Hebr.§ 24. As we shall show in the next 
chapter, the Hebrew Masorets were not uninfluenced by the contemporary scholars 
of Alexandria. 

2 This was by far the most recent of these grammatical epochs of literature, as — 
it began, according to Ideler’s calculations, in the year B.c. 58. See Lepsius, 
Chronologie der Aigypter I. p. 4. 

3 The first six librarians of the Alexandrian collection were Zenodotus, Callimachus, 


CLASSIFICATION OF THE POETS. 421 


Philadelphus. With him we shall associate his contemporary 
Aratus. In the next place, we must present Callimachus, who 
is also distinguished by his success as a teacher of others, and 
who was not only the greatest man of letters under Phila- 
delphus and Euergetes, but counted among his pupils the most 
eminent epic poet of the school, his successor, Apollonius Rho- 
dius, besides the philosopher Eratosthenes, the historian Ister, 
and the grammarian Aristophanes of Byzantium. We shall 
assign the third representative position to Lycophron, who 
retains his place in all the different versions of the Pleiad, or 
list of the seven tragedians of Alexandria, and who was a con- 
temporary and fellow-labourer of Callimachus in the Museum. 
In the fourth compartment we shall class together the epic 
poets Apollonius, Rhianus, and Euphorion. In the fifth group 
we shall have the writers of idyls, Theocritus, Bion, and Mos- 
chus. And in the sixth place, we shall glance at the disrepu- 
table family of Sotades, and the sillographies of Timon. 





Eratosthenes, Apollonius, Aristophanes, and Aristarchus (Ritschl, Alex. Bibl. 
p- 19 sqq., cf. Parthey, Alex. Mus. pp. 71 sqq.), and the following table gives the 
chronology of these writers and their contemporaries (Ritschl, u.s. pp. 89, 90). 
Philip of Macedon. . . Ol. sd Philetas born. 


Ptolemy Soter . . . . . rit { Zenodotus born. 


He Callimachus born. 

117, 3 Ptolemy Philadelphus born. 

ΜῈ Aratus born. 

121, 1 Demetr. Phal. comes to Alexandria. 


Ptolemy Philadelphus . . . 124 Library founded. Zenodotus librarian. 
Antigonus Gonatas. . . . Aratus goes to Macedonia. 
Lycophron. 
126 LEratosthenes and Euphorion born. 
126 


127 Apollonius born. 


ri Aristophanes born, 

131 Apollonius goes to Rhodes. 

133 Callimachus librarian. 
Ptolemy Euergetes. . . . 133, 2 Eratosthenes summoned to Alexandria. 
Ee eee ee a.) Eratosthenes librarian. 

138 

139 
Ptolemy Epiphanes. . . . ‘ ἢ Apollonius librarian. Aristophanes librarian. 
148 


Aristarchus born. 


Eumenes II. . Aristarchus librarian, 


422 THE SCHOOL OF ALEXANDRIA—PORTS. 


§ 3. As far as we can learn, the founder of a school of 
poetry at Alexandria, and the model for imitation not only to 
those who immediately succeeded him in that city, but also to 
the Roman writers of elegiac poetry, whose names are familiar 
as household words to all educated Europeans, was Puruptras of 
Cos, the son of Telephus, whom Ptolemy Soter invited to his 
Court, and made the tutor to his favourite son and successor 
Philadelphus.' This educational appointment was due less to 
the poetical eminence of Philetas than to his repute as a gram- 
marian and critic, and he was associated with Zenodotus of 
Ephesus, not only in this office, but also in the work of editor- 
ship, which formed a great part of the literary business at 
Alexandria. The dates of the birth and death of Philetas are 
unknown. Suidas speaks of him as having lived in the time of 
Philip and Alexander, but this is hardly consistent with the fact 
that he was a contemporary of Aratus,? who flourished at the 
Court of Antigonus Gonatas, and of Theocritus,? who must have 
been at the height of his reputation in B.c. 270. The extreme 
emaciation of his person, which exposed him to the joking im- 
putation of wearing lead in the soles of his shoes lest he should 
be blown away,‘ and which is attributed to a perplexing study of 
the Megaric subtleties,’—a study said to have shortened his life® 
—would seem to indicate a feeble constitution’ quite incon- 





1 The notice in Suidas is: Φιλητᾶς, KGos, vids Τηλέφου, ὧν ἐπί re Φιλίππου καὶ 
᾿Αλεξάνδρου, γραμματικὸς [καὶ], κριτικός" ὃς ἰσχνωθεὶς ἐκ τοῦ ζητεῖν τὸν καλούμενον 
ψευδόμενον λόγον, ἀπέθανεν, ἐγένετο δὲ καὶ διδάσκαλος τοῦ δευτέρου Πτολεμαίου" 
ἔγραψεν ᾿Επιγράμματα, καὶ ᾿Ελεγειὰς, καὶ ἄλλα. 

2 Vit. Arati, apud Clinton, F. Η. s.a, a.c. 272: ᾿Ἄρατος. .. συνήκμασε δὲ 
᾿Αλεξάνδρῳ τῳ Αἰτωλῷ καὶ Φιλητᾷ. 

3 Theocritus speaks as though Philetas were still living in his VII. Jd. 40, where 
he is coupled with Asclepiades of Samos ; with reference to this passage we are told : 
ἀκουστὴς δὲ γέγονε Φιλητᾶ καὶ ᾿Ασκληπιάδου ὧν μνημονεύει (Θεοκρ. yévos); and the 
same statement has been extracted by Wiistemann (Theocr. p. 106) from a corrupt 
passage in Cheeroboscus (fol. 176, Catal, Bibl. Coislin.): Φιλητᾶς [vulgo Φιλίππας]} 
ὁ διδάσκαλος Θεοκρίτου. 

4 Plut. An Seni ὅς. p. 791, E.; Athen. XII. p. 552,.B; ΖΦ πηδη, V. H. IX, 
14, X. 6. 

5 Suidas, u.s. 

ὁ In Athen. IX. p. 401, F., we have the following epigram :— 

ξεῖνε, Φιλητᾶς εἰμί" λόγων ὁ ψευδόμενός με 
ὥλεσε καὶ νυκτῶν φροντίδες ἑσπέριοι. 

7 Plut. u.s. speaks of Prodicus and Philetas as véous μὲν ἰσχνοὺς δὲ καὶ νοσώδεις 
καὶ τὰ πολλὰ κλωρπετεῖς δι᾿ ἀῤῥωστίαν ὄντας. 








PHILETAS. 423 


‘sistent with longevity. All these considerations should 
induce us to fix the period of his birth at about B.c. 330, 
and his death shortly before the accession of Philadelphus 
in B.c. 285. 

Philetas was chiefly celebrated as an elegiac poet, and in 
this branch of literature he occupied the highest place along 
with Callinus, Mimnermus, and Callimachus.' With the 
latter, he formed the chief model for the Latin elegiac poets. 
Propertius, in particular, constantly refers to Philetas as the 
source of his inspiration, once, according to an ingenious 
emendation, in conjunction with Mimnermus, more frequently 
coupled with Callimachus, to whom, however, he seems, on the 
whole, to have preferred him.?_ The style of his poetry, which 
is partly indicated by the fragments, is sufficiently represented 
by these Roman imitators. His elegies were occupied with the 
languishing sentimentalities of an eager or complaining lover. 
A particular mistress, or the feigned name of one, Bittis, 
Battis, or Batto,® plays the same part as the Cynthia and Delia 
of his Roman imitators. The high esteem in which he was 
held by his contemporaries is indicated by the manner in which 
Theocritus mentions his name,‘ and by the effect which he 





1 Proclus, Chrestomath. p. 379, Gaisford. 
3 The following are some of the references to Philetas in Propertius ; III. 26, 31: 
Tu satius memorem Musis imitere Philetam, 
Et non inflati somnia Callimachi, 
where Scaliger reads : Musis meliorem, and Hertzberg : Tu socius Musis Mimnermi. 
Id. 1V.1, 1: 
Callimachi Manes et Coi sacra Philetz 
In vestrum, queso, me sinite ire nemus. 
Fad, ἘΥ͂. 3; 51: 
Talia Calliope lymphisque a fonte petitis 
Ora Philetz& nostra rigavit aqua. 
Id. V. 6, 3: 
Cera Philetzis certet Romana corymbis 
Et Cyrenzeas urna ministret aquas. Ὁ 
Callimachus and Philetas, and their three Roman imitators, are classed together 
by Statius, Silv. IL. 1, 252—255. 

3 Birris, Hermesian. apud Athen. p. 598, F, v. 77. Barris, Ov. Trist. I. 6, 2; 
Ep. ex Ponto, 111. τ, 58. The name Birrw occurs in inscriptions, and Lachmann 
proposes to read Battds from Barra, in Prop. IIT. 26, 3r. 

4 Theocr. VII. 40: οὐ γάρ πω κατ᾽ ἐμὸν νόον οὐδὲ τὸν ἐσθλὸν 

Σικελίδαν νίκημι τὸν ἐκ Σάμω οὔτε Φιλητᾶν 
ἀείδων" βάτραχος δὲ ποτ᾽ ἀκρίδας ὥς τις ἐρίσδω. 


424 THE SCHOOL OF ALEXANDRIA—POETS. 


produced on the fashionable literature at Alexandria and the 
imported poetry of Rome; and there cannot be any doubt that 
he was an admirable specimen of that ingenious, elegant, and 
harmonious versification which takes the place of higher poetry 
in a refined and artificial age. Besides these elegies, Philetas 
wrote sportive epigrams on Bittis (παίγνια, Stobeeus, ἐπιγράμ- 
ματα, Suid.),’ a poem in elegiac verse on the lamentations of 
Demeter for her daughter,’ which may have served as a model 
for the laments of the Bucolic poets, and a poem in Hexa- 
meters, called Hermes,’ which is described by Parthenius* as relat- 
ing to a love affair of Ulysses. An attempt has been made to 
refer to this poet an elegiac couplet quoted by Strabo from the 
Hermeneia of Philetas,” but as he was a grammarian by profes- 
sion, it is not at all improbable that the work referred to was a 
critical treatise on interpretation full of quotations from various 
poets. 

Besides his labours as a poet Philetas was an eminent com- 
mentator and grammarian. In conjunction with his colleague 
Zenodotus, he wrote notes on Homer, which were sharply criti- 
cized by Aristarchus.6 His principal contribution to grammar 
was a book of miscellanies (ἄτακτα or ἄτακτοι yAwoaat),’ 
work of such general notoriety that the comic poet Strato 
refers to it as a well known authority for the meaning of words.* 
It is also combined with a reference to his love poems by Her- 
mesianax,? and is perhaps to be sought in an emendation 





1 Hertzberg, Quest. Propert. p. 208. 

2 Stobeeus, Florileg. CIV. 11, CXXIV. 26. 

3 Id. Flor. CIV. 12, CX VIII. 3; Eclog. Phys. V. 4. 4 Erot. 2. 

5 Strabo, III. p. 168: καὶ Φιλητᾶς τε ἐν Ἑρμηνείᾳ, where it is proposed to read 
ἐν ‘Epp ἐλεγείᾳ. : 

8 Schol. Venet. ad 11. 11, 111. 

7 Cited by Schol. Apoll. Rhod. IV. 989, as ἐν ἀτάκτοις γλώσσαις : by Etym. M. 
s.v. Ἐλινός, as ἐν γλώσσαις. The emendation of Schweighzuser in Athen. XI. 
467, of ὡς Φιλητᾶς φησὶν ἐν᾿Ατάκτοις for év’ σταῖς is generally admitted. 

8. Athen. IX. p. 383, B: 

ὥστε με 
τῶν τοῦ Φιλητᾶ χαμβάνοντα βιβλίων 
σκοπεῖν ἕκαστα τί δύναται τῶν ῥημάτων. 

9. Athen. XIII. p. 598, F: 

Βιττίδα μολπάζοντα θοὴν περὶ πάντα Φιλητᾶν 
ῥήματα καὶ πᾶσαν ῥνόμενον λαλίην. 








HERMESIANAX, PHANOCLES, ARATUS. 425 


of an epigram by the grammarian Crates which combines the 
glosses of Philetas with his Homeric studies." The logical 
studies of Philetas are attested by the extravagant story, to 
which we have already referred, that he wasted his feeble 
frame in vain attempts to solve the Ψευδόμενος of the Megaric 
School. 

_ The immediate successors of Philetas as an elegiac poet were 
his friend Hermestanax’? and Pxranocies, whose age is not 
known.* But if we would understand his importance with 
reference to the school of Alexandria, and the effects which the 
patronage of the Ptolemies produced on the formation of an 
artificial and exotic literature in that great city, we must com- 
pare him with his contemporary Aratus, who was court poet 
to another successor of Alexander in Macedonia itself. No 
efforts on the part of the Macedonian kings seem to have suc- 
ceeded, in creating a love of learning in the country, to the 
neighbourhood of which the Greeks referred the primitive 
poetry of Orpheus. Archelaus gave a welcome to Euripides ; 
Philip committed the education of his son to Aristotle; and 
Antigonus Gonatas entertained Aratus at his court. But no 
lasting fruits were produced, and Macedonia, which contributed 
so much to the Hellenism of Asia, remained to the last only 
partially Greek itself. 

Aratus, the son of Athenodorus, was born in Cilicia, ac- 
cording to some authorities at Soli, according to others at 
Tarsus,* and was a contemporary, perhaps a friend, of Philetas. 
He went to Athens at an early age, and there became a hearer 





1 Anthol. Palat. XI. 218: 
Xolpiros ᾿Αντιμάχου πολὺ λείπεται, ἀλλ᾽ ἐπὶ πᾶσιν 
Xolpirov Ἑὐφορίων εἶχε διὰ στόματος, 
καὶ κατάγλωσσ᾽ ἐπόει τὰ ποήματα, καὶ τὰ Φιλητᾶ 
ἀτρεκέως ἤδει᾽ καὶ γὰρ 'Ομηρικὸς Fv. 
The common reading is τὰ φίλητρα, which makes no sense in this connexion. 

3 There is a considerable fragment of Hermesianax in Athen. XIII. p. 597. 
It is part of the third book of his poem, addressed to his mistress Leontium, and 
has been repeatedly edited in a separate form. 

3 The style of Phanocles belongs to the same class with that of Philetas, 
Hermesianax, and Callimachus, and he was probably their contemporary. 

4 There are four lives of Aratus (Ἀράτου Bios, apud Buhl. I. Vite Arati tres, 11. 
PP. 429—445), besides the article in Suidas. 


; 


426 THE SCHOOL OF ALEXAynn«: —POETS. 


of the Stoic philosopher Perseus,’ whom he eventually accom- 
panied to the court of Antigonus Gonatas, the son of Demetrius 
Poliorcetes. Here he was so well entertained that he spent 
the remainder of his life in Macedonia. At the request of his 
patron he composed the poem which gained him his chief 
celebrity. It was an ingenious versification of the two books 
entitled "Evorrpoy and Φαινόμενα, by which Eudoxus of Cnidus 
had made Egyptian astronomy and meteorology popular in 
Greece. And Aratus, who was not himself an observer, or, 
indeed, a scientific man in that sense, so completely superseded 
Eudoxus, that a great work of Hipparchus was a commentary 
more immediately on the poem of Aratus than on the scientific 
treatise from which its materials were derived.? Aratus divided 
his poem into two parts corresponding to the two works of 
Eudoxus, the first called Φαινόμενα, Phenomena, in 732 verses, 
being an essay on astronomy, and the second called Διοσημεῖα, 
or, more properly, Διοσήμια, Prognostics, in 422 verses, being 
a treatise on the changes of weather and their effects. This 
latter poem was not only taken from Eudoxus, but also bor- 
rowed in good measure from Aristotle’s Meteorologica and 
Theophrastus’ De signis ventorum. The great popularity of 
this work, as a pleasing compendium of the existing knowledge 
on the subject, is shown not only by the fact already men- 
tioned, that a really scientific man like Hipparchus made it the 
text of his learned commentaries, but also by the high repute 
which the work enjoyed among the educated Romans. Cicero, 
who was quite aware that Aratus was only a versifier of a sub- 
ject which he did not thoroughly understand,’ thought it worth 
while to translate the poem into Latin verse, and the same task 





1 According to Suidas he was also a pupil of Menecrates of Ephesus, of Timon, 
and of Menedemus. 

2 The title of the work of Hipparchus is: τῶν ’Apdrov καὶ Evddtou φαινομένων, 
ἐξηγησέων βιβλία +. 

3 The word Διοσήμια occurs in Aristoph. Acharn. 171, and elsewhere: there is 
no authority for Avoonueta, and Grauert maintains (δον die Werke des Dichters 
Aratus von Soli, Niebuhr’s Rhein. Mus. 1827, p. 336, foll.) that even the former 
could not have been the title of a work or part of a work by Aratus. 

4 De Oratore, I. τό, § 69: ‘si constat inter doctos hominem ignarum 
astrologie Aratum ornatissimis atque optimis versibus de ccelo  stellisque 
dixisse,’ &c. : 


ARATUS. 427 


was afterwards undertaken by the Emperor Domitian' and by 
Avienus.? Ovid says’ that the fame of Aratus will be as lasting as 
the sun and moon; and the Apostle Paul, when speaking in the 
Areopagus, cites him to the Athenians as one of their own poets, 
for the saying at the beginning of his poem, that we are all the 
offspring of the chief of the gods.‘ Besides Hipparchus, who 
wrote on the book on account of its scientific contents, it 
formed the subject of numerous critical and grammatical com- 
mentaries, commencing with the time of Callimachus and 
Attalus of Rhodes, who were nearly contemporaries of Aratus, 
and going on to Aristophanes of Byzantium, Aristarchus, and 
Achilles Tatius. A work, which attracted so much notice, 
must have had some special merit, in addition to its popular 
treatment of a generally interesting and difficult subject. But 
we cannot profess much enthusiasm for the specimens preserved 
in the Latin translations, or for the magniloquence of such lines 
as this: 


‘Deep from the marsh where they lie croak forth the fathers of tadpoles.’® 


Besides the two books, which became so popular, it seems that 
Aratus wrote several others on the subject of Astronomy, which 
are quoted under the titles of ᾿Αστροθεσία and ὁ κανών. Ina 
commentary on Hesiod, the grammarian Tzetzes quotes the 
fifth book of the ᾿Αστρικά of Aratus.” And a modern scholar, 
who does not believe that Aratus wrote a book called Διοσήμια, 





1 Tt is generally supposed that the Cesar mentioned as the translator of Aratus 
was Germanicus, the father of Caligula, but Janus Rutgersius (Var. Lect. III. 
p- 276, quoted by Grauert u.s. p. 347) has proved that the translator must have 
been Domitian. : 

2 Aratea Phenomena, and Aratea Prognostica, printed in Lemaire’s edition of 
Avienus. 

3 Amores I. 15, 16: 

Nulla Sophocleo veniet jactura cothorno, 
Cum Sole et Lun& semper Aratus erit. 

4 Acts xvii. 28: ὡς καί τινες τῶν Kad’ ὑμᾶς ποιητῶν εἰρήκασιν' Tod γὰρ καὶ 
γένος ἐσμέν. 

5 Diosem. 946: 

αὐτόθεν ἐξ ὕδατος πατέρες βοοῶσι γυρίνων. 

δ Schol. Arat. v. 450; Suidas s.v.; Achilles Tatius ap. Petav. Doctr. Temp, 
TIT. c. 15. 

7 Ad Hes. O. et D. I. p. 6, Heins.: "Aparos ἐν τῇ πεμπτῇ τῶν ᾿Αστρικῶν. 


428 THE SCHOOL OF ALEXANDRIA—POBRTS. 


but that the book so called got this erroneous name from a 
second title, προγνώσεις διὰ σημείων, has conjectured that in 
the original form of the work called Φαινόμενα several books 
were interposed between the two which became so famous, so 
that the whole poem was of very considerable extent.? Aratus 
is also said to have written elegies, like his contemporary 
Philetas,*? whom he emulated, too, ‘as a critic and commentator 
on Homer, having published a recension (διόρθωσις) of the 
Odyssey. 

From all this, it is clear that Aratus was a poet and 
grammarian of the same mark and likelihood as his contempo- 
raries of Alexandria, and that he really belonged to the school 
in which he found his chief admirers and expositors. Theo- 
critus, whose life was spent between Syracuse and Alexandria, 
addresses a poem to Aratus, and speaks of him as a familiar 
friend,* and could hardly have made his acquaintance unless 
Aratus had been to Alexandria, or had met Theocritus in Cos, 
in the school of Philetas, for he was not likely to have travelled 
to Sicily. We venture, therefore, to consider Aratus, as a 
corresponding member of the school of Alexandria, as an out- 
lying appendage to that body of writers ;° and we regard the 





1 This title is given to the second work in the life of Aratus (Vita 11.), 

2 Grauert, u.s. It is the opinion of Grauert that the ᾿Αστρικὰ of Aratus was a 
poem in five parts, comprehending two parts of the Phenomena, the ’Acrpofecia 
and the Συνανατελλόντων καὶ συνδυνόντων, or ᾿Ανατολή (which Hipparchus at the 
beginning of his commentaries calls Dvvavaronal), then the Kdvwy, and after this 
the Prognostica or Διοσήμια. The Canon of Aratus is farther discussed in an 
excellent paper by Béckh, De Arati Canone, 1828, reprinted in the Philological 
Museum, 11. pp. 101 foll. He says (p. 103): ‘Aratum in Canone sonorum 
musicorum designationem et cum hae spherarum concentum et aliquid fortasse de 
motu docuisse liquet, conjiciasque illud spherarum systema harmonicum, quod a 
musicis excogitatum refert Achilles Tatius, ex Arateo esse Canone petitum.’ 

3 Judging, however, by the specimen in Macrobius (Sat, v. 20, 8), the style was 
not Philetzean : 

αἰάζω Διότιμον ὃς ἐν πέτραισι κάθηται 
Γαργαρέων παισὶν βῆτα καὶ ἄλφα λέγων. 

4 The sixth Idyll of Theocritus is addressed to Aratus, and in the seventh, of 
which the scene is laid in Cos, Aratus is mentioned several times, once as the 
ξεῖνος of the poet (v. 119, cf. vv. 97, 122), and there is good reason for the con- 
jecture of Wiistemann (ad Theocr. p. 108) that Theocritus and Aratus were fellow 
pupils of Philetas in his native island. 

5 Athenodorus, the brother of Aratus, defended Homer against the attacks of 
Zoilus, and was probably a resident at Alexandria.* 


CALLIMACHUS. 429 


fact that he had no followers in Macedonia as a proof of the 
ungenial nature of the soil to which he was transplanted, and 
as an additional tribute to the zeal and good management 
by which the Ptolemies converted their African city into a 
second Athens. : 

§ 4. The established type of an Alexandrian man of letters, 
the most finished specimen of what might be effected by dis- 
tinguished talents, unwearied learning, and the mere ambition 
to obtain the praise of contemporaries, when backed by the 
active patronage of a court, may be seen in CaLiimacuus, who 
was the librarian of Ptolemy Philadelphus, the head of his 
museum, the teacher of Apollonius the poet, Eratosthenes the 
philosopher and historian, and Aristophanes the grammarian 
and critic, and himself the literary dictator and universal 
genius of his age. The following particulars, mainly derived 
from Suidas,' contain all that is known of his life. He was a 
native of Cyrene, son of Battus and Mesatme, and belonging to 
the founder’s kin or clan of the Battiade. His grandfather, 
also called Callimachus, had been general of the Cyreneans.’ 
Educated by the grammarian Hermocrates, he established him- 
self as a schoolmaster in a suburb of Alexandria, called Eleusis, 
and gained such reputation by his various writings that he was 
appointed to the place of chief librarian, when it became vacant 
by the death of Zenodotus, about B.c. 260; and he filled this 
office for the remainder of his life. The year of his death is 
not known, but Aulus Gellius says that he was still flourishing 
at the commencement of the first Punic war,’ and it is known 
that he was alive in the reign of Euergetes.* It is pretty clear, 





1 Καλλίμαχος, vids Βάττου καὶ Mecdruas [Μεγατίμας Hemsterh.], Κυρηναῖος, 
γραμματικός, μαθητὴς Ἑρμοκράτους τοῦ ᾿Ἰάσεως, γραμματικοῦ, γαμετὴν ἐσχηκὼς τὴν 
Ἑῤφράτου τοῦ Συρακουσιοῦ θυγατέρα, οὕτω δὲ γέγονεν ἐπιμελέστατος ὡς γράψαι μὲν 
ποιήματα εἰς πᾶν μέτρον, συντάξαι δὲ καὶ καταλογάδην πλεῖστα, καὶ ἐστὶν αὐτῷ τὰ 
γεγραμμένα βιβλία ὑπὲρ τὰ ὦ" ἐπὶ δὲ τῶν χρόνων ἣν Πτολεμαίου τοῦ Φιλαδέλφου. 
πρὶν δὲ συσταθῇ τῷ βασιλεῖ γράμματα ἐδίδαξεν ἐν ᾿Ελευσῖνι κωμυδρίῳ τῆς ᾿Αλεξαν- 
δρείας. καὶ παρέτεινε μέχρι τοῦ Evepyérou κληθέντος ἸΤτολεμαίου. : 

2 Callim. Zpigr. XXII. Anthol. Pal. VII. 525: 

ὅστις ἐμὸν παρὰ σῆμα φέρεις πόδα Καλλιμάχου pe, 
ἴσθι ἹΚυρηναίου παῖδά τε καὶ γενετήν. 
εἰδείης δ᾽ ἄμφω κεν. ὁ μέν κοτε πατρίδος ὅπλων 
ἦρξεν" ὁ δ᾽ ἤεισεν κρέσσονα βασκανίης. 
3 Noctes Attice, XVII. 41, 21. 4 Suidas, u. s. 


430 THE SCHOOL OF ALEXANDRIA—POBTS. 


at any rate, that he did not die before Ol. 133, B.c. 248—245.' 
His wife was a daughter of Euphrates of Syracuse; and his 
sister Megatime, who married Stasenor, had a son Callimachus, 
who wrote an epic poem ‘on the islands’ (περὶ νήσων), and is 
distinguished from his uncle as Callimachus the younger. 

Few writers have been more prolific than Callimachus. 
Living in the midst of books, and engaged in incessant study, 
he seems to have thought himself obliged to write in verse or 
prose on every subject which he had read about ; and he believed 
at last that he was not only omniscient, but enjoyed a monopoly 
of knowledge. Hence we find that some of his works are 
expressly directed against literary men of rising eminence, whom 
he regarded as poaching on his manor, and his own pupil, 
Apollonius of Rhodes, was a special object of his jealousy. 
It is stated by Suidas that his works were eight hundred in 
number. This means, of course, that every separate poem and 
pamphlet was counted as a distinct work; and, with the 
exception of the Hecale, which he wrote to show that he could 
manage to compose a lengthened poem, Callimachus used to 
justify, by his own practice, his saying, which has become so 
celebrated, that ‘a great book is a great evil.”* It was his 
object, as he tells us in answer to Apollonius and the other 
critics, who thought nothing of a poet unless he could pour 
forth an ocean of words, to give little, but pure and undefiled 
drops from the sacred fountain.* And it is therefore possible 





1 Clinton, F. H. 5. a. B.c. 256, extends his life to B.c. 230, but see Merkel in 
the Prolegomena to his edition of Apollonius Rhodius, Lips. 1854, pp. XI. seqq. 

2 Suidas: Καλλίμαχος Κυρηναῖος ἐποποιός, ἀδελφιδοῦς τοῦ προτέρου, vids Στασή- 
νορος καὶ Μεγατίμας τῆς ἀδελφῆς Καλλιμάχουι And in the former article: ἀδελφῆς 
δὲ αὐτοῦ παῖς ἣν ὁ νέος Καλλίμαχος ὁ γράψας περὶ νήσων δι᾿ ἐπῶν. The writer of the 
article Callimachus in Smith’s Dictionary, calls his father Stasenorus, which is not 
a Greek word. 

3 Athen. III. p. 72 A: ὅτι Καλλίμαχος ὁ γραμματικὸς τὸ μέγα βιβλίον ἴσον, 
ἔλεγεν, εἶναι τῷ μεγάλῳ κακῷ. 

4 Hymn, ad Apollinem, 105 sqq. : 

ὁ Φθόνος ᾿Απόλλωνος ἐπ᾽ οὔατα λάθριος εἶπεν" 
“οὐκ ἄγαμαι τὸν ἀοιδὸν ὃς οὐδ᾽ ὅσα πόντος ἀείδει.᾽ 
τὸν Φθόνον ὡπόλλων ποδί τ᾽ ἤλασεν ὧδέ τ᾽ ἔειπεν" 
“᾿Ασσυρίου ποταμοῖο μέγας ῥόος, ἀλλὰ τὰ πολλὰ 
λύματα γῆς καὶ πολλὸν ἐφ᾽ ὕδατι συρφετὸν ἕλκει. 
Δηοῖ δ᾽ οὐκ ἀπὸ παντὸς ὕδωρ φορέουσι Μέλισσαι, 


CALLIMACHUS. 431 


that he may have made up the large number of writings 
attributed to him in the shape of hymns, elegies, epigrams, and 
fugitive pieces in prose. Of all these writings, we have only 
a few poems; and one of these is extant merely in a Latin 
translation by Catullus, a man of greater poetical genius than 
Callimachus, but who took the Alexandrian poet as his model 
for taste and style. The prose writings of this great gram- 
marian would have been very instructive from the recondite 
reading in which they abounded. But they are all lost; and 
his poetry fully justifies the accurate criticism of Ovid, that 
his celebrity was assured, though he was distinguished by skill, 
and not by genius.’ 

The extant poems of Callimachus are :— 

(1.) Six hymns: five in hexameter verse, and in imitation 
of Homer, namely, ‘To Zeus,’ ‘To Apollo,” ‘To Artemis,’ ‘To 
Delos,’ and ‘To Demeter ;? and one in Doric hexameters and 
pentameters, ‘On the Bath of Pallas.’ These poems are little 
better than mythological scholia in ingenious and musical verse. 
In the last, the poet describes rather pleasingly how Pallas in- 
flicted blindness on Teiresias, who came upon her while bathing 





ἀλλ᾽ ἥτις καθαρή τε καὶ dxpdavros ἀνέρπει 

πίδακος ἐξ ἱερῆς ὀλίγη λιβάς, ἀκρὸν ἄωτον. 

χαῖρε, ἄναξ' ὁ δὲ Μῶμος, ἵνα φθορος, ἔνθα νέοιτο. 

This passage is of some importance in regard to the literary history of Calli- 
machus and Apollonius. It seems from v. 67: 
καὶ ὥὦὥμοσε τείχεα δώσειν 

ἡμετέροις βασιλεῦσίν, ἀεὶ δ᾽ εὔορκος ᾿Απόλλων--- 
that the hymn to Apollo was written for the feast in honour of that God instituted 
by Philadelphus (Vitruv. Pref. libr. VII.), about the time when Euergetes married 
Berenice, the daughter of Magas, king of Cyrene. This would fall about the time 
when Apollonius published the first part of his Argonautics, and as the poem is in- 
scribed to Apollo, it may have been recited at the same feast. The criticism to 
which Callimachus here replies, in an epilogue manifestly added afterwards, was 
probably that of Apollonius. This is shown by the manner in which Apollonius 
parodies the words of Callimachus, Argon. III. 932 sqq. : 

ἀκλείης ὅδε μάντις ὅς οὐδ᾽ ὅσα παῖδες ἴσασιν 

οἷδε νόῳ φράσσασθαι. 
And it is not unlikely that Apollonius wrote these words at Rhodes, where he was 
composing his third book, and the μείδησε δὲ Μόψος ἀκούσας (v. 938) shows that he 
no longer entertained any bitter animosity against his old teacher. See Merkel 
(Prol. in Apollon. pp. XII. XVIII. XIX.). 

1 Amor., 15, 14: 
Battiades semper toto cantabitur orbe : 
Quamvis ingenio non valet, arte valet. 


432 THE SCHOOL OF ALEXANDRIA—POETS. 


with her chosen companion his mother Chariclo, but consoled 
him on her account with the gift of prophecy. This poem was 
translated into Latin elegiac verse by the celebrated Angelo 
Poliziano, who wished to be the Catullus of revived classical 
Latinity. 

(2.) Seventy-six epigrams, which have very considerable 
merit, being in fact among the best of their kind. They are 
preserved in the Anthologia, sometimes, however, attributed to 
other writers, such as Simonides, Bacchylides, Leonidas of 
Tarentum, or Tymnes, The 76th is preserved in a Latin 
translation, and may be the production of some modern poet. 
The epigrams of Callimachus were commented on by Archibius 
soon after that poet’s death, and paraphrased in iambic lines 
by Marianus, who flourished in the reign of Anastasius, and 
performed the same office for the epic poems of Callimachus 
and Apollonius, for the idyls of Theocritus, and for the 
Phenomena of Aratus, 

(3.) Elegies, which exist only in fragments, or in imitations 
by the Roman poets. We have seen that Propertius con- 
stantly couples Philetas with Callimachus, as his models, and 
the great objects of his admiration. It is supposed that the 
20th of Ovid’s Heroidum LEpistole is borrowed from the 
Cydippe of Callimachus. ‘And it. is known that the Coma 
Berenices,' which appears among the elegies of Catullus, is a 
close translation, sometimes word for word,’ of a poem in which 
the court poet of Alexandria recognized among the stars the 
beautiful tresses, which Berenice, the wife of Ptolemy Euergetes, 
had suspended in the temple in performance of a vow, but 
which had been sacrilegiously abstracted. This poem, which 
is perhaps the most far-fetched effort of court flattery in 





1 Merkel has shown (Prolegom. ad Apollonii Argonautica, Lips. 1854, p. xii.) 
that the Berenice in question was the daughter of Magas, king of Cyrene, who 
was married to Ptolemy Euergetes, and that the captam Asiam Aigypti finibus 
addiderat of the poem refers to the conquests of the third Ptolemy in Asia Minor, 
when he founded the city of Berenice in Cilicia, and named it in honour of this 
queen. 

2 The following are some of the fragments of Callimachus, which correspond 
exactly to the translation of Catullus :— 

Idem me ille Conon ccelesti munere vidit 
E Berenices vertice cesariem, ; 


CALLIMACHUS. 433 


existence, represents the lost tresses as describing their own 
deification. They have the extravagance of Pope’s Rape of the 
Lock, without its wit or consistency. Yet they attracted the 
admiration of Catullus, one of the most original of the Latin 
poets, and, at the revival of letters, Salviano of Florence en- 
deavoured to reproduce the Greek original from the Latin 
translation. 

The lost writings of Callimachus included two epic poems, 
the Airia and the ‘ExaXn, to which we have frequent references. 
The former, which Marianus paraphrased, was an antiquarian 
poem in four books, on the causes and origin of mythologies, 
religious usages, and other curiosities of literature, and may be 
regarded as bearing the same relation to the more general 
disquisitions of Ephorus and Theopompus that the Hecale did 
to the Atthis, properly so called. This latter poem, the frag- 
ments of which have been submitted to a searching exami- 
nation by an eminent modern scholar,’ derives its name from a 
hospitable old woman,’ who entertained Theseus with supper 
and mythology when he was on his way to encounter the 
Marathonian bull. The work, which his contemporary Philo- 





Fulgentem clare: quam multis ille Deorum 
Levia protendens brachia pollicita est. 
ἥ με Kovwv ἔβλεψεν ἐν ἠέρι τὸν Βερενίκης 
βόστρυχον ὃν κείνη πᾶσιν ἔθηκε θεοῖς. 
| Theo in Arat. Phan. 146, 
Adjuro teque tuumque caput. 
σήν τε κάρην ὥμοσα σόν τε βίον. 
Etym. M. 450, 32. 


Juppiter ut Chalybum omne genus pereat. 
Zed πάτερ, ws Χαλύβων wav ἀπόλοιτο γένος. 
Schol. Ap. Rh. I. 1323. 
It has been supposed that the fragment in the Hiym. M.s8.v. ᾿Ασσύριοι: ἢ ἀπ᾽, 
(Blomfield ji.’ ἐπ᾽), ᾿Ασσυρίων ἡμεδαπὴ στρατιὴ corresponds to the lines in Catullus: 


Qua rex tempestate novo auctus hymenzo 
Vastatum fines iverat Assyrios. 


But the version is hardly close enough, unless we adopt the other opinion that 
Catullus sometimes departed from the letter of his original; see Nike, Rhein. 
Mus. 1837, p. 13. 
1 A. FB. Nike in the Rheinisches Museum, 1834, pp. 509—588; 1835, pp. 509— 
588; 1837, pp. I—I100. 
2 On the name of Ἑ κάλη, see New Cratylus, § 276. 
Vou. II. FF 


434 THE SCHOOL OF ALEXANDRIA—POETS. 


chorus wrote on the Tetrapolis of Marathon, may have fur- 
nished Callimachus with some of the materials for this versifi- 
cation of legends. The long episode about Visv4mitra, which 
Janaca tells Rama on a. similar occasion, in the Sanscrit 
Epos, represents, in spirit at least, the aged Hecale’s out- 
pourings of Attic lore.’ The Galatea and Glaucus were pro- 
bably epic poems of a similar description. Of the tragedies, 
comedies, and choliambics of Callimachus we have not a trace. 
The Ibis, so called from the Egyptian bird, sacred to. Thoth 
or Hermes, which was worshipped for its services in keeping 
down the plague of serpents and other dangerous reptiles,? 
would have furnished a chapter on the quarrels of authors. It 
was written expressly against Apollonius, the quondam pupil of 
Callimachus, whom his master from literary jealousy had 
begun to regard with the most rancorous animosity. We 
have an imitation of it in the attack which Ovid wrote under 
the same title against Hyginus or some other literary opponent, 

The numerous prose works of Callimachus are lost altogether, 
and if they had been extant we must have reserved the con- 
sideration of them to the following chapter. It is sufficient to 
mention here the work, which would have been most serviceable 
to us, and which was most intimately connected with the general 
business of Callimachus as head of the great library at Alex- 
andria. This was a sort of encyclopedia of Greek literary 
history, a Catalogue Raisonné of all the books in the Alex- 
andrian Bibliotheca. It extended to 120 books or rolls of 
papyrus,® and was no doubt the result of the labours attributed 





1 Rdmdyana, I. cc. 50-65. 

2 It is difficult to see why Apollonius was called by the name of this bird, or 
what reproach was involved in the designation. Its services as a scavenger were 
meritorious, and its religious connexion with Hermes was eminently respectable. 
There may have been some pungent irony in the appellation, just as we might 
call a pedantic scholar ‘an owl,’ from the bird of Minerva. Or it may have been 
intended to intimate the want of a power of judicious selection which Callimachus 
seems to impute to Apollonius in the words quoted above from the epilogue to 
the Hymn to Apollo: 

τὰ πολλὰ 
λύματα γῆς καὶ πολλὸν ἐφ᾽ ὕδατι συρφετὸν ἕλκει. 


3 Suidas: πίνακες τῶν ἐν πάσῃ παιδείᾳ διαλαμψάντων καὶ ὧν συνέγραψαν ἐν βιβλίοις 
κ' καὶ ρ΄. See Bernhardy, Grundriss der Griech. Literatur, I. p. 134. 


LYCOPHRON. 435 


to Callimachus by the author of the fragmentary scholium on 
Plautus,—namely, that he wrote the titles of all the books in 
the library—for this would presume that he made himself ac- 
quainted with their contents. A similar work was his Museum, 
which probably gave an account generally of the literary esta- 
blishments of Ptolemy, and of the persons connected with them. 

§ 5. Next to Callimachus, as a representative of the learned 
poetry of Alexandria, we must place the dramatist and drama- 
tologist, Lycorpnron. Notwithstanding his great celebrity, we 
know but few particulars of his career, and, as we shall see, 
some of the most eminent scholars of the present century have 
raised the question whether his extant poem is not to be 
referred to a later writer of the same name. Suidas informs 
us that Lycophron was a native of Chalcis in Eubeea, that his . 
father was Socles, and that he was adopted by Lycus of 
Rhegium,’ an historian who flourished in the time of Alex- 
ander’s immediate successors, and was an object of animosity 
to Demetrius the Phalerian.? It is to be inferred from this 
adoption that he spent some time among the Eubcean colonies ἡ 
of Magna Grecia, which would account for his familiar 
acquaintance with the affairs of Italy. As his adoptive father 
Lycus wrote among other works a history of Libya, we may 
easily conceive the manner in which Lycophron became con- 
nected with the court of Alexandria. To compose such a 
work, Lycus must have visited and perhaps established himself 
in Egypt, and the plot against him attributed to Demetrius 
would seem to imply that they were both at the court of 
Ptolemy, and that the banished Athenian used his influence 
with the king to procure the ruin of a rival author. Be that 
as it may, we know, on the authority of the Scholium on 
Plautus, which has been already cited,*® that Lycophron was 





1 Suidas: Λυκόφρων Χαλκιδεὺς ἀπὸ EvdBolas, vids Σωκλέους, θέσει δὲ Λύκου τοῦ 
Ῥηγίνου, γραμματικὸς καὶ ποιητὴς τραγῳδιῶν. Tzetzes, Chil. VIII. 481, says that 
he was really the son of Lycus. 

2 Suidas: Λύκος ὁ καὶ Bov@jpas, Ῥηγῖνος, ἱστορικός, πατὴρ Λυκόφρονος τοῦ 
τραγικοῦ, ἐπὶ τῶν διαδόχων γεγονὼς καὶ ἐπιβουλευθεὶς ὑπὸ Δημητρίου τοῦ Φαληρέως. 
οὗτος ἔγραψεν ἱστορίαν Λιβύης καὶ περὶ Σικελίας. 

3 Scholion Plautinwm apud Ritschl, Alex. Bibl. p. 3: ‘Alexander Ζζοϊτβ et 
Lycophron Chalcidensis et Zenodotus Ephesius, impulsu regis Ptolemei, Phila- 
delphi cognomento, qui mirum in modum favebat ingeniis et fame doctorum 

FF 2 


436 THE SCHOOL OF ALEXANDRIA—POETS. 


one of the learned men employed by Ptolemy Philadelphus to 
form a collection and arrangement of the Greek poets; and 
while Alexander the Altolian undertook the tragedies, and 
Zenodotus the poems of Homer and other illustrious poets, the 
comedies were assigned to Lycophron. As a result of these 
labours in the library, we are informed that he composed a 
very valuable work on Greek comedy,’ abounding as it seems 
in anecdotes respecting the authors, which, to judge by a 
specimen in Athenzus,’ must have been lively and entertaining. 
But although Lycophron wrote on comedy, his own poetical 
compositions were chiefly tragic dramas. Suidas gives us a 
list of twenty of these plays,’ and Tzetzes attributes to him 


forty-six or sixty-four tragedies. The fragment of his Pelopide ~~ 


quoted by Stobzus is a simple statement of the common 
thought that death, though prayed for by the unfortunate, is 
never welcomed when it really comes.* He also wrote a 
satyrical drama called Menedemus, in which he makes his 
eminent countryman, the head of the school of Eretria, appear 
in the character of a temperate Silenus, teaching the doctrines 
of total abstinence to a chorus of Satyrs. The caricature 
must have been received by the philosopher as good-natured 
and friendly criticism, for we are told that he was very fond of 
Lycophron.’ By these compositions, Lycophron obtained a 
place in the pleiad of Alexandrian tragedians, and his name 





hominum, Greece artis poeticos libros in anum collegerunt et in ordinem redegerunt ; 
Alexander tragoedias, Lycophron comeedias, Zenodotus vero Homeri poemata ei 
reliquorum illustrium poetarum.’ 

1 See Meineke, Hist. Crit. Com, Gr. p. 100, 

2 XIII. p. 555. 

3 They are the Molus, Andromeda, Aletes, Molides, Elephenor, Hercules, Sup- 
plices, Hippolytus, Cassandreis, Laius, Marathonii, Nauplius, Cdipus I. I1., 
Orbus, Pentheus, Pelopide, Socti, Telegonus, Chrysippus. 

* Stob. Flor. 119, 13: 

ἀλλ᾽ ἡνίκ᾽ ἂν μὲν ἢ πρόσω τὸ κατθανεῖν 
ἅδης ποθεῖται τοῖς δεδυστυχηκόσιν. 

ὅταν δ᾽ ἐφέρπῃ κῦμα λοίσθιον βίου 

τὸ ζῆν ποθοῦμεν" οὐ γάρ ἐστ᾽ αὐτοῦ κόρος. 

5 See Athen. X. p. 420. 

6 Diog, Laért. II. p. 177 C: ἠσπάζετο δὲ καὶ "Ἄρατον καὶ Λυκόφρονα τὸν τῆς 
τραγῳδίας ποιητήν. 


LYCOPHRON. 437 


appears in all the lists along with Homerus and Philiscus.' 
His ingenuity was shown by the composition of anagrams, two 
of them being the conversion of Πτολεμαῖος into ἀπὸ μέλιτος, 
and of ᾿Αρσινόη into ἴον Ἥρας," complimentary transpositions 
which were highly appreciated by the courtiers. All the works 
of Lycophron are lost with the exception of the oracular poem 
called Alexandra or Cassandra; in 1474 regular tragic 
trimeters, which has obtained for its author and itself the 
name of ‘the dark or obscure’ (Λυκόφρων ὁ σκοτεινός, τὸ 
σκοτεινὸν ποίημα). The dates of the birth and death of Lyco- 
phron are equally unknown. Ovid, in the Jbis, which he wrote 
in imitation of Callimachus, intimates that Lycophron was 
assassinated by being shot through the heart with an arrow,’ 
but why or by whom we are not told. 

There is no poem of the Alexandrian school which has been 
more honoured by the attention of ancient and modern scholars 
that the Alexandra of Lycophron. The great number of the 
manuscripts shows that it has always been in demand, and it 
may have been adopted at one period as a text-book of 
mythology and geography. An epigram intimates that it was 





1 The following are the four different versions of the Pleiad : 


Suidas. Schol. I. Schol. II. Tzetzes. 
Homerus Homerus Homerus (Theocritus) 
Sositheus Sositheus Sositheus (Aratus) 
Lycophron Lycophron Lycophron (Nicander) 
Alexander Alexander Alexander antides 
Philiscus Philiscus Hantides Philiscus 
Sosiphanes Dionysides Sosiphanes Homerus 

Zantides Philiscus Lycophron 


See Clinton, Κ΄. H. 111. p. 502. 
2 See the note in the appendix to Dehéque’s edition and translation of the 
Alexandra, Paris, 1853 (pp. 68, 69). 
3° Adetdvipa is the only name known to the ancients, Cassandra being a modern 
corruption. 
4 Suidas, Hence Statius says (Silv. III. 5, 156): 
Tu pandere doctus 
Carmina Battiade tenebrasque Lycophronis atri. 
5 Ibis, 531: 
Utque cothurnatum cecidisse Lycophrona narrant, 
Hereat in fibris fixa sagitta tuis. 
5 Boissonade, Biogr. Universelle 8. τι. LycopHron. Canter says (in Lycophr. 
Prolegom. p. VI.) : ‘ affirmare ausim, quicunque hoc poema, licet parvum, diligenter 


438 THE SCHOOL OF ALEXANDRIA—POETS. 


caviar to the multitude.' And besides the scholia of Duris, 
Theon, and Orus, it has been voluminously commented on by 
John Tzetzes. Since the revival of letters, it has been fre- 
quently re-edited, and in England it was published in Greek 
at the beginning of the eighteenth century by one of our most 
learned archbishops,? and was translated into harmonious 
English verse, about fifty years ago, by an accomplished young 
nobleman.* Notwithstanding this celebrity, the identity of 
the author is still a matter of doubt. For while Aristotle 
attributes to a rhetorical sophist of his own time, who bore the 
same name, a love of compound and glossematic words exactly 
like those which we find in Lycophron the poet,’ Lord Royston,’ 
our great orator C. J. Fox,’ and the historian Niebuhr,’ have 
argued, from certain allusions to Rome and Macedon in the 
Alexandra itself, that it could not have been written in the 
reign of Philadelphus, but must have proceeded from some 
author who wrote after the downfal of Perseus at the latter 
end of Ol. 152, B.c. 169. To these objections another eminent 
scholar, F. G. Welcker of Bonn, has replied by the suggestion, 





perlegerint, eos et historiarum et poeticarum fabularum partem non exiguam probe 
perfecteque esse cognituros.’ 
1 Anthol. Pal. IX. 191: els τὴν βίβλον Λυκόφρονοο---- 


el δέ ce φίλατο Κ αλλίοπη λάβε μ᾽ és xépas’ ef δὲ 
νῆϊς ἔφυς Μουσέων, χερσὶ βάρος φορέεις. 


2 Curd et Opera Joannis Potteri, Oxonii, 1697 and 1702. 

3 ‘Cassandra, translated from the original Greek of Lycophron, and illustrated 
with notes, by Viscount Royston, Cambridge, 1806.’ The translator perished 
in the Maelstroom a year or two after the publication of this version, which 
does the greatest credit to his learning and poetical talents. There are few 
translations of Greek poets into English which exhibit a greater command of 
language, or a more sustained power of versification. We have a copy in- 
cluding some of the proof sheets, which show with what carefulness the author 
revised his work. 

4 Rhet. 111. 3, 1—3. 

5 In the Classical Jowrnal, vol. XIII. No. 25, XIV. No. 27, and in the preface 
to his translation. 

6 Correspondence of Wakefield and Fox, published in 1813. Fox states the 
objection first in a letter dated 12th March, 1800 (p, 129), and gives his conclusion 
the 26th Jan., 1801 (p. 171). 

7 Rheinisches Musewm, 1827, pp. 108—117. 


LYCOPHRON. 439 


that the passages in question are probably interpolations. 
‘Tf, he says,’ ‘interpolations may be expected anywhere, a long 
oracular poem is the most probable place for them; and if any 
subject could lead to the continuation of such prophecies, 
surely the morning-dawn of the empire of the world would be 
most likely to do so.’ Without entering at length into the 
controversy, we may be permitted to say that certain inflexions 
and forms of words in the Alexandra? indicate rather a 
Hellenist of the later Alexandrian school, who wrote according 
to new-fangled analogies, than a Greek fresh from the Eubcean 
colonies of Italy, and from the study of the best Attic come- 
dians. On the other hand, there is nothing to have prevented 
an attentive observer, who had been in the south of Italy in 
the interval between the invasion of Pyrrhus and the first 
Punic war, from drawing a formidable picture of the increasing 
power of Rome. If then the original edition of the Alexandra, 
which is universally attributed to Lycophron of Chalcis, con- 
tained any references to the prowess of the Romans, whom 
Leonidas of Tarentum had called ‘invincible’ in B.c. 279, 
the later editors of the work, whose hands are indicated by the 
grammatical peculiarities to which we have referred, would feel 
an irresistible temptation to add some prophecies after the 
event to the ominous presages of the contemporary of Phila- 
delphus, That the prophecies referring to the glory of Rome,* 
and the downfal of Macedon,* are such additions, is shown 
by the fact that the former is inserted after the account of 





1 Die Griech. Trag. pp. 1259—1263. 

2 Such as ἐσχάζοσαν for ἔσχαζον (v. 21), πέφρικαν for πεφρίκασιν (v. 252), &e., 
which belong to the language of the Septuagint: see Sturz, de Dialect. Maced. et 
Alexandrind, p. 58. 

3 In the inscription on the spoils taken in the battles of Heraclea and Asculum, 
B.C. 280, 279, which is preserved in Latin Saturnians. See Niebuhr, H, &, III. 
note 841, and Varronianus, p. 228, ed. 2; where an attempt is made to reproduce 
the original. 

4 vv. 1226—1280. The reference to the δίπτυχοι τόκοι Μυσῶν ἄνακτος, Τάρχων 
τε καὶ Tuponvos (1245—1248), indicates a considerable knowledge of the ethnography 
of Italy, and is quite in accordance with the present writer’s theory as to the 
distinct origin of the Etruscans and Tyrsenians: see Varronianus, p. 71, and 
elsewhere. 

5 vv. 1446—1450. 


440 THE SCHOOL OF ALEXANDRIA—POBTS. 


the disasters of Idomeneus and his family, and before the 
lines :-—’ 

Such woes, so hard to bear, shall they endure 

Who soon will devastate my native land. 


And the definite reference to the overthrow of Perseus as sixth 
in descent from Alexander’ is the close of the poem, where such 
an addition would naturally be appended. 

With regard to the poetical merits of this extraordinary 
production, the most diverse opinions have been expressed, 
The German critics will not allow it to be called a poem, One 
of them® terms it ‘a grammatical monster, in which a store- 
house of nomenclature, consisting in mythical and geographical 
names of rare occurrence, in glossematical words from Aischylus 
and other poets, and in bombastic compounds, is employed, 
without any gain to mythology,’ and tells us that it has no 
spirit, and cannot be read with any pleasure; and Niebuhr 
thinks that the word ‘ poem’ would be misapplied in speaking 
of the Alexandra.* On the other hand, a great English orator 
is soothed by its melancholy strain, and an eminent scholar 
reads it again and again with increasing gratification : and we 
have an English version of it, which, if it is obscure and 





1 y, 1281: 
τοσαῦτα μὲν δύστλητα πείσονται κακά 
οἱ τὴν ἐμὴν μέλλοντες αἰστώσειν πάτραν. 


2 See Lord Royston’s Preface, p. X., where the six generations are counted from 
Alexander the Great, in the persons of the five lineal descendants of Antigonus, 
namely, Demetrius, Antigonus Gonatas, Demetrius II., Philip V., Perseus. 
Dehtque counts 207 years from the expedition of Xerxes, B.c. 480, to the treaty 
between the Romans and Ptolemy Philadelphus, in B.c. 273, to which he thinks 
the six generations refer. 

3 Bernhardy, Grundriss d. Gr. Lit. II. p. 1027. : 

4 Rhein. Mus. 1827, p. 112. Schlegel calls the Alexandra, ‘einen endlosen, 
weissagenden mit dunkler Mythologie iiberladenen Monolog,’ and Wachler terms 
it, ‘ ein verkiinstelt-dunkles prophetisch-episches Monodrama.’ 

5 Gilbert Wakefield says, in a letter to Charles James Fox (u.s. p. 120): 
‘Lycophron by all means read—a spirit of melancholy breathes through his 
poem, which makes him, with his multitude of events, as delightful to me as 
any of the ancients. I have read him very often, and always with additional 
gratification. His poem is delivered in the form of a prophecy, and therefore 
affects an enigmatical obscurity by enveloping the sentiment in imagery, mytho- 
logical allusions, and a most learned and elaborate phraseology. You cannot fail, 
I think, after the first difficulties are surmounted, to like him very much.’ Fox 
replies (p. 128): ‘I have lately read Lycophron, and am much obliged to you for 


LYCOPHRON. 44ϊ 


enigmatical like the original Greek, is at least conceived in 
the highest elevation of poetical language. We are not able to 
compare the poem with the Αἴτια of Callimachus and other 
versifications of mythology, but it appears to us. that for the 
kind of thing which it pretends to be, and for the special 
taste which it was intended to gratify, it is neither an unskilful 
nor an unpleasing composition. The oracular obscurity was of 
course intentional; and it afforded, no doubt, considerable 
amusement to the ingenious scholars of Alexandria to interpret 
familiar allusions clothed in enigmatic phraseology. The poem 
begins with a few lines addressed to Priam by the guard whom 
he had set over Cassandra, in which there is an apology for the 
length of the predictions. And then we have in Cassandra’s 
own words the prophecy which she uttered when Paris was 
setting sail for Greece. This prophecy begins with a reference 
to the exploits of Hercules, whose Pheenician mythology was 
not unknown to the poet. It passes on to the history of 
the Trojan war and its immediate results in the wanderings 
and other misfortunes of the Greek leaders. It then reverts 
to the old legends of enmity between Asia and Europe, of which 
the Trojan war was a special development, and the counter- 
invasions of Xerxes and Alexander the final consummation. 
After all this, Cassandra checks herself abruptly with the re- 
flexion that no one will believe her presages. And the poem 
concludes with a prayer from the guard on behalf of his master’s 


house :— 
But oh! may all these woes be turned to joy ! 
Still may the God who watches o’er thy house 
Spread round thy bosom his protecting shield, 
And guard with arms divine the Phrygian throne! 


On the whole, we are inclined to think that Lycophron has 
left us a favourable specimen of the versified and diversified 
learning, which delighted the courtiers of Ptolemy Philadelphus. 

§ 6. The Alexandrian poets, whom we have hitherto dis- 
cussed—Philetas of Cos, Callimachus of Cyrene, and Lycophron 
of Chalcis—were foreigners attracted to Alexandria by the 





recommending me to do so; besides there being some very charming poetry in 
him, the variety of stories is very entertaining.’ And in another letter he says 
(p. 137): ‘to my mind nothing was ever more soothing, in the melancholy strain, 
than many passages in Lycophron,’ 


4492 THE SCHOOL OF ALEXANDRIA—POETS. 


literary fame of the city and the prospect of royal patronage. 
We now pass on to one who was a native Alexandrian, educated 
in the Museum, and brought up in the philosophic court circle 
of Philadelphus, but compelled by the jealousy and ill-will of 
Callimachus to leave his native place, and not welcomed back 
again until he had achieved a reputation in the distant island 
which has given him his usual epithet. Arozionivs, generally 
known as ‘ the Rhodian,’ was the son of Silleus or Ileus of 
Alexandria, where he was born some time in Ol. 126, 127, 
B.C. 276—269, being a contemporary of Eratosthenes, whom 
he ultimately succeeded in the librariauship. Athenzus calls 
him ‘the Rhodian or Naucratite,' and is followed by Ailian. 
The former collector may have had no other reason for con- 
necting Apollonius with his own city Naucratis than the fact 
that the poet wrote a book on the foundation of that place, 
from which Atheneus is quoting in the particular passage. 
This would be an equally good reason for assigning him to 
Caunus or Canopus, for he wrote on the origin of those cities 
also. It is expressly stated that Apollonius was not only an 
Alexandrian,’ but belonged to the tribe called Ptolemais in that 
city.“ He was a scholar of Callimachus; but it appears that 
some early misunderstanding between the teacher and his pupil 
soon developed itself into a deadly quarrel between them. The 
particulars are not known to us, and we are left to the con- 
clusion, which is supported by incidental statements, that the 
younger poet either rejected the dictation of the veteran critic, 
or excited his jealousy by attempting a more ambitious style of 
poetry, or entered into direct rivalry with him by reciting his 
Argonautica at a feast of Apollo, for which Callimachus had 
prepared his own hymn to that god.’ There are many examples 
in the history of literature of this opposition between the head 
of a school and some prominent disciple; and we have seen in 
the case of Aristotle that there is a tendency to impute this 
feeling of conscious rivalry even when it does not exist—a 
proof, at least, that the antagonism is not considered unnatural. 





1 Athen. VII. 283 Ὁ: ᾿Απολλώνιος ὁ ‘Pddios ἢ Navxparirns ἐν Navxpdrews 
κτίσει. 

2 Hist, Anim. XV. 3. 3 Strabo XIV. p. 655. 

4 Suidas, . δ Above, p. 431 [271] note. 


APOLLONIUS. 443 


As far as we can judge from the few circumstances known to 
us, the quarrel between Callimachus and Apollonius originated 
in some discrepancy of opinion with regard to the subjects and 
mode of treatment best suited for epic poetry. The chief effort 
of Callimachus in this field was his poem called Atria; and an 
epigram attributed to Apollonius is still extant, in which a 
most abusive reference is made to this work of the older poet.’ 
On the other hand, Apollonius had selected for his subject one 
which admitted of a more purely Homeric treatment, and in 
which the book-learning of the Alexandrian school would 
become subservient to the elaboration of a well-known and in- 
teresting story. The antagonistic principles of the younger poet 
were perhaps exhibited in the familiar discussions of the Museum 
with little deference to the veteran librarian who guided the taste 
of the court and of the city. And when Apollonius published his 
poem in the usual way, namely, by a public recitation of it, and 
in this particular instance, at a feast of Apollo,’ it was probably by 
the influence of Callimachus that it was condemned and rejected. 
The young poet was so mortified by this failure, and his literary 
prospects so blighted by the ill-will and opposition of the head 
of the Alexandrian school and his partizans, that he left his 
native city and established himself as a teacher of rhetoric in 
the island of Rhodes, which was in some sort a rival to 
Alexandria as a seat of learning. Here his genius and attain- 
ments were adequately appreciated, and he became the most 
renowned man of letters in his adopted country. The Rhodians 
honoured him with the full franchise and some other distinctions 





1 Anthol. Pal. XI. 275: ᾿Απολλωνίου γραμματικοῦ---- 
Καλλίμαχος τὸ κάθαρμα, τὸ παίγνιον, ὁ ξύλινος νοῦς, 
αἴτιος, ὁ γράψας Αἴτια Καλλιμάχου. 
Merkel supposes very ingeniously (Proleg. ad Apollon. p. XXI.), that Apollonius 
here uses the word κάθαρμα, in the sense of ‘mythological rubbish’ (Niebuhr, 
H, R. ΤΙ, p. το), and with a playful reference to the word κάταργμα, which, as he 
conjectures, may have been used in the Αἴτια, as the ἄκρος dwres of the Hymn to 
Apollo, v. 112, cf. Hiym. M. p. 53,1. 53. The fourth book of the Aira treated of 
rites and usages ; among these may have been the ἐπικρήνια (ἑορτὴ Δήμητρος παρὰ 
Λάκωσιν, Hesych.), to his treatment of which Callimachus perhaps alludes in the 
epilogue to Hymn to Apollo, 110: 
Δηοῖ δ᾽ οὐκ ἀπὸ παντὸς ὕδωρ φορέουσι μέλισσαι. 
2 Above, p. 431 [271], note. 


444 THE SCHOOL OF ALEXANDRIA—POETS. 


—perhaps a seat in their senate—and he took from thenceforth 
the name of Rhodian. It is expressly stated that he revised 
and considerably improved the epic poem, which was so ill 
received at Alexandria, but there is no doubt that in plan and 
conception it was substantially the same, and it still retains 
the dedication to Apollo, which was probably due to the 
recitation of the poem at the feast of Apollo, instituted by 
Philadelphus, when Apollonius and Callimachus were brought 
into rivalry with one another.’ From his independent position 
in the island of Rhodes he was enabled to make Callimachus 
feel the effects of his vindictive criticism. The old poet retorted 
by an obscure and scurrilous poem, in which he assailed Apol- 
lonius as an 7018. or devourer of reptiles and vermin,’ and showed 
by more than one incidental allusion how he smarted under 
the blows of his rival, and feared the posthumous consequences 
of his detraction. The established reputation, which Apollonius 
gained by his epic poem, led to his recall or voluntary return 
to Alexandria. This was certainly after the death of Calli- 
machus, perhaps not till the reign of Epiphanes, when the 
librarianship again became vacant by the decease of Eratosthenes, 
whom Apollonius was appointed to succeed in B.c, 194. How 
long he held this office, and when he died, we are not informed. 
He was most probably librarian at the time of his death, about 
Ol. 147, 4. B.c. 193—18g; and, according to one account, was 
buried in the same tomb as Callimachus. 

Apollonius wrote grammatical works ‘ on Archilochus,’* and 
‘against Zenodotus,’* and a number of poems relating to the 
foundations (κτίσεις) of various cities. That ‘on Canopus’ 
seems to have been composed in choliambic verse.’ Of his 
epigrams we have only the one on Callimachus, which has been 





1 See above, p. 431 [271], note. 

2 On the title of this poem Merkel remarks (Prolegom. in Apollon. p. XXI.): 
‘ scriptam olim conjiciebam, quo tempore Apollonius Rhodii cognomen adsumpsisset, 
quod biographus testatur, p. 532, 27: ut Callimachus patriam minus illustrem 
Naucratin ei objecerit.’ As we have already mentioned, the reference to 
Naucratis as the birthplace of Apollonius is probably due to the wish on the part 
of Athenzus to claim the poet for his own native place, and the Jbis would not 
refer him to Naucratis rather than any other Egyptian town. 

3 Athen. X. p. 451, D. . 4 Schol. JU. 7, 657. 

5 See Steph. Byz. s.vy. χώρα, Κόρινθος. 


APOLLONIUS. 445 


already cited. His reputation depends on his epic poem ‘on 
the Argonautic expedition’ ( Αργοναυτικά) in four books, of 
which the fourth is the longest, and containing altogether 5835 
lines. This poem has come down to us complete,—indeed, 
with traces of its two distinct recensions by the author,'—and 
illustrated by elaborate scholia of a very early date, which are 
a repertorium of information on many points of antiquarian 
interest. Apollonius could hardly have chosen a better subject 
for a poem, which was to combine the properties of the old 
epos with an opportunity for displaying the erudition of an 
Alexandrian scholar. The fourth Pythian ode of Pindar had 
developed some of the epic qualities of the Argonautic 
legend, and had connected it with the establishment of a Greek 
colony at Cyrene. And it was perhaps on this account, among 
others, that Callimachus resented the choice of such a subject 
by his scholar, when he had himself neglected or declined to 
commemorate the legendary glories of his own family. Be- 
sides having a good love-story, and a plentiful supply of super- 
natural incidents, the expedition of the Argonauts enabled a 
learned poet to introduce any amount of geographical or mytho- 
logical episodes. The heroes themselves belonged to a period 
immediately preceding the Trojan war, in which their sons took 
a prominent part, and had appeared in the old epic, lyric, and 
dramatic poems of the classical period. And their popularity at 
Alexandria is indicated hy the use which Theocritus has made 
of some of their adventures. The subject, then, in spite of 
Callimachus, could not fail to be attractive; and it cannot be 
denied, that Apollonius has treated it with considerable skill, 
and, all things considered, with wonderful freedom from affec- 
tation.” The language is the conventional epic style founded 
on a careful study of Homer, whose words are not always used 





1 This subject has been fully discussed by Gerhard, Lectiones Apolloniane, 
Lip. 1816. See also Bernhardy, Grundriss, II. pp. 235 sqq. 

2 Our great orator, Charles James Fox, had a high opinion of Apollonius. When 
he had only read a portion of the Argonautica, he wrote to Wakefield (u. s. p. 109) : 
‘from what I have read, he seems to be held far too low by Quintilian [X. 
I, ὃ 54], nor can 1 think the equalis mediocritas to be his character.’ What he had 
read appeared to him ‘as fine poetry as can be.’ And when he had studied the 
whole poem, and compared it with the imitations by Virgil and Ovid (p. 194), he 
was still able to say (p. 211): ‘there are some parts of Apollonius, such as Lib. 


446 THE SCHOOL OF ALEXANDRIA—POETS. 


in their original signification, as it has been established by the 
researches of modern philologers. The effect is much the 
same as if an English poet of the nineteenth century were to 
undertake a poem in the style of Chaucer, or, to adduce an 
actual case, it was the same as if Chatterton had published his 
forgeries in his own name instead of assuming that of the old 
monk Rowley. Apollonius has the usual fault of imitative 
poets—a liability to artificial exaggeration, instead of that 
natural wonder which belongs to an earlier form of civilization.’ 
For example, no ancient Epopceist would have said of Jason’s 
cloak that the eye could easier gaze on the noontide sun than 
on its brilliant scarlet. Such an exaggeration would have been 
reserved by Homer for the blaze of golden armour wrought by 
Vulcan.* There is great inequality in the delineation of cha- 
racter. The impersonation of Jason, who is the hero of the 
piece, is very indistinct; but the love of Medea is painted in 
very vivid colours, and nothing can be prettier or more natural 
than the embarrassment of the maiden, when she is left alone 
with her lover in the temple of Hecate;* and there is exquisite 
tenderness in the passage where she tells Jason how she shall 
think of him when he is far away, and how she will know, by 
some instinct or omen, whether he remembers his deliverer.’ 
There is also a good rough trait of Hercules, when the heroes 
look to him as their leader, and he tells them that the man 
who mustered the crew ought to be captain ;° and the sulkiness 





III. from 453 to 463, and from 807 to 816, that appear to me unrivalled.’ Lon- 
ginus calls him ἄπτωτος (De Subl. XXXIII. 4). , 
1 We find special examples of this in the florid rhetoric of Lucan. What Homeric 
hero would have been made to act like the historical Sceeva? (Pharsal. VI. 217.) 
2 Argon. I. 725, 6: 
THs μὲν ῥηΐτερόν κεν és ἠέλιον ἀνιόντα 
ὄσσε βάλοις ἢ κεῖνο μεταβλέψειας ἔρευθος. 
8. Iliad XVI. 70, XVIII. ότο. 
4 Argonaut. III. 962—965, 1008 sqq. 
5 Ibid. 1109 sqq. : 
ἀλλ᾽ οἷον τυνὴ μὲν ἐμεῦ, ὅτ᾽ Τωλκὸν ἵκηαι, 
μνώεο, σεῖο δ᾽ ἐγὼ καὶ ἐμῶν ἀέκητι τοκήων 
μνήσομαι" ἔλθοι ὃ ἡμὶν ἀπόπροθεν ἠέ τις ὅσσα, 
ἦέ τις ἄγγελος ὄρνις ὅτ᾽ ἐκλελάθοιο ἐμεῖο. 
61,343: 
ὁ δ᾽ αὐτόθεν, ἔνθα περ ἧστο 
δεξιτέρην ἀνὰ χεῖρα τανύσσατο φώνησέν τε" 


EUPHORION, RHIANUS, NICANDER. 447 


of Idas is well described.’ The poem is full of epigrammatic 
prettinesses and neatly turned commonplaces; as when he 
expresses the trite sentiment that mortal joy is ever mixed 
with anxiety,’ or when he paints, in a few touches, the stillness 
of night. He sometimes rises to a higher strain, as when he 
makes Medea meditate on suicide* and combat the thought 
with reflections on the sweets of life,’ in a strain not altogether 
unworthy of a great dramatist. On the whole, we are not dis- 
posed to underrate this effort of the Alexandrian school, and 
we think that it deserves more attention than has been paid to 
it by classical students in this country. The value which was 
set upon the work by the ancients is shown by the antiquity of 
the scholia, which are derived from nearly contemporary com- 
mentaries by Lucillus of Tarra, Sophocles, and Theon,® and 
by the attempts to translate or imitate the poem which were 
made by the learned Romans P. Terentius Varro Atacinus, 
and Valerius Flaccus. At a later period Marianus para- 
phrased the poem in iambic trimeters. 

Evrnorton of Chalcis and Ruranus of Crete, who obtained 
considerable reputation as epic poets, and represented the prin- 
ciples and taste of the Alexandrian school, though the former 
does not appear to have visited the city of the Ptolemies, have 
not left any adequate specimens of their writings. We have 
two specimens of didactic versification from the pen of NicanDER 
of Colophon, who lived in the reigns of Ptolemy Epiphanes 
and the last Attalus (B.c. 185, 135). 

Rhianus and Euphorion flourished in the latter part of the 
third century B.c., and were, therefore, contemporaries of Era- 





‘uh τις ἐμοὶ τόδε κῦδος drdfeTw’ οὐ yap ἔγωγε 
πείσομαι, ὥστε καὶ ἄλλον ἀναστήσεσθαι ἐρύξω. 
αὐτός, ὅτις συγάγειρε, καὶ ἀρχεύοι ὁμάδοιο.᾽ 
11, 462 sqq., ITI. 556 sqq. 
2 IV. 1165 sqq. : 
ἀλλὰ γὰρ οὔποτε φῦλα δυηπαθέων ἀνθρώπων 
τερπωλῆς ἐπέβημεν ὅλῳ ποδί" σὺν δέ τις αἰεὶ 
πικρὴ παρμέμβλωκεν ἐϊφροσύνῃσιν avin. 
8 ΤΙ], 746—750. 4 Ibid. III. 771 sqq. 
5 Tbid. 111, 811 sqq. 
6 Vit. Apollon.: παράκειται τὰ σχόλια ἐκ τῶν τοῦ Λουκίλχου Ταῤῥαίου καὶ Dodo- 
κλέους καὶ Θέωνος. Cf. Schol. Aristoph. Nub. 397. Steph. Byz. s. vv. “ABapvos, 
Κάναστρον. 


448 THE SCHOOL OF ALEXANDRIA—POETS. 


tosthenes. The former was an epic poet’ of the same kind as 
Panyasis, whom he probably imitated in his Heracleia, a poem 
of mythological incidents in fourteen books. His Achaica in 
four books, his Eiiaca in three books at least, his Thessalica in 
sixteen books, and his Messeniaca in about six books, were 
historical romances in verse, and the latter especially kept so 
close to the facts that Pausanias appeals to it as an authority.’ 
Rhianus has left eleven epigrams of an erotic character which 
are extremely elegant and vivacious. He was also a commen- 
tator on Homer. Euphorion was born in 274 8.c., and, after 
spending the best part of his life at Athens, where he became 
very opulent, entered the service of Antiochus the Great as 
librarian, and died at Apamea in Syria, or, according to some 
writers, at Antioch. We have some twenty titles of works 
written by him,’ including mythological epics, satirical or con- 
troversial poems like the [dis of Callimachus,’ and elegiac poems 
of an amatory kind, which were imitated in Latin by Proper- 
tius and Tibullus, and in Greek by the Emperor Tiberius,* and 
at a later period by Nonnus, and were very popular at Rome 
in Cicero’s time.’ Like his countryman Lycophron, Euphorion 
was considered eminently obscure,* and encumbered by the 





1 Atheneus calls him ‘Piavds ὁ ἐποποίος (XI. p. 499 D). 

2 IV. 1, § 6, 6, ὃ 2, 15, ὃ 2, esp. 17, § 11: δηλοῖ καὶ τάδε ὑπὸ ‘Pravod πεποιη- 
μένα ἐς τοὺς Aaxedarpovlous— 

οὔρεος ἀργεννοῖο περὶ πτύχας ἐστρατόωντο 
χείματά τε ποίας τε δύω καὶ εἴκοσι πάσαΞε--- 
χειμῶνας γὰρ καὶ θέρη κατέλεξε, ποίας εἰπὼν τὸν χλωρὸν σῖτον καὶ ὀλίγον πρὸ ἀμητοῦ. 

3 Suidas, 5. v. 

4 There is a full account of Euphorion’s writings in Meineke, De Euphorionis 
Vité et Scriptis, Gedani, 1823. 

5 Of this class the most important were his dpal, ἢ ποτηριοκλέπτης, which sug- 
gested the Dire of Cato and Virgil, his χιλιάδες, which probably supplied the name 
of the well-known collection of John Tzetzes, and the ἀντιγραφαὶ πρὸς Oewpliav 
(or Θεοδωρίδαν), which is supposed to have been part of a grammatical controversy 
in verse. 

6 Suetonius says (Tiber. 70): ‘fecit et Greeca poemata imitatus et Euphorionem 
et Rhianum et Parthenium, quibus poetis admodum delectatus, scripta eorum et 
imagines publicis bibliothecis inter veteres et preecipuos auctores dedicavit.’ 

7 Cic. Tuse. Disp. III. το, § 45; of Ennius: “Ὁ poetam egregium, quamquam 
ab his cantoribus Euphorionis contemnitur.’ 

8 Id. De Divin. IT. 64, ὃ 132: ‘poeta nimis obscurus. At non Homerus. Uter 
igitur melior ὃ 


THE BUCOLIC POETS. 449 


excessive ventilation of his learning. In the epigram, which 
we have already quoted from Crates of Mallus,’ Euphorion is 
described as an imitator of Cheerilus, and, if the reading sug- 
gested is correct, of Philetas also. His prose works were chiefly 
on antiquarian and grammatical subjects. 

Nicander was a medical man and naturalist, and his poems 
have no value except as contributions to the history of these 
branches of science.? Besides a number of works in prose 
and verse, which are known to us only by their titles and 
some fragments, he wrote two poems which are still extant, 
one in 630 lines on the remedies for poisons (᾿Αλεξιφάρμακα), 
and one on the bites of venomous beasts (Θηριακά) in 958 lines. 

§ 7. Of all the writers of the Alexandrian school, the bucolic 
poets have enjoyed the most universal and permanent popu- 
larity. The first beginnings of pastoral poetry among the 
Greeks are to be sought in the primitive life of the shepherds 
and husbandmen, especially in those countries which fell under 
the dominion of the Dorian tribes; and it assumed a definite 
form in Laconia, where it was connected with the worship of 
the Doric Artemis, and in Sicily, where this goddess was 
honoured by special festivals at Tyndaris and Syracuse.® 
Epicharmus had mentioned the bucolic strains of the Sicilian 
shepherds,‘ and Stesichorus had given a lyric form to this 
species of poetry. But this was rather an application or 
accommodation of the thing than its genuine or natural con- 
dition. Bucolic poetry, as it exhibits itself in Greek literature, 
cannot be reduced strictly under any one of the three heads 
of epic, lyric, or dramatic poetry. It appeared originally as a 
set of alternating strains sung in rivalry by the shepherds, who 
were candidates for the rustic prize, and these amoebean poems 
(ἀμοιβαῖαι ἀοιδαί), as they were called, are not only reproduced 





1 Above, p. 425 [265]. 

2 Plutarch says of Nicander, Empedocles, and Parmenides, that the verse is but 
a vehicle for the prose of their thoughts (De audiendis Poetis, p. 61, Wytt.). 

3 See Miiller, Dorians, IV. 6, ὃ το. Bernhardy, Grundriss, II. p. 925. 

4 Athen. XIV., p. 619 B: Δίομος δ᾽ ἣν ὁ βούκολος Σικελιώτης ὁ πρῶτος εὑρὼν τὸ 
εἶδος" μνημονεύει δ᾽ αὐτοῦ Ἐπίχαρμος év‘ Αλκυόνι καὶ ἐν ᾿Οδυσσεῖ ναναγῷ. 

5 Mlian, V. Η. X. τ8. Stesichorus wrote a pastoral poem called Δάφνις ; Theo- 
critus, VII. 72 ; see above, ch. XIV. ὃ 6, p. 202. 

Vou. II. GG 


450 THE SCHOOL OF ALEXANDRIA—POETS. 


among the most polished compositions of this class, but were, 
till lately, extant in some parts of Southern Italy and Sicily.’ 
As we have it in the writers whom we are about to examine, 
the bucolic poem is generally epic in metre, Doric in dialect, 
dramatic in form, and elegiac or erotic in character. Thus it 
combined the characteristic refinements of the artificial poetry 
of Alexandria with subjects and a mode of treatment borrowed 
from the fresh green pastures and wooded mountains of Sicily ; 
and we can readily imagine what a charm this must have had 
for the courtiers and citizens of Alexandria, hemmed in as they 
were between two seas, and having no access to rural scenery. 
‘One can well conceive,’ says an able English writer,’ ‘ the 
delight which’ this bucolic poetry ‘must have given to those 
dusty Alexandrians, pent up for ever between sea and sandhills, 
drinking the tank-water, and never hearing the sound of a 
running stream, whirling, too, for ever in all the bustle and 
intrigue of a great commercial and literary city. Refreshing, 
indeed, it must have been to them to hear of those simple joys 
and simple sorrows of the Sicilian shepherd, in a land where 
toil was but exercise, and mere existence was enjoyment.’ To 
this we must add, that the bucolic poetry of the Alexandrians 
was dressed out in the court colours; and though the shep- 
herds and shepherdesses did not appear in the drawing-room 
attire of the ladies and gentlemen of Watteau’s pictures, their 
language and sentiments are those which breathe in the refined 
elegiacs of Philetas or Asclepiades, and in the love scenes of 
Apollonius; and the Doric is just broad enough to give a zest 
to the elegancies-of the metre and diction. These pastoral 
poems were called by a name significant of their pictorial and 
descriptive character—Idyls (εἴδη, εἰδύλλια)," i.e., little pictures 
of common life, a name for which the later writers have some- 
times substituted the term Eclogues (ἐκλογαῖ), i.e., “ selections,’ 
a name applicable to any short poem, whether complete and 





1 Swinburn’s Travels in Sicily, I. p. 480. Riedesel’s Reise nach Sicilien und 
Grossgriechenl., p. 175, quoted by Pauly, I. p. 1188. 

2 Kingsley, Alecandria and her Schools, p. 46. 

3 Ἐϊδύλλιον is a diminutive of εἶδος, which might signify a poem like the odes of 
Pindar: εἰδύλλιον λέγεται ὅτι εἶδός ἐστιν, ὁποῖόν ἐστι NOyos* ὑποκοριστικῶς δὲ εἴρηται 
εἰδύλλιον, Prolegom. in Theor. , 


THEOCRITUS. 451 


original, or appearing as an elegant extract... The Jdyl, or 
‘picture poem,’ is a refinement of the old mimes of Sophron, 
being both descriptive and dramatic, and appearing as a little 
drama in a framework of narrative. Now and then we have a 
bright burst of merry humour ;? here and there we listen to the 
melancholy strains of a dirge or a lover’s elegy;* but the general 
effect is warm and sunny, or fresh with the cool breezes which 
play at eventide among the rustling leaves. Such is the poetry 
which made Theocritus a favourite both with Hiero and 
Ptolemy ; which Virgil imitated in his choicest hexameters 
under Augustus; and which we still read with undiminished 
enjoyment. 

Tueocritus, who gives his name to the most important of 
the extant bucolic poems, is said by Suidas to have been the 
son of Praxagoras and Philinna of Syracuse,* and this is con- 
firmed by an epigram attributed to him, and by Moschus.’ 
According to another account, he was a native of Cos, and 
only a resident at Syracuse, and his father’s name was not 
Praxagoras, but Simichidas or Simichus. This statement has 
perhaps no better foundation than an inference from the 
apparent fact that Theocritus resided in Cos as a pupil of 
Philetas, and from the language of the seventh idyl, which is 
narrated in the person of one Simichidas of Cos. It is not at 
all improbable that Theocritus may have called himself by the 
pastoral name Simichus or Simichidas with reference to the 
σιμότης of the goat,® just as Virgil represents himself as a 





1 The term ἐκλογὴ is applied primarily to the short passage considered as an 
extract (Athen. XIV. p. 663 C: ἔχει δὴ ἡ σύμπασα ἐκλογὴ οὕτως) ; but it also 
denotes the shortness of the passage, whether prose or verse, without any reference 
to the idea of selection or borrowing ; see Suetonius, Vita Horat. p. 50, ed. F. A. 
Wolf. 

2 As in Theocritus, Jd. X. 38 sqq. 3 As in Theocritus, Jd. I. 64 sqq. 

4 Θεόκριτος, IIpataydpou καὶ Φιλίννης" of δὲ Σιμμίχου, Συρακούσιος" οἱ δέ φασι 
ἘΚ ῴον, μετῴκησε δὲ ἐν Συρακούσαις. 

5 Epigr. 22: 

ἄλλος ὁ Χῖος" ἐγὼ δὲ Θεόκριτος ὃς τάδ᾽ ἔγραψα 
εἷς ἀπὸ τῶν πολλῶν εἰμὶ Συρηκόσιος, 
υἱὸς Πραξαγόραο περικλειτῆς τε Φιλίννης" 
μοῦσαν δ᾽ ὀθνείην οὔποτ᾽ ἐφελκυσάμην. 
So also Moschus, Epitaph. Bionis, 106: ἐν δὲ Συρακοσίοισι Θεόκριτος. 
6 Cf. Theocr. ITT. 8, VIII. 50; Plato, Theetet. p. 133, E;, Sympos. 216, C, Ὁ. 
GG 2 


452 THE SCHOOL OF ALEXANDRIA—POETS. 


Tityrus, which was the Laconian and Sicilian name for the 
leading goat or ram of the flock.’ The general impression left 
upon the reader of his poems is that Theocritus was a native 
Dorian from Syracuse, and this is especially apparent in pas- 
sages like that in the Adoniazuse, where he speaks somewhat 
proudly in the person of a Syracusan woman.’ The dates of 
his birth and death are unknown. It is stated in the argument 
to his fourth idyl that he flourished in Ol. 124, B.c. 284—281 # 
his fourteenth, fifteenth, and seventeenth idyls were manifestly 
written at Alexandria in the reign of Ptolemy Philadelphus, 
and he is referred to the same period by his relations with 
Philetas and Aratus ; while the sixteenth idyl, which is an en- 
comium on Hiero the son of Hierocles, was probably written 
about the time when that personage was raised to the throne, 
i.e, in B.c. 270.4. As in this poem he speaks of being in 
search of a patron,’ it may be inferred that he returned from 
Alexandria shortly before this time, and spent the remainder of 
his life in his native island. 

Our imperfect and uncertain information respecting the 
biography of Theocritus is supplemented by considerable doubts 
as to the authorship of the thirty poems which bear his name. 
An epigram attributed to Theocritus would lead us to con- 
clude that he had himself made a collection of his writings.’ 
Another, which bears the name of Artemidorus, a pupil of 
Aristophanes of Byzantium, speaks of a general collection of 
the bucolic poets.’ To prove that the thirty poems ascribed to 
Theocritus were not all written by him, appeal is made to great 
differences of style and character, and these are most. conspicuous 
in the compositions which stand at the end. Then it is known 





1 Miiller, Dor. TV. 6, ὃ το, note e, That the name Simichidas was a general 
designation of a shepherd is shown by the line in the Syrinw 13: πᾶμα Πάρις θέτο 
Σιμιχίδας. 
᾿Ξ XV. ρο-9ο5. Wedo not of course overlook the comic force of the passage. 

3 Θεόκριτος δὲ, ὥσπερ ἐδείξαμεν κατὰ τὴν κδ' (read ρκδ΄) ᾿Ολυμπιάδα ἤκμαζεν. 

4 Wiistemann, Theocritus, p. 244. 5 XVI. 5; 13 al. 

8 Above, p. 451 [291], note 5. 

7 Anthol. Pal. IX. 208: ᾿Αρτεμιδώρου τοῦ γραμματικοῦ ἐπὶ τῇ ἀθροίσει τῶν 
βουκολικῶν ποιημάτων :— 

βουκολικαὶ Μοῖσαι σποράδες ποκα, νῦν δ᾽ ἅμα πᾶσαι 
ἐντὶ μιᾶς μάνδρας, ἐντὶ μιᾶς ἀγέλας. 


THEOCRITUS. 453 © 


that many Alexandrian grammarians wrote commentaries on 
Theocritus,’ which form the basis of our extant scholia. But these 
scholia do not extend beyond the eighteenth idyl. From these 
and similar considerations we should infer that a number of mis- 
cellaneous poems have been bound up at the end of a collection 
containing some of the genuine works of ‘Theocritus. On the 
other hand, it is clear that he wrote many poems which do not 
appear atall in our collection. Athenzeus has preserved a frag- 
ment of his Berenice,’ and Suidas says that he wrote Προιτίδες, 
᾿Ελπίδες, Ὕμνοι, Ἡρωΐναι,᾿Ἐπικήδεια μέλη, ᾿Ελεγεῖα, Ἴαμβοι, 
of which only the Ὕμνοι can be identified with the poems 
which we still have. From all this it would appear that the 
Theocritean poems correspond in a smaller degree to .the 
Hippocratic collection, and contain portions of the various 
writings which were accepted at Alexandria as belonging to the 
same class with the works of Theocritus. 

The collection, however, is as miscellaneous in its subjects 
and character as it is in authorship. Only the first eleven 
poems, and the twenty-seventh, are in any Sense bucolic poems 
of the Sicilian stamp, and of these the second, called Dappa- 
κευτρία, or ‘the Sorceress, is not so much ἃ pastoral 
poem as a scene from common life, borrowed, we are told, 
from one of Sophron’s mimes.’ The fourteenth, fifteenth, and 
twenty-first are three dramatic scenes of the same kind; the 
second being laid in the city of Alexandria, and the last being 
a dialogue between two fishermen. The twelfth, nineteenth, 
twentieth, twenty-third, and twenty-ninth, are erotic poems, 
of which the twentieth approaches nearest to the bucolic 
strain. The thirteenth and the eighteenth are derived from 
epic subjects. The sixteenth and seventeenth, though in 
hexameter verse, belong to the same class as the encomia of 





1 For example, Theon, Amarantus, Asclepiades of Myrlea, Munatus, Neo- 
ptolemus, Nicanor of Cos, and Amerias. 

2 Atheneus, VII. p. 283 A. This Berenice was the mother of Philadelphus, 
not the wife of Euergetes, whose hair is honoured by Callimachus. 

3 Hypoth. Gr.: τὴν δὲ Θεστύλιδα ὁ Θεόκριτος ἀπειροκάλως ἐκ τῶν Sibpovos 
μετήνεγκε Μίμων. 

4 The Scholiast tells us that the eighteenth idyl, or the hymenzal song of 
Menelaus and Helen, was an imitation in many places of a poem by Stesichorus 
on the same subject. 


454 THE SCHOOL OF ALEXANDRIA—POETS. 


the old lyric poetry. The twenty-second, twenty-fourth, twenty- 
fifth, and twenty-sixth, are fragments of epic poems of the 
Alexandrian school. The twenty-eighth is an occasional poem 
on an ivory distaff which the poet was about to take with him 
as a present to Theagenis, the wife of his friend Nicias, a phy- 
sician of Miletus, to whom the eleventh and thirteenth idyls are 
inscribed. The thirtieth is an anacreontic poem on Adonis. 
This classification will show how much diversity there is im the 
Theocritean collection. We proceed to examine the separate 
poems in detail, with a view to a proper estimate of their 
authenticity. 

The first criterion is the dialect, the second the subject. If 
we rightly imterpret the profession of Theocritus himself, he 
wrote only in the Doric dialect, and only on subjects which 
admitted a legitimate application of the Doric hexameter.' 

Both of these considerations will exclude the twelfth idyl, called 
᾿Αἵτης, or ‘ the beloved youth,’ which has nothing in common 
with the bucolic style, and is written in the Ionic dialect. It 
is more likely to have been composed by Theocritus, the sophist 
of Chios, than by his namesake of Syracuse. The second 
criterion, or that of subject, affects most strongly the assumed 
authenticity of the epic or quasi-epic fragments (twenty-second, 
twenty-fourth, twenty-fifth, twenty-sixth), two of which (the 
twenty-fourth and twenty-fifth) have been attributed by some 
writers to Peisander’ or Panyasis.* Ina lesser degree this objec- 
tion applies to the half epic fragments (the thirteenth and 
eighteenth). The peculiar relations of the poet might explain 
the deviations from the usual topics and mode of writing in 
such poems as the addresses to Hiero and Ptolemy (the six- 
teenth and seventeenth), and the envoy of the distaff (twenty- 
eighth). The subject will overbalance the mode of treatment in 
the twentieth idyl, called Βουκολισκὸς or ‘the young herds- — 
man ; but the other erotic poems, the nineteenth, twenty-third, 
and twenty-ninth, are not at all in the style of Theocritus. The 





In Epigr. 22,1. 4: 
μοῦσαν δ᾽ ὀθνείην οὔποτ᾽ ἐφελκυσάμην, 


where ὀθνεῖος must mean strange or foreign in reference to Theocritus, as ἃ Dorian 
of Sicily, and a bucolic poet κατ᾽ ἐξοχήν. 
* This was Reiske’s opinion. 3 See Ἐς, Schlegel, Vorles. vol. I. p. 201. 


THEOCRITUS. 455 


Sophronic mimes, the second, fourteenth, fifteenth, and twenty- 
first, must be retained on account of their style and mode of 
treatment, although, as we have said, they are not strictly 
bucolic. It has been conjectured’ that the first part of the 
eighth idyl is an unskilful addition by some later hand, and 
that this and the ninth idyl, which have the same interlocutors, 
should be melted down into one poem. 

Supposing then, according to this discrimination, that we 
recognize as genuine works of Theocritus all those poems which 
are written in the new Sicilian Doric, and which are either 
bucolic, mimic, or demonstrably related to the special circum- 
stances of the poet’s life, we shall be able out of these 
materials to form an adequate estimate of his _ peculiar 
talents: and we shall say that Theocritus has had few equals 
in his power of appreciating and describing scenery, and in 
the happy faculty of portraying characters by a few distinc- 
tive touches. The former quality of his poems is of course 
most seen in those which are strictly bucolic; the latter is 
most conspicuous. in those which belong to the same class as 
the Sophronic mimes. Picturesque descriptions are found in 
all the idyls of the first class. For example, nothing can be 
prettier than the opening lines of the whole collection, where 
even the cadence of the metre imitates the sweet whispering of 
the pine tree which murmurs beside the fountain.? Again, we 
have a rustic prettiness in the serenade of the third idyl, where 
the amorous shepherd wishes he was a humming bee, and 
could come into the grot of his Amaryllis, penetrating through 
the ivy and fern which mantled around 10. Similarly in the 
fifth, we have a charming picture of the oaks and the cyperus, ~ 
the swarms of bees in one continued humming, the two cool 
fountains, the birds chirping on the boughs, the unrivalled 





1 By Reinhold (De genwinis Theocriti carminibus et suppositiciis, Jens, 1819). 
5. J. init. : 

ἁδύ τι τὸ ψιθύρισμα καὶ & πίτυς, αἰπόλε, τήνα, 

ἃ ποτὶ ταῖς παγαῖσι μελίσδεται, 
eat, 14: 

αἴθε γενοίμαν 
ἁ βομβεῦσα μέλισσα καὶ ἐς τεὸν ἄντρον ἱκοίμαν, 
τὸν κισσὸν διαδὺς καὶ τὰν πτέριν ἃ τὺ πυκάσδῃ. 


456 THE SCHOOL OF ALEXANDRIA—POETS. 


shade, and the fir-cones falling from on high.’ But the most 
complete of all these landscapes is furnished by the seventh 
idyl, of which the scene is laid in Cos. The poet, who here 
calls himself Simichidas, is going with two friends, Eucritus 
and Amyntas, to keep the feast of Ceres by the river Halens 
with Phrasidamus and Antigenes, the sons of Lycopes.”7 When 
about half-way, they are overtaken by a Cretan shepherd, 
Lycidas, whose attire is minutely described.* ‘ Whither,’ he 
says, ‘are you dragging your feet at midday, when the lizard is 
sleeping on the dyke, nor are the crested larks on the wing? 
Are you invited to some feast or vintage? As you march 
along every stone rings against your thick-soled boots”* The 
poet greets his friend with compliments, and invites him to 
join in bucolic strains. Whereupon Lycidas bursts forth imto 
a pastoral song in praise of his favourite Ageanax, who has 
sailed for Mitylene.’ Simichidas in return describes the love 
of Aratus for young Philinus.® Here Lycidas leaves the 
party, having first presented Simichidas with his shepherd’s 
crook, as an acknowledgment of his poetic skill.? The three 
friends arrive at the country place of Phrasidamus, and take 
their seats on prepared heaps of sweet lentisk, with black 
poplars and elms nodding over their heads, and the sacred water 
running close by them in a bubbling brook from a grotto of 
the nymphs ; the sun-burnt cicadas are chirping on the branches, 
farther off the woodlark murmurs in the acacia, larks and 
linnets are singing, the turtle dove is cooing, the bees are 





1 V. 45 sqq.: 
τουτεὶ δρύες, ὧδε κύπειρος, 
ὧδε καλὸν βομβεῦντι ποτὶ σμανεσσι médica, 
ἔνθ᾽ ὕδατος ψυχρῶ κρᾶναι δύο" ταὶ δ᾽ ἐπὶ δένδρων 
ὄρνιχες λαλαγεῦντι" καὶ ἁ σκιὰ οὐδὲν ὁμοία 
τᾷ παρὰ τίν" βάλλει δὲ καὶ ἁ πίτυς ὕψοθε κώνους. 
3 VII. 1—4. 3 V. 10 sqq. 
Ibid, vv. 21 sqq.: 
Σιμιχίδα πᾷ δὴ τὺ μεσαμέριον πόδα ἕλκεις, 
ἁνίκα δὴ καὶ σαῦρος ἐφ᾽ αἱμασίαισι καθεύδει, 
οὐδ᾽ ἐπιτυμβίδιοι κορυδαλλίδες ἠλαίνοντι ; 
ἢ μετὰ δαῖτα κλητὸς ἐπείγεαι; ἤ τινος ἀστῶν 
λιχνὸν ἐπιθρώσκεις ; ὡς τεῦ ποσὶ νεισσομένοιο 
πᾶσα λίθος πταίοισα ποτ᾽ ἀρβυλίδεσσιν ἀείδει. 


5 Ibid. Vv. 52 sqq. 6 Ibid. 96 sqq. 7 Ibid. vv. 128 sqq. 


THEOCRITUS. 457 


fluttering about the streamlets—everywhere there is the smell 
of fruitful autumn ;' pears, aud apples, and plums are strewed 
around them in the greatest profusion, and the cask of four- 
year-old wine is broached for the occasion. It is one of those 
cheerful scenes which we find in Walton’s Angler, only that we 
have the more gorgeous colours of a landscape in the 
/Egean. 

The mimetic or dramatic power of Theocritus is most con- 
spicuous in the fourteenth, fifteenth, and twenty-first idyls. 
In the first of these, Aischines, a country farmer, accounts 
for his neglected person and dress by detailing to his friend 
Thyonichus how his jealous temper had led him to strike his 
mistress Cynisca at a drinking-bout, in consequence of which 
she had forsaken him; and he is recommended to take service 
under Ptolemy, whose character is drawn in very flattering 
colours,* and the farmer become soldier is painted most accu- 
rately with a few strokes of the pen. The well-buckled cloak, 
the lengthened stride, and the firmness of the disciplined 
phalangite are all brought before our eyes in a line or two.’ 
The fifteenth idyl takes advantage of a sumptuous feast, in- 
stituted by Arsinoe in honour of Adonis, to praise Ptolemy and 
his whole family. The machinery is very ingeniously con- 
trived. Two Syracusan women of the lower order, Praxinoe 
and Gorgo, who have migrated to Alexandria with their 
husbands, are introduced just as they are starting in their 
smartest dresses to see the spectacle. The whole of the intro- 
duction is a little comedy. The crowd is described with all the 
exaggerations of female terror.’ The amiable women abuse their 
husbands,° deceive their children,’ and scold the maid-servant.° 





a V6 43): 

πάντ᾽ ὦσδεν θέρεος μάλα πίονος, ὦσδε δ᾽ drwpns. 
2 Ibid. v. 147: 
τετράενες δὲ πίθων ἀπελύετο κρατὸς ἄλειφαρ. 

3 XIV. 58—62. : 
4 Ibid. 63—65 : 
el τοι κατὰ δεξιὸν ὦμον ἀρέσκει 

λῶπος ἄκρον περονᾶσθαι, ἐπ᾽ ἀμφοτέροις δὲ βεβακὼς 
τολμασεῖς ἐπιόντα μένειν θρασὺν ἀσπιδιώταν, 
ἃ τάχος εἰς Αὔγυπτον. 
5 XV. 4-7. 8 vv. 9-20. 7 vv. 14, 40. 8 vv. 27, 31. 


458 THE SCHOOL OF ALEXANDRIA—POETS. 


Praxinoe’s gown is admired and priced.’ They are frightened 
out of their wits by the king’s led horses.2 An old woman 
gives them oracular encouragement as they are forcing their 
way into the palace.’ They are separated from their waiting- 
maids and get their dresses torn. One person in the crowd 
protects them and is praised ;* another rebukes their incessant 
gabbling,® and is proudly told that they are Syracusans, origi- 
nally from Corinth, ‘ the country of Bellerophon, if you please, 
sir,’ and that they exercise their undoubted privilege of talking 
the pure Doric of the Peloponnese.’ The piece terminates 
with a song in honour of Adonis by the prima Donna of Alex- 
andria, and Gorgo returns home to face an angry husband, 
who has not yet had his breakfast, and is not very approachable 
under such circumstances. The twenty-first idyl, addressed to 
Diophantus, begins with a minute description of a poor fisher- 
man’s establishment on the seashore, and then introduces us 
to Asphalion the angler,’ who beguiles a sleepless night by 
relating to his partner how he had dreamt one afternoon that 
he had caught a golden fish, and had sworn never to go fishing 
again. He is prudently reminded that his oath is as unsub- 
stantial as his dream, which will find its best accomplish- 
ment if he plies his rod and line without dozing. ‘ Seek,’ 
says his friend, ‘ the fish of flesh, lest you die of hunger, 
with all your golden dreams.’ It seems that this idyl is com- 
posed in direct imitation of Sophron, who wrote two mimes 
about fishermen, the ᾿Αλιεὺς and the Θυννοθήρας. This 





1 vv. 34 sqq. 2 vv. 51-56. 3 vv. 60-63. 
4 vv. 69-76. 5 vv. 74, 75- 6 vy. 87, 88, 
7 Vv. 90-93: 


Συρακοσίαις ἐπιτάσσεις ; 
ὡς εἰδῇς καὶ τοῦτο, Κοορίνθιαί εἰμες ἄνωθεν, 
ὡς καὶ ὁ Βελλεροφῶν. Πελοποννασιστὶ λαλεῦμες" 
Δωρίσδειν δ᾽ ἔξεστι δοκῶ τοῖς Δωριέεσσι. 

8 vv. 147, 148. 

9 The man is represented as fishing with a rod (KXI. 43, 47), and his name 
᾿Ασφαλίων points to the word ἀσπαλιευτής, about which we hear so much in the 
Sophistes of Plato (pp. 218 E, sqq.). 

10 vy. 65-67: 

εἰ δ᾽ ὕπαρ ob κνώσσων τὺ τὰ χώρια ταῦτα ματεύσεις 
ἐλπὶς τῶν ὕπνων" ζάτει τὸν σάρκινον ἰχθύν, 
μὴ σὺ θάνῃς λιμῷ καίτοι χρυσοῖσιν ὀνείροις. 


THEOCRITUS. | 459 


poem is unusually corrupt in the copies which have come 
down to us. 

Besides these longer compositions, twenty-two epigrams bear 
the name of Theocritus, and he is made the author of a fantastic 
little poem called the Syrinxz, in which twenty verses are so 
arranged that complete and catalectic lines succeed one another 
_ in couplets, passing from the hexameter down to the dimeter 
dactylic metre, so as to represent the successive lengths of the 
reeds in a Pandean pipe. This jew d’esprit is attributed with 
more justice to Simmias of Rhodes, who composed similar 
copies of verses in the shape of an egg, an altar, and a double- 
edged axe or pair of wings. It is not improbable that Theo- 
critus wrote most of the epigrams. But, on the one hand, the 
tenth epigram of Erycius is attributed by a manuscript to 
Theocritus; and, on the other hand, the seventeenth and 
tenth epigrams of Theocritus are assigned to Leonidas of 
Tarentum by the modern editor of the Anthology. 

There can be no doubt that Theocritus had an original 
genius for poetry of the highest kind. The absence of the 
usual affectation of the Alexandrian school, the constant appeal 
to nature, the perception of character, the power of description, 
the keen sense both of the beautiful and of the ludicrous, con- 
tribute to indicate the highest order of literary talent, and 
account for the universal and undiminished popularity of an 
author whose era was not that of original men. His conspicuous 
superiority to Virgil, who directly imitates him, shows that the 
greatest skill as a writer of verses would not have enabled him 
to produce these effects, if he had been merely a second-hand 
writer of idyls. At the same time, it is quite clear that he had 
many models to guide him or suggest his subjects to him. 
Philetas, Aratus, and Asclepiades, were his immediate teachers. 
Sophron and the older writers of his own country were con- 
stantly before him ; and there are evidences of a careful study 
of the great Attic poets, especially Sophocles.’ But with all 





1 For example, the following coincidences in one chorus of the Antigone can 
hardly be fortuitous: 
Soph. Antig. 585: 
κυλίνδει 
βυσσόθεν κελαινὰν 
θῖνα καὶ δυσάνεμον. 


460 THE SCHOOL OF ALEXANDRIA—PORTS. 


this, his position may have been as independent as that of our own 
Shakspere, who had the stories of his plays ready to his hand 
in Italian novels, English annals, and translations of Plutarch, 
but made everything new as it passed through the alembic of 
an imagination, with which, it must be owned, Theocritus had 
much in common. 

The two other bucolic poets of the Alexandrian school were 
Bion of Phlossa near Smyrna, and his pupil Moscuus of 
Syracuse. <A sort of elegy by the latter poet, which is extant 
as his third idyl (Eztragioc Biwvoc), is our chief authority for 
all that we know about Bion’s personal history. It appears 
that he migrated from Asia Minor to Sicily, the home of 
bucolic poetry, where he was poisoned, and where just punish- 
ment overtook his murderers.' The appeal to the Bistonian 
nymphs to bewail the Dorian Orpheus’ does not at all prove 
that Bion had visited Macedonia. The passage, from which it 
was concluded that he was a contemporary of Philetas, Ascle- 
piades, Lycidas, and Theocritus, is justly considered as an 
interpolation borrowed from the seventh idyl of the last-named 
of these poets.’ As, however, Bion was the friend and, as it 
seems, the teacher of Moschus, who was an acquaintance of 
Aristarchus,‘ and therefore flourished about the middle of the 
second century B.c., and as he died prematurely, he must have 
lived in the generation immediately succeeding Theocritus, and 
was therefore a contemporary of Apollonius and Eratosthenes. 
The poems of Bion, which used to be mixed up with those of 
Theocritus, consist of a lament of Adonis, with a continual 





Theocr. VII. 58: 
edpov bs ἔσχατα φυκία κινεῖ, 
Soph. Antig. 600: 
οὔτ᾽ ἀκάματοι θεῶν (1, θέοντες] μῆνες. 
Theocr. XVI. 71: 
οὔπω μῆνας ἄγων ἔκαμ᾽ οὐρανὸς οὔτ᾽ ἐνιαυτούς. 

1 Epitaph. Bionis, 136: 

φάρμακον ἦλθε, Βίων, ποτὶ σὸν στόμα, φάρμακον, εἶδες. 
Ibid. 136: 

ἀλλὰ Δίκα κίχε πάντας. 
2 Ibid. 16, 17, 
εἴπατε πάσαις 

Βιστονίαις νύμφαισιν, ἀπώλετο Δώριος ᾿Ορφεύς. 
3 See Hermann, Bionis et Moschi Carmina, Lipsiz, 1849, pp. 77, 78. 
4 Suidas s.v.: Μόσχος, Συρακούσιος, γραμματικός, ᾿Αριστάρχου γνώριμος. 


BION, MOSCHUS. ~ 461 


refrain,’ not unlike that in the first idyl of Theocritus, or the 
elegy on himself by Moschus; and eighteen other fragmentary 
idyls, including the Κηριοκλέπτης, which occupies also the 
nineteenth place among the idyls of Theocritus, but which 
Hermann has added to the poems of Bion in accordance with 
the suggestion of Valckenaer.? Bion writes harmonious verses 
with a good deal of pathos and tenderness ; but he is as inferior 
to Theocritus as he is superior to Moschus. From the latter 
we have the following poems: (1) ‘Runaway Love’ (ἔρως 
δραπέτης), a little piece in twenty-nine lines, also included in 
the Anthologia, and written in the style of the later Anacreontics ; 
(2) ‘Europa,’ in τόρ lines; (3) ‘The Elegy on Bion’ already 
mentioned; (4) ‘ Megara the wife of Hercules, in 127 lines; 
to which are added three short fragments from Stobzeus, and 
an epigram from the Anthology of Planudes; and Hermann 
has also appended to his edition of Moschus ‘ the Conversation’ 
(Oagisric) between Daphnis and the Nymph, which appears 
as the twenty-seventh idyl of Theocritus.* Of these remains 
of Moschus, the two poems on Europa and Megara are not 
bucolic, but fragments of epic poems of the Alexandrian class, 
and they are written in the Ionic dialect. The style of Moschus 
is very artificial, with occasionally very unusual transpositions 
or inversions of the natural order ;* and in his imitations it may 
be sometimes doubted whether he understood the figures which 
he borrowed.* Altogether, he is rather the learned versifier 





1 αἰαῖ τὰν Κυθέρειαν, ἀπώλετο καλὸς "Α δωνις ; so also in the Epitaphius Bionis: 
ἄρχετε Σικελικαὶ τῷ πένθεος, ἄρχετε Μοῖσαι, and in Theocritus I. 64, &e.: ἄρχετε 
βωκολικᾶς, Μῶσαι φίλαι, ἄρχετ᾽ ἀοιδᾶς. 

3 Hermann, p. 63. ’ 

3 Jacobs says: ‘sunt qui Moschum auctorem existiment. Que opinio ut minime 
absurda est, ita certis firmisque argumentis destituitur.’ There is a pretty general 
agreement among critics that, whether Moschus was the author or not, this poem 
cannot be justly ascribed to Theocritus. 

* For example, IV. το, 20: 

οὐ δέ σφιν δυνάμην ἀδινὸν καλέουσιν ἀρῆξαι 
μητέρ ἕήν, 
for καλέουσιν μητέρ᾽ ἑήν: and similarly in vv. 83, 93. 
> In IV. 58: 
τὰ δέ of θαλερώτερα δάκρυα μήλων 
κόλπον ἐς ἱμεροέντα κατὰ βλεφάρων ἐχέοντο--- 
Moschus seems to have imitated the strong metaphor in Theocritus XIV. 38: 
τήνῳ τὰ σὰ δάκρυα μᾶλα ῥέοντι, without exactly understanding it. 


462 THE SCHOOL OF ALEXANDRIA—POETS. 


than the true poet, and more exactly represents his friend 
Aristarchus than his predecessor Theocritus. 

§ 8. We must not conclude this account of the Alexandrian 
poetry. without a few remarks on an inferior species of it, 
belonging, like the bucolic poems which we have just discussed, 
to the old carnival sports and rude burlesques of the Dorian 
rustics.. These efforts of the merry-andrew class were called 
sometimes ἱλαροτραγῳδίαι or ‘tragi-comedies,’ sometimes 
παρῳδίαι or ‘ travesties, and sometimes φλύακες τραγικοὶ OF 
‘tragic fooleries,’ whence the class of writers is termed the 
Phlyacographers (φλυακογράφοι). The founder of this style of 
writing was Ruintruon of Tarentum, called also a Syracusan, 
who flourished in the reign of the first Ptolemy, and who gave 
the earliest literary expression to the old farces of the Dorians. 
The merit is claimed for him in an epigram of Nossis in rather 
humble terms,’ and he does not appear to have set much value 
on his own performances.’ It is pretty clear, from the subjects 
of the plays attributed to him, that he particularly delighted 
in travesties of Euripides. He was succeeded in his own par- 
ticular style by Soparer, Scrras, and a Campanian named 
Buizasus, and was well known to the Romans, insomuch that 
Lucilius made him a model for imitation.* Parodies on Homer 
had been made at an earlier date, and we have a long fragment 
from a poem of this kind by Marron of Pitana,’ who was at 
the latest a contemporary of Alexander the Great. As Rhin- 





1 Miller, Dor. TV. 7, ὃ 7. 
2 Anthol. Pal. VII. 414: 
καὶ καπυρὸν γελάσας παραμείβεο καὶ φίλον εἰπὼν 
ῥῆμ᾽ ἐπ’ ἐμοί. “Ρίνθων δ᾽ εἶμ᾽ ὁ Συρακόσιος, 
Μουσάων ὀλίγη τις ἀηδονίς᾽ ἀλλὰ φλυάκων : 
ἐκ τραγικῶν ἴδιον κισσὸν ἐδρεψάμεθα. 

3 He seems to have expressed his disregard of metre even in the middle of his 
poems. Thus Hephestion says (p. 9, Gaisford): Ῥίνθων μὲν yap καὶ ἐν ἰάμβῳ 
ἐπισημασίας ἠξίωσε τὸ τοιοῦτον, ἐν yap ’Opéoryn δράματι φησίν" 

ὡς σὲ Διόνυσος αὐτὸς ἐξώλη θείη 

τὸ μέτρον Ἵππώνακτος" οὐδέν μοι μέλει, 
where he seems to have been writing iambic trimeters, and to have allowed a choli- 
ambic to slip in inadvertently. The common reading is εἴθ᾽ ‘Imm. τὸ μ., where εἴθ᾽ 
is probably a gloss on the ws in the line above. 

4 Lydus I. 41. 

5 Athen. IV. pp. 134-137: He is called Matreas in Athen. I. p. 5 A. 


SILLI AND CINADI. 463 


thon and Matron burlesqued the tragedians and Homer, so 
Timon of Phlius, a contemporary of Philadelphus, in his three 
books of SiAXor or ‘ mockeries,’’ satirized and ridiculed all the 
schools of philosophy, except that of the Sceptics to which he 
belonged. This work was in hexameter verse, and the second 
and third books were in the form of a dialogue between himself 
and Xenophon of Colophon.* From the specimens it seems to 
have been a poem of considerable merit, and was made the 
subject of special commentaries by Apollonides of Nicza, 
Antigonus Carystius, and Sotion of Alexandria. 

With these Σίλλοι of Timon, Diogenes of Laérte imme- 
diately connects Κίναιδοι or ‘obscene poems,’ as having been 
written by this satirist of the philosophers,’ and the same 
* degraded class of writings is connected with the Φλύακες, in an 
article by Suidas* respecting Sorapes and ALEXANDER the AXto- 
lian, who were the authors of this lascivious versification. The 
other writers mentioned by Suidas are Pyrruus the Milesian, 
Tueoporvs, or THEoporipAs, TrmocHaripas, and XENARCHUS. 
Alexander the Aitolian, as we have already seen, was a respec- 
table grammarian and poet of the Museum at Alexandria, and 
not only undertook the editorship of the tragic writers, but 
obtained a place in the Pleiad by his own tragedies; and it 
must be hoped, that his contributions to the class of writings 





1 There is a difficulty about the etymology of this word. Some compare it with 
oss, and it must be remarked that σιμῳδὸς, from the name of the Magnesian poet 
Simus, was a synonym for ἱλαρῳδός, Athen. p. 620, Ὁ. lian (V. H. III. το) 
connects it with Σειληνός, and adds: τὸν δὲ σιλλὸν ψόγον λέγουσι μετὰ παιδιᾶς δυσ- 
ἀρέστου. Others derive it from ἰλλός (see Schoell, Hist. dela Litt. Gr. III. p. 179). 
Something may be said for each of these derivations. With regard to the last opinion, 
as Apollonius of Rhodes was the son of Sil/ews or Ileus, we may easily account for 
the moveable s ; and as ἰλλίζω (-- διανεύω, Suidas) and ἐπιλλίζω occur, especially 
in writers like Apollonius, in the sense of καταμωκᾶσθαι (cf. Argonaut. I. 486, and 
especially IIT. 791, where ἐπιλλίζουσιν is followed by μωμήσονται), it does not seem 
at all unlikely that σίλλος and its verb σιλλαίνω (= διασύρειν or μωκᾶσθαι, Hesych.) 
really involve the same root. This at least is quite in accordance with the descrip- 
tion given of Timon’s book, Diog. Laért. IX. 111: ἐν οἷς (cidXos), ws ἂν σκε- 
πτικὸς ὦν, πάντας λοιδορεῖ καὶ σιλλαίνει τοὺς δογματικοὺς ἐν παρῳδίας εἴδει. 

5 Diog. Laért. IX. 111. The first book was αὐτοδιήγητος, or μονοπρόσωπος, 
and began: ἔσπετε viv μοι ὅσοι πολυπράγμονες ἐστὲ σοφισταί. 

3 Tbid. ττο: καὶ γὰρ ποιήματα συνέγραψε καὶ ἔπη, καὶ τραγῳδίας καὶ σατύρους 
καὶ δράματα κωμικὰ τριάκοντα, τραγικὰ δὲ ἑξήκοντα, σίλλους τε καὶ κιναίδους. 

4 s.v. Σωτάδης ; cf. Athen. XIV. p. 620, from whom Suidas gets this infor- 
mation, and Strabo, XIV. p. 648. 


464 THE SCHOOL OF ALEXANDRIA—POETS. 


under consideration approximated rather to the Φλύακες of 
Rhinthon than to the Κίναιδοι of Sotades. This latter, who 
was a Cretan from Maronea, carried the extravagances of his 
indecency so far that Suidas called him ‘ possessed of an evil 
spirit’? (δαιμονισθείς); and he has the main discredit of the 
cineedological poetry, which is called after him the Σωτάδεια 
ἄσματα. The subjects of his poems are chiefly mythical,’ and 
they were probably travesties like those of Rhinthon, only com- 
bined with unrestrained obscenity, and applied to purposes of 
personal satire and defamation. He had the audacity to attack 
both Lysimachus and Ptolemy Philadelphus; and having pro- 
voked the anger of the latter by a gross allusion to his marriage - 
with his sister Arsinoe, he was obliged to abscond from Alexan- 
dria, after having sustained a grievous imprisonment there, and 
being overtaken at Caunus by Patroclus, one of Ptolemy’s 
generals, was inclosed in a leaden case and flung into the sea.’ 
He wrote both in the Ionic dialect and in the so-called Ionic 
amajore metre, which bore the same relation to the choriambic 
that the Ionic a minore did to the anapestic.? The general 
tone, in spite of the indecency, was borrowed from the common- 
places of morality, and Sotades had many imitators, including 
the Roman poets Ennius and Accius; but his name became a 
by-word of reproach, and in the same way as the intolerant 
churchmen of the middle ages combined an imputation of un- 
natural lust with the charge of heresy so frequently alleged, 
the opponents of Arius thought themselves bound to accuse 





1 The titles given are "Ἄδωνις, ᾿Αμάζων, els “Avdov κατάβασις, els Βελεστίχην, 
*INas, Πρίηπος. 

2 Athen. XIV. pp. 620 F—621 B, 

3 The Jonic a majore was really a dactyl with an anacrusis, and the rhythm of 
the tetrameter brachycatalectic line used by Sotades was generally choriambic : for 


might be divided as: 


ee ee i .... [ἢ] ... ee (ee ὦ’ 
~— — 





---- —_—-— ~— a ὠς — 


which is quite in the choriambic cadence. The following are specimens (Stob. 
Flor. XCVI1,) : 

αὐτὸς γὰρ ἐὼν mavroyévns ὁ πάντα γεννῶν 

οὐ κρινεῖ δικαίως τὰ κατ᾽ ἄνθρωπον ἕκαστον. 


SOTADES. 465 


him of imitating the style of the Sotadean poems.’ The life 
of Sotades was written, and his works commented on, by his 
son Apollonius, and by Carystius of Pergamus. 





1 Select Treatises of Athanasius, translated by J. H. Newman, Oxford, 1842: 
Ῥ. 94: ‘he drew up his heresy on paper, and imitating, as if in festivity (ws ἐν θαλίᾳ), 
no graye writer, but the Egyptian Sotades, in the dissolute tone of his metre, &c.’ ; 
and p. 179: ‘and for Moses and the other saints, they have made the discovery of 
one Sotades, a man whom even Gentiles laugh at.’ See Newman’s note on the 
former passage. 


Vou. II. H H 


466 


CHAPTER XLVI. 


PROSE WRITERS OF ALEXANDRIA. 


§ 1. Classification of the prose writers of Alexandria: Demetrius the Phalerian. 
§ 2. (a) Grammarians and critics: Zenodotus of Ephesus, Aristophanes of By- 
zantium, and Aristarchus of Samothrace. § 3. The recension of Homer. ὃ 4. 
(b) Historians and chronologists. § 5. Translations of Egyptian, Chaldean, and 
Hebrew annals. § 6. (c) Pure and applied mathematics: Euclid, Archimedes, 
Apollonius of Perga, Eratosthenes, and Hipparchus. 


§ 1, ὁ ets multifarious studies and avocations of the book- 

learned men of Alexandria render it almost as difficult 
to classify the prose writers as it has been to arrange the poets, 
whose productions have characterized this epoch of Greek 
literature. Very many of the most eminent poets were also 
prose writers, and not only so, but they exhibited their yersa- 
tility by writing on almost every subject of literary interest. 
Callimachus, as we have seen, composed numerous books on 
criticism and history, which are now lost, and Eratosthenes, 
who must be, in some sense, the hero of our present chapter, 
not only composed original and important works on geography, 
chronology, literary criticism, mathematics, and philosophy,’ 
but was also the author of a poem called Hermes, which was 
probably an exposition of astronomy, like that of Aratus,? and 
a mythological poem called Erigone, which Longinus pro- 
nounces faultless.* This being the case, it is obvious that a 
mere arrangement of the principal prose writers, whether they 





1 The following enumeration of the works of Eratosthenes has been drawn up by 
Bernhardy (Zratosthenes, Ὁ. XVI.): ‘(1) Geographica; (2) Mercurius, Poema ; 
(3) Libri de Mathematicd disciplind ; (4) Cubi duplicatio; (5) Opera philosophica ; 
(6) De antiqud comedid ; (7) De chronographiis.’ He omits the Hrigone, the 
epistles, the Arsinoe, and the treatise ‘on good and bad things.’ 

2 The commentary on Aratus, which is attributed to him, is a later work ; see 
Bernhardy, Hratosthenes, pp. 117, 185. 

3 De Subl. XXXIII. 5: ᾿Ερατοσθένης ἐν τῇ ᾿Ηριγόνῃ (διὰ πάντων γὰρ ἀμώμητον 
τὸ ποιημάτιον). 


DEMETRIUS PHALEREUS. 467 


were also poets or not, according to their chronological succes- 
sion, would not correspond to a methodical classification of the 
subjects on which they wrote. It seems best, therefore, that 
we should endeavour to ascertain the departments which were 
chiefly studied by the scholars of the Museum, and the order 
or succession in which these studies were developed, and that 
we should then treat of the authors individually according to 
the branch of study in which they obtained the greatest repu- 
tation. An able writer on this subject’ has divided the per- 
formances of the Alexandrian writers according to three epochs. 
In the first and earliest of these periods, he finds a prepon- 
derating number of poets, and an active criticism of the ancient 
writers. In the second, which he regards as the ripe manhood 
of the Alexandrian school, he recognizes a development of the 
severer sciences, not unconnected with their application to prac- 
tical matters. And in the third, which he considers the period 
of decline, he places the speculations of the Eclectics and Neo- 
Platonists. This subdivision is generally true. Accordingly, 
reserving for a future chapter*® the consideration of the last of 
these three epochs, we must inquire what is the proper and 
methodical arrangement of the authors who have rendered the 
two former periods illustrious; and having already discussed 
the poets who preponderate in the first of them, we shall find 
that the progress of development was from grammar and criti- 
cism, the firstfruits of book learning, to the more elaborate and 
learned treatment of history and chronology, and from the 
ancillary questions of space and time, of distances and dates, 
involved in such an examination of ancient annals, to observa- 
tions and speculations in pure and mixed mathematics, perhaps 
not altogether unconnected with researches in. the ancient lite- 
rature and learning of Egypt. The eminent Athenian, to 
whose arrival at Athens the literary tendencies of the active 
and warlike Ptolemy Soter are generally attributed, was likely, 
from the nature of his previous avocations, to give precisely this 
direction to the studies of the Egyptian Greeks. Drmernrius 
the Pua.ertan, the disciple of Theophrastus and the friend and 





1 Parthey, Das Alexandrinische Museum, pp. 216 sqq. 
2 See below, chapter 1.111, 
}: 85: ae 


468 PROSE WRITERS OF ALEXANDRIA. 


fellow-pupil of Menander, had governed Athens as the head of 
the Macedonian party, from Ol. 115, 4. B.c. 317, to Ol. 118, 2. 
B.C. 307, when his power was overthrown, and he took refuge at 
the court of Ptolemy Soter, over whom he acquired great influ- 
ence, insomuch that he engaged the king in that formal patro- 
nage of literature with which we are now concerned, and was even 
indulged with the favourite occupation of a philosopher, the forma- 
tion or revision of a code of laws.’ Having given advice unfavour- 
able to the pretensions of Philadelphus, he was banished to Upper 
Egypt when that monarch came to the throne, and died in exile 
(from the bite of an asp) some little time after B.c. 283. 
During the long period which Demetrius thus spent at Alexan- 
dria,* he was occupied in the composition of works belonging 
to the class which we regard as specially characteristic of the 
first period of Alexandrian prose literature. We are told that he 
wrote on history and politics, on the poets, and on rhetoric, 
publishing also some of his own speeches; and that besides this 
he prepared collections of Aisop’s fables.* He made, therefore, 
a first beginning of the grammatical and critical literature of 
his adopted country. As he had distinguished himself, while 
still in power at Athens, by a revival of the taste for epic 
poetry, and by a restoration of the old rhapsodical recitations of 
Homer,’ it is not improbable that he stimulated the labours 
which bore so much fruit in the hands of Zenodotus and Aris- 
tarchus. As an Athenian, who never forgot his native land,* 
it may be supposed that he took a special interest in the old 
history of the country which sent forth the legendary Cecrops, 
and which the conquerors of Xerxes had endeavoured to make 
an appendage of Attica.’ And it is not at all improbable that 





1 Milian, V. H. III. 7. 

2 Diog. Laért. V. 78: ὑπ’ ἀσπίδος τὴν χεῖρα δηχθείς. 

3 Cic. De fin. V. το, § 54- 

4 Diog. Laért. V. 80, gives a long list of his writings, dv, he says, ἐστι τὰ μὲν 
ἱστορικά, τὰ δὲ πολιτικά, τὰ δὲ περὶ ποιητῶν, τὰ δὲ pyropixt, δημηγοριῶν τε καὶ 
πρεσβειῶν, ἀλλὰ μὴν καὶ λόγων Αἰσωπείων συναγωγαὶ καὶ ἄλλα πλείω. 

5 Athen. XIV. p. 620. Eustath. ad Jl. p. 1479. 

6 Plut. De Exilio, p. 601, F.: οὗτος μὲν γὰρ ἐν ᾿Αλεξανδρείᾳ, μετὰ τὴν φυγήν, πρῶτος 
ὧν τοῦ Πτολεμαιοῦ φίλων, οὐ μόνον αὐτὸς ἐν ἀφθόνοις διῆγεν, ἀλλὰ καὶ τοῖς ᾿Αθηναίοις 
δωρεὰς ἔπεμπε. 

7 Thucyd. I. 104, 109. 


ZENODOTUS. 469 


he may have given the first suggestion for those translations of 
the hieroglyphic annals of Egypt which are connected with the 
names of Manetho and Eratosthenes. A similar impulse of 
curiosity may have led him to wish for a version of the myste- 
rious books of the Jews, and an old and consistent tradition 
carries back the commencement of the Septuagint translation 
of the Old Testament to the period when the advice of Deme- 
trius was still respected in the Museum, which he did so much 
to found.’ The school of Alexandria followed the impulse thus 
given to it. From grammar and criticism, which dealt with 
words and with books, it passed to history, which treated of 
events; and from Greek history, it passed, in a scholar-like 
spirit unknown to the earlier Greeks, to researches in the old 
Egyptian and Hebrew annals, to which the peculiar position of 
Alexandria directed the attention of the learned men of the 
Museum. And the peculiar genius of a few eminent mathema- 
ticians found a ready transition from these subjects to the 
further prosecution of those geometrical studies for which the 
ancient Egyptians had always been remarkable. We can 
hardly adopt a more methodical arrangement of the prose 
writers of Alexandria than that which is thus suggested by the 
predominant influence of such a man of letters as Demetrius 
the Phalerian. 

ὃ 2. The earliest grammarians and critics of the Museum 
were, as we have seen, Alexander of AStolia, Lycophron of 
Chalcis, and Zenodotus of Ephesus; and while we are told by 
the scholiast on Plautus that the two former especially under- 
took the recension of the tragic and comic poets respectively, 
the great epos of Homer and the other illustrious poets 
were assigned to Zenodotus. We have already mentioned 
Alexander and Lycophron among the poets of Alexandria, 
and we know little or nothing of their prose writings. But 
Zenovotvs, who wrote little or no poetry himself, deserves a 
special notice here, as the leader of the professed critics of 
the Museum. 

The ancient lexicographers and scholiasts mention three, or, 
as some think, four critical scholars of the name of Zenodotus 





1 Valckenaer, Diatribe de Aristobulo, ec. XVI. sqq. p. 47 849. 


470 PROSE WRITERS OF ALEXANDRIA. 


—the Ephesian,' the Alexandrine, the native of Mallus,* the 
disciple of Crates.* F. A. Wolf® identifies the last three with 
one another, conceiving that the disciple of Crates of Mallus 
was of the same place as his teacher, but was called the Alexan- 
drian from his settlement in Egypt. Be this as it may, it is 
clear that the Alexandrian Zenodotus wrote in opposition to the 
Homeric criticisms of Aristarchus,’ to whom Crates of Mallus 
was especially opposed ; and it is not absolutely impossible that 
the name of the great Zenodotus, the first editor of Homer, 
may have been assumed as a nom de guerre by any man of 
Alexandria or Mallus, who wished to impugn the subsequent 
editorship of Aristarchus. We have seen that the Ephesian 
Zenodotus was the colleague of Philetas, as the tutor of Phila- 
delphus, and as the editor of Homer. Some have made him 
the pupil of Philetas, and the preceptor of the children of 
Philadelphus. It is not impossible that he may have taught 
both the father and his sons, and it is clear that he flourished 
in the reign of the second Ptolemy as well as under the son of 
Lagus. Although Suidas calls Zenodotus an epic poet (éo- 
ποιός), and though the Anthology contains three epigrams 
- attributed to him,’ which may, however, be the work of another 
and later writer of the same name, it seems pretty clear that 
Zenodotus did not, like Callimachus, indulge in poetical compo- 
sition, but that he devoted himself heartily and unreservedly to 
the business of a grammarian and critic. Besides the Epitome 
and historical memoirs’ quoted by Athenzus, which may have 
been the works of the Alexandrian Zenodotus,” and the collec- 





1 Suidas: Znvddoros, ᾿Εφέσιος, ἐποποιὸς καὶ γραμματικός, μαθητὴς τοῦ Φιλητᾶ, 
ἐπὶ Πτολεμαίου γεγονὼς τοῦ πρώτου, ὃς καὶ πρῶτος τῶν ‘Ourpou διορθωτὴς ἐγένετο, 
καὶ τῶν ἐν ᾿Αλεξανδρείᾳ βιβλιοθηκῶν προὔστη καὶ τοὺς παῖδας ἹΙτολεμαίου, 
ἐπαίδευσε. 

2 Id.: ηνόδοτος ᾿Αλεξανδρεύς, γραμματικός, ὁ ἐν ἄστει κληθείς. 

3 Theon, ad Arat. Phenom. 33: Ζηνόδοτος 6 Μαλλώτης. 

# Schol. ad. Jl. XXIII. 79: Znvddoros ὁ Κρατήτειος. 

5 Prolegom. Hom. p. CXCIX. 

6 Suid.: πρὸς τὰ ὑπ᾽ ᾿Αριστάρχου ἀθετούμενα τοῦ ποιητοῦ. 

7 Stobeeus (Serm. 2, 61) gives a few iambic lines attributed to Zenodotus. 

8 Athen, X. p. 412, A. 

9 Td. III. p. 96, A: ἐν ἱστορικοῖς ὑπομνήμασι. 

10 This is the opinion of Reinesius and other scholars, 


ARISTOPHANES, 47} 


tions of unusual words (γλῶσσαι), and foreign phrases (λέξεις 
£Ovxai),? which undoubtedly belonged to the Ephesian critic, 
the first librarian of the Museum published an elaborate edition 
of all the chief poets, the tragic and comic writers only 
excepted. Among these we hear of a recension of Pindar* and 
Anacreon,‘ and a collection of the poets of the Epic Cycle.’ 

But his greatest work, and that on which his reputation mainly 
rests, was his edition (ἔκδοσις) or revision (διόρθωσις) of the 
text of Homer. His main object seems to have been the com- 
parison of the different manuscripts brought together in the 
library at Alexandria, and the establishment of a consistent text, 
by expunging or obelizing the doubtful verses, by transposing 
the lines, or by introducing verbal alterations, in accordance 
with certain principles which he had laid down for himself. 
The scholia mention about 400 readings due to Zenodotus, 200 
introduced by Aristophanes, and 1000 corrections of Aristarchus. 
It does not appear that Zenodotus wrote any commentary on 
Homer, but the lexical works referred to above may have been 
connected with his Homeric studies, and he is supposed to have 
been the author of the calculation of the days of the Iliad, 
which is found in the Ilian table, and was prefixed to his 
edition of Homer.’ 

The path opened by Zenodotus was pursued in a more com- 
prehensive spirit of philology by his pupil ArisToPHANEs, 
the son of Apelles of Byzantium, who succeeded Erato- 
sthenes and Apollonius in the management of the Alex- 
andrian library, and flourished about s.c. 200. There was 
hardly any department in the labours of Zenodotus, in which 
he was not followed by Aristophanes, who was, like his 
master, an editor of Homer and the other great poets,’ and, 





1 Schol. Apollon. Rhod. II. 1005. 

5 Galen, Gloss. Hippocr. s.vv. πέζαι, πέλλα. 

3 Béckh, Pref. ad Schol. Pind. p. TX. sqq. 

* Bergk, Anacreont. Carm. Relliquie, p. 25. 

5 Heffter, De Zenodoto ejusque studiis Homericis, Brandenburg, 1839. 

δ See Clinton, F. H. 111. pp. 491 sqq. 

? Diintzer, De Zenodoti Studiis Homericis. Géttingen, 1848, pp. 194 seqq. 

8 He was especially an editor of Pindar. Thomas Magister says in his life of 
Pindar (p. XLV. Donalds.): 6 δὲ ἐπινίκιος οὗ ἡ ἀρχὴ, ‘”"Apiocrov μὲν ὕδωρ,᾽ προ- 
τέτακται ὑπὸ ᾿Αριστοφάνους τοῦ συντάξαντος τὰ Πινδαρικά. 


472 PROSE WRITERS OF ALEXANDRIA. 


like him, compiled collections of unusual or foreign words 
(γλῶσσαι, λέξεις), and wrote memoirs or commentaries (ὑπο- 
μνήματα). But Aristophanes took a wider range in his studies. 
He was a philologer in the largest sense of the term, and may 
be regarded as the great Masoret of Greek literature; for he 
invented the system of accentuation, which, for so many years, 
preserved the original pronunciation of the language ;? he intro- 
duced punctuation, and the divisions of words in the lines ;* and 
by his various writings prepared the groundwork for our revival 
of scholarship in modern times. He not only endeavoured, by 
the aid of the manuscripts, to establish a good text of the best 
writers, but also criticized them with regard to their subject- 
matter, and their taste and judgment in handling it. Nor did 
he, like Zenodotus, confine his attention to the poets. He 
edited Plato* and Aristotle, and wrote an abridgment of the 
work by the latter ‘on the nature of animals.” Many of the 
arguments of the ancient dramas are due to him, and he is con- 
stantly quoted in the scholia. His independent works were a 
commentary on the tables of Callimachus,’ an elaborate trea- 
tise, in several books, on the courtesans of Athens,’ and some 
historical monographs, especially on Thebes or Beotia.’ To 
Aristophanes belongs the honour of having first founded a school 
of grammar; he counted among his pupils the far-famed Aris- 
tarchus, Agallias of Corcyra, Diodorus, and Callistratus; and 
it was from this school that the canon of Greek writers ema- 
nated ; so that Aristophanes and Aristarchus nearly succeeded 
in doing for Greek literature what the scribes of the Great 
Congregation effected for the sacred books of the Jews.® 





1 A portion of his λέξεις is still extant, and is printed in Boissonade’s edition of 
Herodian’s Partitiones. : 

2 See Foster’s Essay on Accent and Quantity, p. 181 sqq. 

3 Id. ibid. p. 186, sqq., ‘Before his time the words were written, wno ae per- 
petuo ductu, the letters of the same and of different words at exactly the same 
distance, without any mark of a pause to distinguish either sentences, or members 
of sentences, or words from one another.’ 

4 He arranged the dialogues of Plato in T'rilogies, Diog. Laért. III. 61. 

5 Athen. IX. p. 408. 

® Ibid, XIII. pp. 567, 583. He enumerated no less than 535 of them. 

7 Suid. s.v. ὁμολώϊος Ζεύς. Plut. De Malign. Herodoti 31. 33, Steph. Byz. s.v. 
᾿Αντικονδυλεῖς. 

8 Cicero (De Oratore, III. 33, ὃ 132) mentions Aristophanes and Callimachus 


‘ 


ARISTARCHUS. 473 


The complete establishment of the Alexandrian school of 
grammar and criticism is attributable to Aristarcuus of 
Samothrace. Having succeeded his teacher Aristophanes both 
in his lecture-room and at the library, he was intrusted by the 
sixth Ptolemy, Philometor, with the education of his son, and 
also had Ptolemy Physcon for his pupil.’ The period of his 
greatest eminence was about B.c. 156. In the decline of his 
life he was so dissatisfied with the treatment which he received 
from Physcon (who commenced his sole and undisputed reign in 
B.C 146,) that he retired to Cyprus, where he died at the age of 
seventy-two, having, it is said, starved himself to death because 
he was labouring under incurable dropsy.2 He left two sons, 
Aristagoras and Aristarchus, who were also grammarians, but he 
was succeeded in his school by Ammonius.’ He counted no less 
than forty scholars, and his school flourished for a long time at 
Alexandria, and afterwards at Rome. ‘There can be no doubt © 
that Aristarchus deserves the reputation which he enjoys as the 
greatest critic of ancient times. He carried to the highest 
point of perfection and refinement the traditions which he 
derived from Zenodotus and Aristophanes, and occupied himself 
mainly with the objects which they had pursued—the correc- 
tion and elucidation of the texts of the ancient authors in 
general, of the poets in particular, and above all of Homer. 
Suidas says that he wrote no less than eight hundred memoirs 





among the most eminent men in different branches of literature and science ; Pliny 
(H. N. Ὗ. 5) calls the former ‘celeberrimus in arte grammatica ;’ and Mr. Foster, 
who has elaborately vindicated his reputation, says (Essay on Accent and Quantity, 
p- 191): ‘On the-whole, in regard to this man’s real character and merit, I cannot 
help repeating what has been said above, and declaring even more, that posterity 
hath been more truly and essentially benefited by the ingenuity of this learned 
Greek, than by the writings of any one profane author of antiquity.’ He refers 
particularly to the invention of punctuation, of which he had said (p. 187) that ‘he 
should not scruple to prefer the merit of it to that of the best critical or gramma- 
tical treatise that was ever written, not excepting Aristotle’s and Quinctilian’s 
great rhetorical works.’ 

1 Athen. II. p. 71, B. 

2 Suidas, s.n.: τελευτᾷ δὲ ἐν Κύπρῳ ἑαυτὸν ὑπεξαγαγὼν ἐνδείᾳ τροφῆς νόσῳ τῇ 
ὕδρωπι ληφθείς. 

8 Suidas informs us respecting the sons of Aristarchus: ἄμφω δὲ ἐγένοντο 
εὐήθεις ὥστε καὶ ἐπράθη ὁ ᾿Αρίσταρχος. ᾿Αθηναῖοι δὲ ἐλθόντα παρ᾽ αὐτοῖς ἐξωνή- 
σαντο. 


474 PROSE WRITERS OF ALEXANDRIA. 


or commentaries (ὑπομνήματα), but unfortunately all his works 
are lost, and we are left to form a judgment of his wonderful 
acuteness and accuracy from the fragmentary extracts scattered 
through the pages of Eustathius and the scholiasts on Homer. 
His great object, like that of our modern critics of the Por- 
sonian school, was to reduce everything to fixed principles and 
definite rules, and this led him to mark with the obelos a great 
number of passages in Homer which did not square with his 
Procrustean criterion of genuineness.” Against these rude 
remedies of fire and steel there was much reclamation among 
his contemporaries, and the younger Zenodotus, Callistratus, 
and others, wrote against his principles of rejection. On more 
general grounds, he was involved in more than one controversy 
with Crates of Mallus, the head of the school aud library of 
Pergamus. Crates wished to favour the allegorical interpre- 
“tation of Homer, which was for a long time fashionable,® and 
which has revived in modern times; but Aristarchus insisted 
on a literal understanding of the narratives in the epic poem. 
And the strict principles of uniformity in usage and construc- 
tion, which were maintained by Aristarchus in his treatise ‘on 
analogy’ (epi ἀναλογίας), were directly combated by Crates in 
an essay ‘on irregularity’ (περὶ ἀνωμαλίας). We may infer 
the love of form and order, which was so characteristic of 
Aristarchus,’ from the fact that he was at the pains to arrange 
the two great Homeric poems in exactly twenty-four books 
each, in accordance with the number of letters in the com- 
plete or later Greek alphabet, a process which must have 
been quite arbitrary, and must have increased his predilection 
for limitations and exclusions. The same process must have 





1 λέγεται δὲ γράψαι ὑπὲρ & βιβλία ὑπομνημάτων μόνον. See the list of his 
writings in Clinton, 7. H. III. p. 530, note f. 

2 See Lehrs, De Aristarchi Studtis Homericis, Kénigsberg, 1833. 

3 On the theories and works of Crates, see Wolf, Proleg. p. CCLXXVI. 
Clinton, F. H. III. p. 528, note e. 

4 A. Gellius, Noctes Atticw, II. 25: ‘duo autem Greci grammatici illustres 
Aristarchus et Crates summa ope, ille ἀναλογίαν, hic ἀνωμαλίαν defensitavit.’ 

* This love of order and symmetry was not exhibited in his person, for Aris- 
tarchus was a notorious sloven. Athen. I. p. 21, C: Καλλίστρατος δ᾽ Ἀριστοφά- 
νειος ᾿Αρίσταρχον ἐν συγγράμματι κακῶς εἴρηκε ἐπὶ τῷ μὴ εὐρύθμως ἀμπέχεσθαι, 
φέροντός τι καὶ τοῦ τοιούτου πρὸς παιδείας ἐξέτασιν. 


ARISTARCHUS. 475 


been adopted in his dealing with the canon of Greek writers in 
general. It seems that this canon or rule for the exclusion of 
all unworthy writers from the list of first-rate or classical 
writers, was first conceived by Callimachus. It was completed 
by Aristophanes of Byzantium, and the list was most rigorously 
reyised by Aristarchus, who struck out of the canon at least all 
writers of his own time. It is not possible to restore the list 
which met with the approbation of Aristarchus. Different 
authorities give us different enumerations of the canonical 
writers, amounting in all to 109 names, and it is clear that 
many of these must have been omitted by the fastidious head 
of the Alexandrian school. The numerous grammarians of 
Alexandria, who followed Aristarchus, were less particular. 
Indeed, they seem to have preferred commenting on poets 
who were almost their contemporaries, and there can be little 
doubt that the canon ultimately contained every Greek writer 
who succeeded in obtaining any reputation or popularity.’ 

Aristarchus was regarded by his immediate successors as the 
leader of grammarians (ὁ κορυφαῖος τῶν γραμματικῶν), the 
arch-grammarian of Greece (ὁ γραμματικώτατος), and Panetius 
considered that his wonderful sagacity amounted to a kind of 
inspired divination.? He stands far above the numerous tribe 
which followed in his steps—the scholiasts, writers on points 
of ‘syntax, etymology, metres, and music, the lexicographers, 
and the laborious collectors of peculiarities of dialects, 
whose numerous works are still extant, whereas we know 
Aristarchus only by the reflex of an universal reputation. 

§ 3. The chief employment of Zenodotus, Aristophanes, 
and Aristarchus, and that which was common to all three of 
these early scholars, was the revision and settlement of the 
text of Homer. And as the form, in which these only re- 
maining specimens of the epic cycle have come down to us, is 
mainly that which was finally established by Aristarchus, the 
subject deserves a special notice in a history of Greek lite- 
rature, 





1 Vide Ruhnken, Hist. Or. p. XCIV., Parthey, Das Alexandrinische Museum, 
pp. 125—128. ᾿ 

53 Athen. XIV, p. 634 C.; ’Apicrapxos ὁ γραμματικός, ὃν μάντιν ἐκάλει ἸΤαναί- 
τιος ὁ Ῥόδιος φιλόσοφος διὰ τὸ ῥᾳδίως καταμαντεύεσθαι τῆς τῶν ποιητῶν διανοίας, 


476 PROSE WRITERS OF ALEXANDRIA. 


The scholiast on Plautus, to whom we have more than once 
referred, tells us that the first collection of the previously scat- 
tered poems of Homer was made in the time of Pisistratus by 
Conchylus and Onomacritus of Athens, Zopyrus of Heraclea, 
and Orpheus of Croton, and that the work which they began 
was finally completed by Aristarchus.' By the side of this 
statement respecting Pisistratus and his edition of Homer, we 
have the regulation of his contemporary Solon, that the 
rhapsodes who recited the Homeric poems at the Panathenza 
should do so according to the .regular succession of the 
subjects,” and should be kept to the authorized text bya 
prompter appointed for that purpose. These traditions taken 
together show that at a very early period the same step had 
been taken with regard to the Homeric poems‘in particular, as 
was adopted with regard to all the epic poems of the Greeks 
when they were formed into the epic cycle, which was an 
arrangement of the poems according to the succession of the 
events recorded in them. How far we are to agree with the 
χωρίζοντες or separators, who referred the Iliad and Odyssey 
to different authors, how far these poems, as they were arranged 
in the time of Solon and Pisistratus, corresponded to the text 
which we have received from Aristarchus, how far the 
διασκευασταὶ or interpolators began their work in the days of 
Orpheus and Onomacritus, how far the ‘ Wrath of Achilles’? and 
the ‘ Iliad,’ properly so called,’ were melted down into one whole 
before the Athenian recension, are questions which we cannot 
expect to settle with the data now accessible to us. Thus much, 
however, may be concluded with tolerable certainty. Aristar- 
chus, with his love of uniformity, and with that pedantic © 





1 Ritschl, Alezandr. Bibl. p. 4: ‘ Pisistratus sparsam prius Homeri poesim ante 
Ptolemzeum Philadelphum annis CC. et eo etiam amplius sollerti cura in ea que 
nunc extant redegit volumina, usus ad hoe opus divinum industria quattuor cele- 
berrimorum et eruditissimorum hominum, videlicet, Conchyli, Onomacriti, Atheni- 
ensium, Zopyri Heracleotee, et Orphei Crotoniate. Nam carptim prius Homerus 
et nonnisi difficillime, legebatur. Quinetiam post Pisistrati curam et Ptolemzi (é.e. 
Philadelphus, who employed Zenodotus) diligentiam Aristarchus adhuc exactius 
in Homeri elimandam collectionem vigilavit.’ 

2 Diog. Laért. XXI. 57, quoting Dieuchidas; Welcker, Ep. Cycl. p. 378. 

3 See Miiller, above, chapter V. 88 5, 6. Grote, History of Greece, II. pp. 
236, foll, _ 


THE RECENSION OF HOMER. 477 


accuracy which led him to insert the accents throughout the 
poems of Homer, did not allow any incongruities either of lan- 
guage, style, or subject, so far as he could discover them. He 
therefore reduced the two poems to one dialect, and as he ar- 
ranged them in a number of books exactly corresponding to 
the letters of the Greek alphabet in his own time, he must 
have dealt with the subdivisions in a somewhat arbitrary 
manner. Perhaps it was he who first inserted some of the 
episodes in order to make up the number of books which his 
fondness for symmetry suggested to him as the most appropriate. 
Originally the separate rhapsodies were arranged merely in 
accordance with their subjects—thus, what are now the fifth 
and sixth books of the Jiiad were originally called ‘ the prowess 
or paramount excellence of Diomed ;? the second book was 
divided into two rhapsodies, ‘the dream,’ and ‘the catalogue ;’ 
and the ninth was called ‘the supplications.’ Crates of 
Mallus, the opponent of Aristarchus, adopted an arbitrary divi- 
sion of the Iliad and Odyssey, suggested by that of Herodotus, 
according to the number of the nine muses, for he arranged 
each poem in nine books.’ In taking the greater number of 
books of unequal length, Aristarchus must have wished to in- 
corporate all that was contained in the different editions of 
Homer, as they appeared in the Alexandrian library. Of these 
editions there were two classes, the public texts, as they were 
received in the different cities, which had from an early period 
encouraged the recitation of Homer’s poems (ai πολιτικαί, κατὰ 
πόλεις, ἐκ πόλεων) and the editions revised by certain eminent 
individuals (ai κατ᾽ ἄνδρα). Of the former, the best known 
were the Massilian, Chian, Argive, Cyprian, Sinopic, Cretan, 
and Molic, the most highly esteemed being the Massilian, 
which was imported at a very early period from Phocza to the 
south of Gaul, and the Chian, which claimed a transmission from 
an original school of the Homeridz. Of the individual texts, the 
best known was the recension by Antimachus of Colophon, who 
flourished at the same time as Plato,* that which the great 





1 Suidas s.v. Κράτης: συνέταξε διόρθωσιν ᾿Ιλίαδος καὶ ᾿Οδυσσείας ἐν βιβλίοις 6’. 

2 Wolf, Proleg. p. CLXXYV.; Villoison, Prol. ad Schol. Venet. p. 26; Mure, 
Hist. of Lit. of Gr. I. p. τρο. 

3 Above, ch, XXX. § 5. 


478 PROSE WRITERS OF ALEXANDRIA. 


Aristotle prepared for the use of Alexander,’ the edition of the 
Odyssey by Aratus, and that of both poems by Rhianus,’ a con- 
temporary of Eratosthenes. All these copies must have been 
accessible to Aristarchus, and there is no reason to think that 
he either introduced his own conjectural emendations into the 
text, or that he omitted any passage which he regarded as 
ungenuine. Thus, though he agreed with Aristophanes in 
considering that the Odyssey properly terminated at 1. 296 of 
book XXIITI.,* he did not hesitate to publish all the twenty-four 
books as they now are, and though his ἀθετήσεις or dis- 
allowances of passages were of constant occurrence, he did not 
expunge any of the lines to which he objected. He contro- 
verted the doctrine of the χωρίζοντες or separators, who, 
originating it seems with Xenon, and supported by Hellanicus 
of the school of Zenodotus, wished to assign the Jliad and 
Odyssey to two different poets.’ In general we may conclude 
that Aristarchus claimed for Homer all that had been attri- 
buted to him on any competent authority, and though his love 
of regularity induced him to impose upon the language and 
metres of Homer a modernized uniformity of orthography and 
dialect, beneath which we have to seek for the language of the 
old poems as they were recited by the rhapsodists before the 
invention or common use of writing,’ and though he ar- 
ranged his collection in an arbitrary and fanciful number of 
books, we are indebted to his critical sagacity and literary 
honesty for a textus receptus of these oldest relics of Greek 
poetry, which has preserved and transmitted to us a record of 
the concurrent traditions respecting the Homeric rhapsodies, so 
far as they were known at Alexandria in the second century 
before our era. 

§ 4. It was not likely that a literary community, such.as that 
which flourished under royal patronage at Alexandria, would 





1 Above, ch. XL. § τ΄ 2 Wolf, Prol. p. CLXXXVI. 

3 Id, p. CLXXXVII. * 5680), Buttmann. ad loc. 

5 Mure, I. p. 192, II. pp. 119, foll. ’ 

6 For example, he writes ἕως for the old @Fos, where the metre requires a 
trochee, though the existence of ds in Pindar and Aristophanes, and the analogy 
of λᾶς, λέως and λαός, véws and ναός, might have induced him to leave the old 
word: see New Cratylus, § 257; Varronianus, p. 288, where this was first 


indicated. 


HISTORIANS OF ALEXANDER THE GREAT, 479 


undertake the composition of histories like those of the classical 
period. Neither the state of public affairs nor the opportu- 
nities enjoyed by these scholars would have enabled them to 
write original histories like that of Philochorus, to say nothing 
of the greater works of Herodotus, Thucydides, and Philistus. 
The only writers of this class belonging to the Ptolemaic period 
were some of the kings themselves. Protemy Sorer, in par- 
ticular, wrote a history of the wars of Alexander the Great, in 
which he*took an active and distinguished part; and Arrian, 
to whom we are indebted for our best account of the battles, in 
which the Macedonian conqueror overthrew the power of the Per- 
sian Empire, often speaks in high terms of the information which 
he derived from the memoirs of Ptolemy. He mentions them, 
along with those of Arisrosu.vs, as the most trustworthy autho- 
rities for the events which he recorded, and it is almost certain 
that the military details in Arrian, which have quite the air of a 
contemporary description,. were derived directly from the soldier- 
like narratives of Ptolemy in particular. It is clear, from 
some passages, that Ptolemy was as careful to abstain from 
claiming a share in exploits in which he had no share, as he 
was in narrating the facts which fell under his own cognizance.’ 

There were other historians of Alexander the Great, who 
flourished in the time of the earlier Ptolemies, but were not, as 
far as we can learn, connected with the Alexandrian school of 
literature. Such were Anticterpes of Athens, whose books 
on Alexander and other historical subjects are often cited ; 
Anaxtmenes the rhetorician of Lampsacus, who wrote Philip- 
pica, or the history of Philip and his son; CauuistHENzs, the 
nephew of Aristotle, who published a history of Alexander and 
other memoirs; Nearcuus the admiral, and his pilot Ownesi- 
critus of Aigina, Hirronymus of Cardia, Cuarzs of Mytilene, 
Cieitarcuus of AMolia, Duris of Samos, and Nympuis of 
Heraclea, all of whom composed histories of the whole or part 
of Alexander’s expeditions, and some of whom wrote about his 
successors.” Their works are lost, and we can only say that 





1 See for example Arrian, Anab. VI. 11, 88 7, 8. 
2 See a list of these writersin Schoell’s Histoire dela Litterature Greque profane, 


ITI. pp. 199, seqq. The fragments have been collected by C. Miiller, as a sup- 
plement to Diibner’s edition of Arrian, Paris, 1846. 


480 PROSE WRITERS OF ALEXANDRIA. 


they belonged, more or less, to the same class with the writings 
of Ptolemy Soter and Aristobulus of Cassandria, though they 
do not seem to have possessed the same value and authenticity. 

The majority of the Alexandrian writers on history were 
book-learned compilers from the written materials to which 
they had such ready access. They belonged to precisely the 
same class as the Atthidists, whom we have discussed in a 
previous chapter, and one of these, the Callimachean Isrer, 
was an Alexandrian grammarian. The Alexandrian Compilers, 
however, did not confine themselves to Attic history, or even, 
as a general rule, make this the basis of their investigations. 
On the contrary, as we have already seen, some of the most 
eminent of them wrote on the antiquities of the Greek towns 
in Libya, and others discussed questions relating to Beotia 
and other provinces of old Greece. Their mythography, too, 
was very general. The favourite form which they gave to 
their researches was that of poetry, and this again furnished a 
vehicle for learned commentaries in explanation of the allusions 
which served the same purpose as the special investigations of 
the Atthidists. Sometimes, however, they wrote systematic 
treatises on mythology, and so endeavoured to bolster up the 
popular belief, which had been sorely shaken by the levity of 
the comic writers, and had received a very questionable support 
from the rationalistic ingenuity of the Cyrenaics. One of this 
school, Evemervus or EvHEMERvs, who was living at the court 
of Cassander in B.c. 316,’ had published a book of ‘sacred 
records’ (ἱερὰ ἀναγραφῆ), in which he endeavoured to deprive 
the ancient mythology of all its supernatural elements, and to 
represent the gods of Hellas as human beings who performed: 
ordinary, or at least possible, exploits.? This procedure found 
no favour with the learned men of Alexandria, and Eratosthenes 
treated Euhemerus with great contempt. And the old poetical 
machinery is revived in a treatise of the Alexandrian school, 
which has come down to us, at least in part. This is the 





1 Euseb. Prep. Evang. II. 2, p. 59 sqq. (I. p. 130, Gaisford; p. 67, Heinichen,) 
Clinton’s Fasti Hell. III. p. 481. 

2 Plut. 78. ef Ostr. c. XXIII. p. 360; Lactant. Jnst. 1. XI. 33; Cic. De Nat. 
Deor. I. 11, 119; Varro, R. R. I. 48, 2; and especially see Hieron. Columna, in 
his edition of Ennius, Neap. 1590, pp. 479-505 ; Creuzer, Symbolik, I. 113, sqq., 
II. 54, 258, 11, 143, IV. 667. 


APOLLODORUS. 481 


Bibliotheca of Avottoporus of Athens, who was, for a long 
time, the pupil of Aristarchus,' and flourished in the second half 
of the second century B.c.? This work, which is in three books, 
and which has not been preserved without many mutilations 
and corruptions, contains a general sketch of the mythic legends 
of the Greeks, derived directly from the old chroniclers and 
poets, especially from the lost poems of the epic cycle.* The 
accuracy with which the author followed the traces of his old 
books, is shown by the frequent occurrence of purely poetical 
phrases in the midst of his prose,‘ and on this account the 
work is of considerable value to us. The first book begins 
with six sections about the theogonies and cosmogonies of the 
ancients, and then passes on to the oldest Hellenic myths, 
especially those of the Aolic tribes; we have the groundwork 
of many an epic poem ; the stories of the Aloides, of Marpessa, of 
(Eneus, Ino, and Athamas, Peleus, Neleus and Nestor, Bias 
and Melampus, the hunt of the Caledonian boar, and the 
voyage of the Argonauts. The second book contains the his- 
tory of the families of Inachus and Perseus. From these the 
author passes on to a full account of Hercules and his adven- 
tures ; and the book closes with the return of the Heracleide, 
and the mythic history of the Peloponnesus down to the time 
of Aipytus. The third book takes up the family of Agenor, 
which it discusses in seven sections, beginning with the Cretan 
legends, going on to those of Thebes, with a special episode 
about Bacchus, and a brief exposition of the Theban war and 
the fate of Alemzon. In the next two chapters it treats of 
Arcadian myths, and goes through the seven daughters of 
Atlas. Taygete introduces us to Lacedeemonian, and Electra 
to Trojan legends. We have then somewhat abrupt transitions 





1 Suidas s.v. ᾿Απολλόδωρος" εἷς τῶν ἸΤαναιτίου τοῦ ‘Podiov φιλοσόφου καὶ ᾿Αριστάρ- 
χου τοῦ γραμματικοῦ μαθητῶν, ᾿Αθηναῖος τὸ γένος. Scymm. Chius v, 22: συνε- 
σχολακὼς δε πολὺν ᾿Αριστάρχῳ χρόνον. 

3 He dedicated his Chronica to Attalus Philadelphus, who died in B.c. 138, and 
the work came down to B.c. 143. Hence it is concluded that Apollodorus was 
known as a writer between Ol]. 150-160. 

8. He mentions expressly Stesichorus, Pindar, the tragedians, especially 
Euripides, Pherecydes, Herodotus, Acusilaus, Amelesagoras, Philocrates, Dema- 
ratus, Asclepiades, Castor, besides Homer, Hesiod, the poets of the epic cycle, 
and Apollonius of Rhodes. 

4 Miiller, Pragm. Hist. Gr. p. XL. 

Vou. 11: II 


482 PROSE WRITERS OF ALEXANDRIA. 


to the Macide, and the stories of Attica; and the book breaks 
off in the history of Theseus, although we know that Apollo- 
dorus discussed the Trojan war and the return of Ulysses.’ 
Apollodorus writes in a simple and unaffected style, though 
sometimes with a brevity which becomes obscure. The work, 
as we have it, is undoubtedly incomplete, but there is no eyvi- 
dence or reason for concluding that it is a mere compendium 
or epitome of the book originally published by Apollodorus. 
The title of Bibliotheca, or ‘library,’ which is given to this 
treatise in all the manuscripts, was probably not prefixed to it 
by Apollodorus himself? It seems more probable that this 
title belonged to a collection of works by Apollodorus, of which 
we have only the separate names—‘ concerning the gods,’* ‘ con- 
cerning the ships im the second book of the liad, * ‘a chro- 
nicle,’® in iambic verse, containing the annals of 1040 years 
from the taking of Troy down to B.c. 143, and a gazetteer in 
comic verse, like the treatises still extant by Seymnus and 
Dionysius.’ The epigram applied by Photius to the Bibliotheca, 
as we have 10,70 would more truly describe this comprehensive 
collection of treatises. Besides these books, Apollodorus wrote, 





1 According to Welcker (Der Epische Cyclus, I. p. 92), the following is the 
succession of the epic poems as they were arranged by Apollodorus. Book I. 
The Theogony, with the Titanomachy and Gigantomachy, the Heroogony, Thebais, 
Corinthiaca, Melampodia, Argonaute. Book II. The Phoronis, Danais, the 
Heraclea of Peisander, the Minyas, the taking of chalia, Hgimius. Book III. 
Europe, Dionysiaca, Cidipodia, the Epigoni (as distinct from the Thebais), the 
Hymn to Mercury, the Cypria, the Trojan war as far as the Odyssey, and 
perhaps the Telogonia, with which Dictys ends. That the book included the 
adventures of Ulysses we know from I. 3, 4: Σειρῆνες περὶ ὧν ἐν τοῖς περὶ ᾽Οδύσ- 
σεως ἐροῦμεν. Photius, Cod. CLXXXVI.: ἐπιτρέχων καὶ τῶν ἀπὸ Τροίας πλάνας 
τινάς, μάλιστα δ᾽ ᾽Οδυσσέως, εἰς ὃν αὐτῷ καὶ ἡ ἀρχαιολογία καταλήγει. 

2 This is the opinion of Clavier, in the preface to his edition of Apollodorus, and 
of Welcker, Ep. Cycl. p. 89. See also Miller, Fr. Hist. Gr. pp. XXXVIIL. sqq. 

3 περὶ θεῶν, in at least twenty-four books, in which he explained the mythology 
by means of allegories and etymologies, after the Stoic fashion. 

4 περὶ νεῶν καταλόγου, in twelve books, partly derived from Demetrius of Scepsis 
(Strabo VIII. p. 522), and Eratosthenes (id. p. 457). 

5 χρονικὴ σύνταξις. Scymnus of Chios, v. 16 sqq. 

6 περὶ γῆς, or περιήγησις, in at least two books ; see Steph. Byz. s.v. ᾽Ἃ βυλλοι 
et alibi. 

7 Cod. CLXXVI. : ἔχει δὲ καὶ ἐπίγραμμα τὸ βιβλιοδάριον οὐκ ἄκομψον τόδε" ᾿... 

αἰῶνος σπειρήματ᾽ ἀφυσσάμενος ἀπ᾽ ἐμεῖο #4 
παιδείης μύθους γνῶθι παλαιγενέας" ( 


ERATOSTHENES. 483 


like Aristophanes of Byzantium and Eratosthenes, ‘on the 
courtesans of Athens ;’* he contributed to the literary history 
of Sophron? and Epicharmus ;’ and showed his connexion with 
the school of Aristarchus by a treatise ‘on etymologies.’ * 

The most valuable characteristic of the historical learning of 
Alexandria was the attention which these scholars paid to chro- 
nology. The Atthidist Philochorus, who was, no doubt, in some 
sense their model, had set them an example in this respect, and 
he had been preceded by Timeeus.’ But the first foundation 
of scientific chronology was laid at Alexandria by the great 
EratostHENnes, whose various labours we shall discuss at the 
end of this chapter. Besides the works of Philochorus and 
Timeeus, Eratosthenes had before him the chronological compu- 
tations of his own teacher and countryman Callimachus, and 
his views were adopted and presented in a metrical form by 
Apollodorus, the pupil of Aristarchus, in the chronological work 
dedicated to Attalus, of which we have just spoken. That the 
chronology of Apollodorus was based entirely on that of Era- 
tosthenes is distinctly stated by Strabo ;° a Byzantine chrono- 
grapher of the ninth century a.p., Georgius, who is generally 
known by his title of Syncellus or colleague and associate of 
the Patriarch Tarasius, in giving the lists of Theban kings 
which he found in Apollodorus, speaks as if it were merely an 
extract from Eratosthenes,’ and modern Egyptologers have so 
regarded it.’ The main effort of Eratosthenes was to establish 
the Trojan xra, which he, and Apollodorus after him, fixed in 
1183 or 1184 B.c., and the greatest modern authorities are 
agreed in regarding this as merely ‘a conjectural date origin- 





und és‘Ounpeinv σελίδ᾽ ἔμβλεπε, μηδ᾽ ἐλεγείην, 
μὴ τραγικὴν μοῦσαν μηδὲ μελογραφίην, 

μὴ κυκλίων ζήτει πολύθρουν στίχον" εἰς ἐμὲ δ᾽ ἀθρῶν 
εὑρήσεις ἐν ἐμοὶ πάνθ᾽ ὅσα κόσμος ἔχει. 


1 Athen, XIII. p. 567 A, 583 Ὁ. 2 Jd. III. p. 89 A 

3 In at least six books, Suid. 5. v. καρδιώττειν. ᾿Απολλόδωρος ἑν ἕκτῳ περὶ 
*Exixdppov. 

4 περὶ ἐτυμολογιῶν or ἐτυμολογουμένων, in at least two books, Athen. II. p. 63 Ὁ. 

5 Above, chapter XLIII. ὃ 6; below, chapter XLIX. ὃ 1. 

6 Strabo, VII. p. 298 sqq. 

7 Syncellus, Chronogr. p. 91, quoted by Bunsen, Zgypten, III. p. 61. 

8. Bunsen, gypten, I. p. 158. 

It 2 


484 PROSE WRITERS OF ALEXANDRIA. 


ally fixed by Eratosthenes, and derived from him to succeeding 
chronologers.’' But, although the actual year of this starting 
point in Greek chronology may be regarded as approximate 
only, and resting on probable inference rather than on absolute 
certainty, we are not the less indebted to Eratosthenes for the 
laborious studies by which he arrived at his conclusions. And 
Mr. Clinton, who has reminded us that a conjectural date can 
never rise to the authority of evidence, has been careful to 
record his opinion? that ‘the chronology of Eratosthenes, 
founded on a careful comparison of circumstances, and approved 
by those to whom the same stores of information were open, 
is entitled to our respect.’ 

δ 5. The want of documentary evidence, which thus qualifies 
the value of the Greek chronology of Eratosthenes and Apollo- 
dorus, is not to be alleged in disparagement of the chronological 
lists of the Egyptian kings which were drawn up by Erato- 
sthenes and Manetho from the copious and authentic records 
of the wonderful country of which Alexandria had become the 
capital. The practice of committing to writing the chronicles 
of their native monarchs which the Egyptians had adopted 
from the first dawn of their history,’ the lasting significance of 
their hieroglyphic symbols, the durability of the material on 
which they were carved, and the dryness of the climate which 
rendered these stony archives indestructible,* had provided Egypt 
with records of the past unrivalled in antiquity and genuine- 
ness. The Ptolemies, who gladly accepted the flattering homage 
of the Egyptian priests, and allowed themselves to be addressed 
as the successors of the ancient Pharaohs,’ eventually conse- 
erated temples to Ammon, Phre, and Phtha, as well as to the 





1 Clinton, 7. H. 1. p. 123; II. p. IV. Béckh, Corp. Inser. II. p. 328. Cf. 
Miller, Fragm. Hist. Grec. p. 568 ; Grote, Hist. of Greece, II. pp. 47 sqq- 

* FH.’ p. 138. 

* It has been shown that the system of hieroglyphic writing was quite complete 
in Egypt in the fourth dynasty, that is, in the fifth century of the kingdom, and 
even the names of kings of the third dynasty are written according to this system 
(Bunsen, I. p. 363). 

4 See the remarks of Lepsius, Chronologie der Aigypter, I. pp. 28 sqq. 

5 Thus, on the Rosetta Table, Ptolemy is glorified as ὃν ὁ Ἥφαιστος ἐδοκίμασεν, 
ᾧ ὁ Ἥλιος ἔδωκεν τὴν νίκην, εἰκὼν ζῶσα τοῦ Διός, vids τοῦ Ἡλίου, αἰωνόβιος, ἠγαπη- 
μένος ὑπὸ τοῦ Φθᾶ. 


ERATOSTHENES. 485 


Sarapis of Alexandria, and our clue to the interpretation of the 
ancient hieroglyphics is derived from a tri-lingual inscription, 
in which Ptolemy Epiphanes is commemorated, not only in his 
own Greek, but in hieroglyphic and demotic versions of it.! 
Under these circumstances, it was quite natural that, on the 
one hand, the Greek scholars of the Museum would make 
themselves acquainted with the old language of Egypt, and the 
hieroglyphic system of writing in which the records of the 
country were locked up; and, on the other hand, that Egyp- 
tian priests and scribes would become familiar with the language 
of the court, and would display their own inherited learning in 
what had become the general idiom of the civilized world. In 
regard to the history and chronology of Egypt we have two 
remarkable examples of these counter processes. For before 
_the great scholar Eratosthenes of Cyrene learned the old Egyp- 
tian of the hieroglyphics in order that he might draw up 
lists of the Pharaohs, and approximate to the chronology of the 
ancient dynasties, Manetho of Sebennytus, a native Egyptian 
priest, who flourished in the reigns of the first two of the 
Ptolemies, had become a master of the Greek language, per- 
haps under the teaching of Timotheus, the interpreter of 
Ptolemy Soter, and had written, for the edification of the new 
masters of his country, on the history and chronology of 
ancient Egypt, and on the religion and science of the Egyp- 
tians.2 From what sources Diczearchus, the scholar of Aristotle, 
had derived his statements with regard to the ancient history 
and chronology of Egypt, for a knowledge of which we are 
indebted to the Alexandrine scholia on Apollonius of Rhodes,’ 
we have no means of ascertaining; but there is no doubt that 
the researches of Eratosthenes, which we know through Apollo- 
dorus and Georgius Syncellus,* rested on a study of the original 





1 The Rosetta table, now in the British Museum, was discovered by the French 
artillery officer Bouchard, in 1799, and became the property of England when the 
French were expelled from Egypt. 

2 Euseb. Prep. Evangel... Prowm. ad Lit. 11. p. 44 ¢. (p. 52 Heinichen): πᾶσαν 
μὲν οὖν τὴν Αὐγυπτιακὴν ἱστορίαν els πλάτος τῶν Ἑλλήνων μετείληφε φωνῆς, ἰδίως 
τε καὶ τὰ περὶ τῆς κατ᾽ αὐτοὺς θεολογίας Μανεθὼς ὁ Αἰγύπτιος ἔν τε ἣ ἔγραψεν ἱερᾷ 
βίβλῳ καὶ ἐν ἑτέροις αὐτοῦ συγγράμμασιν. 

3 See the passages quoted in Bunsen, gypten, III., Urkundenbuch, pp. 68. 

4 Id. ibid. pp. 61 sqq. 


486 PROSE WRITERS OF ALEXANDRIA. 


monuments of Egypt, and though they are confined to the 
Memphito-Thebaic kings, they are still our chief authority for 
the restoration of the first thirteen dynasties; and all that 
modern investigation has attempted for the exhibition of a con- 
sistent view of old Egyptian chronology is deduced from a com- 
parison between the fragments of Eratosthenes and Manetho, 
and the names of the kings still preserved in the hieroglyphic 
tables of Carnak and Abydos. 

The illustrious Manretuo, whose name Ma-n-théth or Thoth- 
ma, ‘given by Thoth or Mercury,’ is a synonym of the Greek 
Hermodotus or Hermodorus,’ although belonging to the compa- 
ratively late period of Alexandrian literature, has come down to 
us shrouded in a mist of legend? And while his genuine works 
exist only in fragments and quotations, or in epitomes of doubtful 
accuracy, his name has been given to an astronomical poem in 
six books, called ἀποτελεσματικά, which has been proved to be as 
late as the fifth century a.p.,* and to a book on Sothis, or the 
dog-star, intentionally forged for the purpose of reconciling the 
old Egyptian chronology with that of the Jews and Christians.‘ 
There can be no doubt, however, after the elaborate researches 
of Bunsen and others, that Manetho of Sebennytus was a real, 
historical personage, who flourished in the reigus of Soter and 
Philadelphus, and deserved what he obtained, the highest 
reputation for judgment and learning. An old tradition, 
‘which is not certain but cannot be refuted,’ places him in the 





1 This is Bunsen’s opinion (4gypten, I. p. gt). Lepsius (Chronol. I. p. 405), 
with whom Parthey confidently agrees (ad Plutarch. Js. et Osirid. p. 180), says that 
the Egyptian form was Mai-en-Thoth, ‘beloved by Thoth.’ Fruin (Maneth. reliqu. 
1847, p. XXVIII.) supposes the original form to have been Ma-net or Ma-Neith 
= qui Neith (¢.e., Minervam) amat. 

2 Bockh (Manetho und die Hundssternperiode, Berlin, 1845, p. 394) says: ‘na- 
mentlich ist mir niemals ein verwirrterer Gegenstand der Betrachtung, als dieser 
Manetho vorgekommen.’ 

3 See Heyne, Opuscul. I. 95. Rigler and Axt, Comment. in Manethonis A poteles- 
matica, Colon. 1832, pp. III. sqq. XXXIV. 

4 Bunsen, Zgypten, I. pp. 256 sqq. Lepsius, Chronologie, I. p. 413 sqq- 

5 Bockh, Manetho, p. 395. This tradition is shown by the dedication of his 
Sothis, which has been fabricated in consequence of the old belief, and by the 
mention of Ptolemy and Arsinoe in the Apotelesmatica. Hengstenberg, who 
always reasons with a set purpose, and with the one-sidedness of an advocate, con- 
tends that Manetho was not an Egyptian, and probably lived under the Roman 
Emperors (die Biicher Moses und 4igypten, pp. 237 sqq. 256, 264). 


MANETHO. 487 


reign of Philadelphus, and the anecdote about the introduction 
of the god Sarapis, which is almost our only certain detail 
about his life, falls, according to Cyril, in Ol. 124 (284—281 
B.c.),' and may therefore be placed at the very end of Soter’s 
life. This story, which is told by Plutarch in the book on 
Isis and Osiris? mostly taken, as Bunsen thinks,’ from the 
theological works of Manetho, is as follows. Ptolemy Soter 
saw in a dream the Sinopic statue of Pluto, which ordered the 
king to transfer him with all speed to Alexandria. Ptolemy, 
who had never seen the image itself, and did not know where 
it was to be found, was enabled to identify it by the description 
of a traveller named Sosibius, and got it from Sinope to Egypt. 
When it arrived it was recognized by Timotheus, the king’s 
interpreter, and Manetho, as Sarapis, the Egyptian Pluto, or 
the Osiris and Dionysus of the lower world; and this new god 
was accordingly established at Alexandria, and his worship 
ultimately superseded that of the older divinities. This cir- 
cumstantial narrative exhibits Manetho to us in important 
relations with the king and the Greek religionists of his court,— 
for Timotheus was an Eumolpid,‘—and we may infer from it 
that he not only introduced the Greeks to a knowledge of the 
Egyptian religion and annals, but conspired with the liberal 
Timotheus in establishing a form of worship which was not 
exclusively Greek or Egyptian, but partook of both systems of 
mythology. The genuine works of Manetho were (1) his ‘ holy 
book’ (ἱερὰ βίβλος), which discussed the religion of Isis, 
Osiris, Apis, Sarapis, and other deities, and was probably the 
basis of Plutarch’s well-known treatise, our most valuable 
authority on the subject ;° (2) his ‘sketch of natural history’ 
(φυσικῶν ἐπιτομῇ, Or φυσιολογικά), which seems to have 
explained the elementary origin of the Egyptian religion, as it 





1 Cyrillus Alex. In Julianum, p. 13 Spanh. 

2c, 28, p. 361 Xyl. It is also given by Tacit. Hist. IV. 83, 84; Clemens 
Alex. Protrept. IV. 48, p. 42 Potter. 

3 Bunsen, Agypten, I. p. 95. = 

4 Tac. Hist. 1V. 83: ‘Timotheum Atheniensem, e gente Eumolpidarum, quem ut 
antistitem cerimoniarum Eleusine exciverat.’ 

5 Eusebius, Pr. Hv. II. p. 44 ¢. Cf. Theodoret. Serm. II. De Therapeut. vol. 
IV. p. 753: Μανέθως δὲ τὰ περὶ Ἴσιδος καὶ ᾽Οσίριδος καὶ "Απιδος καὶ Σαράπιδος καὶ 
τῶν ἄλλων θεῶν τῶν Αἰγυπτίων ἐμυθολόγησε. 


488 PROSE WRITERS OF ALEXANDRIA. 


stated, among other things, the identity of Osiris and Isis with 
the sun and the moon;’ (3) ‘on a love of antiquity and piety ” 
(περὶ ἀρχαϊσμοῦ καὶ εὐσεβείας), which seems to have been a 
treatise on the old religious usages of the Egyptians ;? (4) ‘ on 
festivals’ (περὶ ἑορτῶν), of which we know nothing beyond a 
short notice in Laurentius Lydus;* (5) ‘on the fabrication of 
the different kinds of sacred incense’ (περὶ κατασκευῆς τῶν 
κυφίων), ἃ work having reference to a specialty of Egyptian 
ritual, for Plutarch tells us‘ that the ingredients of the κῦφι 
were not mixed at haphazard (ὅπως ἔτυχεν), but according to 
fixed sacerdotal receipts; (6) ‘against Herodotus’ (πρὸς 
Ἡρόδοτον),᾽ a criticism apparently of those parts of Herodotus 
which treated especially of Egypt ; but Bunsen supposes’ that it 
might have been an extract from the next work, made by those 
who wished to impugn the accuracy of the Greek historian ; 
(7) ‘commentaries on Egypt’? (Αἰγυπτιακά or Αἰγυπτιακὰ 
ὑπομνήματα), in three books. In this book, which has 
furnished the modern Egyptologers, Rosellini, Wilkinson, 
Boéckh, Bunsen, and Lepsius, with the materials for their 
criticisms, Manetho, besides dealing with the astronomical 
periods of the ante-historical mythology, elaborately reckoned 
up 3555 years, from Menes to the death of the younger 
Nectanebus, and in doing this formed a chronological canon, 
which must have influenced the calculations of Eratosthenes 
and Apollodorus.2 In drawing up this chronology, it is clear 
that he did not content himself with adding together the sums 
of the years in the different reigns, for this would have given a 
much greater number of years, but that he learned, by an 
examination of the traditions, that many of the kings in the 
lists were contemporary rulers, and that the general result was 





1 Diog. Laért. Proem. §§ το, 11. Suidas calls it φυσιολογικά. It is referred to 
by 4élian, Hist. An. X. τό. 

2 Porphyr. De Abstinentid, II. 55 ; Euseb. Pr. Ev. IV. τό, 1, p. 164, Heinichen. 

3 p. o1, Bekker. 4 De Iside et Osir. ο. 81. 

5 Joseph. ὁ. Apion. I. 14; Eustath. ad 11. λ' p. 857; Etym. M. 5. v. λεοντοκόμος. 

6. gypten, I. p. 100. 

? That the latter is the true title is conjectured by Béckh (Manetho, p. 395) from 
the Latin version of the Armenian Eusebius, which cites it as Manethi 4igyptiaca 
Monumenta. 

8 Bunsen, “gypten, I. p. 122 sqq. 


HECATZUS, BEROSUS. 489 


to be estimated on independent grounds. When the Egyptian 
learning of Manetho had been followed by the scientific chro- 
nology of which Eratosthenes was the founder, Greek literature 
had passed through all the epochs of its dealings with the 
history of the Pharaohs. In Herodotus, as has been well 
observed,' we have the genial Greek, in Manetho the dry and 
documeutary Egyptian, and in Eratosthenes the critical Alex- 
andrian, and in the combination and intermixture of these three 
sources of information, we obtain all the reliable information 
which we can derive from ancient times to aid us in the inter- 
pretation of the half understood hieroglyphics. 

Hecarzvus of Appera, who is often confounded with his 
older namesake Hecatzeus of Miletus, travelled as far as Syria 
in the train of Alexander the Great, and seems to have acquired 
the language of the Jews,’ whose history he wrote. He was 
also a writer on Egyptian history, and had travelled up the 
Nile as far as Thebes. A work on the Hyperboreans is attri- 
buted to him,’ but we know little or nothing about it. 

A contemporary of Manetho, Βεκοβυβ (i.e. Bar-Oseas) of 
Babylon, performed the same good office for the history of his 
own countrymen that the Egyptian priest had undertaken in 
regard to his own sacred archives.‘ It cannot be determined 
whether this Greek version of Assyrian and Babylonian history 
was suggested by what had just been done in Egypt, or whether 
it was a similar result of similar causes. Berosus had the 
charge of the temple of Belus at Babylon, and, as he had acquired 
the Greek language, it was quite natural that he should en- 
deavour to recommend himself to the Greek dynasty, which 
was established in his country, by a version of the archives 
which were under his care, and which enabled him to show both 





1 Bunsen, gypten, I. p. 176. 

3 Whether the work ‘about Abraham and the Egyptians,’ from which Clemens 
Alexandrinus (Strom. V. p. 717, Potter) quotes a fragment of Sophocles, was 
included in the history of the Jews (Joseph. c. Apion. I. 22 ; ef. Ant. I. 7), or in the 
history of Egypt (Diod. I. 47), it seems to presume an acquaintance with Gen. 
XII. τὸ sqq:, or the document from which that narrative was derived. 

8 Diodor, 11. 47 ; lian, H. A. XI. 1, alii. 

* Lepsius, Chronol. I. p. 10: ‘He dedicated his history to Antiochus Soter of 
Syria, a little before Manetho had dedicated his Egyptian history to Ptolemy 
Philadelphus.’ 


490 PROSE WRITERS OF ALEXANDRIA. 


his own learning and the ancient glory of the Babylonians. 
The work, which he published in three books, and which is 
known to us only from the fragments preserved by the later 
writers, is sometimes quoted as his ‘ Babylonian annals’ 
(Βαϑυλωνικα), sometimes as his ‘ Chaldean history? (Χαλδαϊκά, 
Χαλδαϊκαὶ ἱστορίαι). It brought his history down to B.c. 269, 
and had derived dates from the inscriptions on the bricks, 
probably cuneiform, which enabled him to carry back his 
chronology to an astronomical period of 480,000 years ; and his 
work contained an account of the cosmogony and deluge, which 
are probably reflected in the annals of the Jews.? ΑΒΥΡΕΝΒ, 
who wrote on Assyrian history, has been considered by some 
to have been a scholar of Berosus, with whose works he was 
undoubtedly acquainted. He also quotes from MrcastuEnes, 
a friend of Seleucus Nicator,* who wrote a work about India in 
four books. Whether this work was derived from native 
documents is unknown. It was regarded as a standard autho- 
rity by Arrian and other later writers on the subject of India. 
Pliny’ mentions that one Dionysius was sent by Ptolemy 
Philadelphus to pursue his researches in- India, while Mega. 
sthenes was there ; we do not know what were the results of this 
mission. It is quite uncertain when Mznanpzr published the 
Pheenician history from native sources which is quoted by 
Josephus.° 

While the Greeks at Alexandria and elsewhere thus gained 
a knowledge of the annals and religious books of the nations 
to which the conquests of Alexander the Great had carried 
their victorious arms, the same curiosity gave birth to a trans- 
lation which has exercised a more lasting influence on the 
civilized world than that of any book that has ever appeared 
in a new tongue. There is a tradition, attributed falsely to 





1 Athen. XIV. p. 639; Clemens Alex. Strom. I. p. 392, Potter; Protrept. 
p- 57, Potter. 

2 See Niebuhr’s Lectures on Ancient History, I. p. 18, and compare Ohr. Orthod. 
pp. 131, 221. 

3 Cyrill. Alex. in Julianum, pp. 8, 9. 

4 Clem. Alex. Strom. I. p. 360, Potter. 

5 Ἢ, Ν. VI. 17, 58: ‘sicut Megasthenes, et Dionysius a Philadelpho missus ex 
e4 causa, vires quoque gentium prodidere.’ 

8 ¢, Apion. 1. 18; cf. Clem, Alex. Strom. I. p. 140. 


TRANSLATORS OF THE SEPTUAGINT. 491 


Aristeas, and generally rejected as fabulous,’ that when Deme- 
trius Phalereus persuaded Ptolemy to get the Jewish books 
translated into Greek, Aristeas suggested an expedient by 
means of which the high priest of Jerusalem was induced to 
send the king seventy-two picked translators, six from each 
tribe (ten of the tribes having vanished long before this time !); 
and that in seventy-two days the work was accomplished with 
miraculous fidelity, each of the translators having been shut 
up in a separate cell, and each having executed the whole 
version in the same words and letters!* There is only one 
circumstance more wonderful than this story, namely, that any 
men of sense and learning should have given it a moment’s 
attention.* The origin of the Alexandrine version of the Old 
Testament, and the cause of the name—‘ that of the seventy,’ 
or Septuagint—by which it is still known, can only be inferred 
from a careful study of the translation, and an examination of 
the literary history of the Jewish books themselves.“ The 
Jewish collection of sacred books was gradually formed, after the 
return from the captivity, in the three divisions, still recognized 
by the Jews themselves—namely, (a) the Law or Pentateuch, 
i.e. the five books attributed to Moses; (4) the historical and 
prophetical books; and (c) the miscellaneous works called 
Hagiographa, sometimes designated from the book of Psalms, 
itself a miscellaneous collection in five parts,> which was 
placed at the head of this division of the Jewish literature. 
This collection of the Jewish books themselves was going on 
from B.c. 446, when the Jews were restored, to B.c. 131, the 





1 It was first doubted by Lud. Vives in a note on August. C. D. XVIII. 42, 
_and by the great Scaliger on Eusebius Chron. p. 133. The complete rejection of 

the story is due to Humphry Hody, who wrote a tract on the subject in 1685, and 
returned to it in his great work, De Biblior. Textibus Originalibus, Oxon. 1705, 
pp. I.—XXXVI.; see also H. G. J. Thiersch, De Pentateuchi Versione Alexan- 
drina, Erlang. 1841, pp. 6 sqq. 

2 The statement of the separate cells is Justin Martyr’s story ; Epiphanius is 
contented with thirty-six cells, one for every two of the translators. 

3 The fiction is defended by Usher, Voss, Walton, and even to some extent by 
Valckenaer. 

4 We have discussed this question at length in a book entitled Christian Ortho- 
dowy reconciled with the Conclusions of Modern Biblical Learning, London, 1857, 
pp. r89-26r. 

5 See Jashar, Berolini, 1854, pp. 315, 333- 


492 PROSE WRITERS OF ALEXANDRIA. 


thirty-eighth year of Euergetes II., when the son of Sirach speaks 
of the Greek version as complete.‘ Now, the Greek version of 
the Pentateuch, which seems to be the work of one writer,’ corre- 
sponds remarkably to the Samaritan text, which was taken from 
Jerusalem by Manasseh in the reign of Darius Codomannus (B.¢. 
336—331);° and as the name of ‘ the seventy’ may very well 
refer to the number of members in the Jewish Sanhedrim, it is 
reasonable to conclude that the renegade priest adopted a text 
which was at that time formally sanctioned at Jerusalem, and that 
the same text, with the same sanction, formed the basis of the 
version made for the use of the numerous Jews whom Alex- 
ander settled in Egypt soon after the time of Manasseh and 
Sanballat. The Samaritan version of the Pentateuch, made by 
Nathaniel a little before our era, and the Targum of Onkelos, 
who flourished about the same time, also concur in many points 
with the Septuagint, where it differs from the Masoretic text, so 
that this.agreement alone would not prove the early date of 
the Septuagint Pentateuch. But the necessities of the Jews at 
Alexandria, the step already taken by Manasseh, the natural 
curiosity of the Greeks of the Museum, stimulated by the 
labours of Manetho and Berosus, justify the conclusion that 
there must be a basis of truth in the tradition that the be- 
giuning of the Greek version of the Jewish books was made in 
the reigns of the first two of the Ptolemies. The rest of the 
translation was of course not undertaken or authorized until 
the original books had found a place in the Jewish canon. 
Attention has been directed to marks of time in the separate 
books. A Gallic word (γαισός) found in Joshua* has been 
taken for an evidence that this book was not translated till 
after the Gallic imvasion of B.c. 277. It is inferred from the 





1 Σοφία Σείραχ, πρόλογος, vv. 6, 16. He counts from the beginning of the 
joint sovereignty of Physcon in B.c. 169. 

3 Hody entertained a contrary opinion: ‘sed istam Hodii opinionem,’ says 
Thiersch, u.s., p. 12, ‘Sturzius quidem, uti dictum est, negavit, qui Pentateuchi, 
inquit, versio ab uno auctore videtur profecta esse, nemo autem, quantum novimus, 
refutavit,’ and he proceeds to prove that there is, at all events there was, an uni- 
formity of plan and method in the version of the Pentateuch. 

3 Joseph. Antigu. XI. 7, §2, 8, 82, 4, 6. See Gesenius, De Pentateuch. Samar. 
origine, indole, et auctoritate. 

4 Joshua VIII. 18: ἔκτεινον τὴν χεῖρά cov ἐν τῷ γαισῷ τῷ ἐν τῇ χειρί σου ἐπὶ τὴν. 
πόλιν. Of. Athen. VI. p. 273, and see Hody, p. 178 sqq. 


TRANSLATORS OF THE SEPTUAGINT. 493 


termination of the book of Esther’ that it was not translated 
till the reign of Philometor (s.c. 181—146), and other in- 
dications are remarked in others of the later books. The 
Pentateuch and the book of Proverbs are the most carefully 
translated, but, at the best, we find great defects in the ver- 
sion. Its authors reading the Hebrew rolls without vowel 
points, which were a later invention, and apparently with an 
imperfect knowledge of Hebrew, which had ceased to be their 
vernacular language, adopted strange corruptions of the original 
words,” or sometimes indulged in the rashest conjectures.* 
The book of Job was translated by a man who was well 
acquainted with Greek, and had but a smattering of Hebrew; 
the Psalms and Prophets were rendered by Jews who had no 
literary merit, and whose knowledge of the sacred language 
was very imperfect;‘ and the Septuagint translation of the book 
of Daniel, probably the latest work of the Jewish canon, is so 
unlike the Masoretic text, that the Christian Church adopted 
the later version of Theodotion.? But with all its imequalities 





' Esther X. 43—47. 

2 For example, the common confusion of vesh and daleth, together with the 
substitution of the ordinary meaning of the preposition -by for a more refined 
and idiomatic usage of the word, led them. to read ὉΠ or on for ἘΠῚ in Levit. 
XIX. 26, and to render it μὴ ἔσθετε ἐπὶ τῶν ὀρέων, instead of ἐπὶ τῷ αἵματι, which 
is, after all, a good Greek idiom. 

3 See, for example, the strange confusion which they have made of Gen. IV. 7. 

4 Hichhorn, Hinleitwng, § 166. 

5 Jerome, Prefat. in Danielem: ‘Dan. juxta LXX. interpretes Dom. Saly. 
Ecclesiz non legunt, utentes Theodotionis editione ; et cur hoc acciderit nescio ; 
hoe unum affirmare possum, quod multum a veritate discordat, et recto judicio 
repudiatur.’ - The Greek version of Daniel is interesting, as exhibiting to us 
the process of editorship, while it was still going on, and before the Masoretic 
texts were fixed in their subsequently unalterable form. It is clear that there 
were two editions or recensions of the book of Daniel concurring in many points, 
but differing in a sort of reciprocal avoidance of the most startling impossibilities. 
That followed by the LXX. omits the strange story about the magi, who were 
ordered to describe the dream, as well as to interpret it (Dan. IV. 3—6); also 
the speech of Daniel in V. 17—22. On the other hand, the Masoretic text 
omits the equally improbable prayer of Asariah, and the song of the three intended 
martyrs in the midst of the flames, where there is a manifest gap after the twenty- 
third verse of the third chapter. That the LXX. was in this and other additions 
a bond fide translation of a Hebrew-Chaldee original, is clear from the reasons 
given by Rosenmiiller (Prowemium, ὃ VII.). These indications of the process of 
literary revision, in the case of one of the latest canonical books, support the infe- 


494 PROSE WRITERS OF ALEXANDRIA. 


and defects, this Alexandrine translation of the Jewish books 
exercised a wonderful influence on the world at large. 

The Masoretic editorship of the Jewish schools continued in 
active operation down to the year 506 a.p.; and till the publi- 
cation of the Massorah in that year, the Hebrew text was liable 
to constant emendation. But the name of the Septuagint 
seems to point to an early canonization by the Sanhedrim, to 
the exclusion of other books written in Greek, but not trans- 
lated from the Hebrew, which we now call by their Greek 
name, the Apocrypha. All the references by the earliest 
Christian writers are to this version rather than to the Hebrew 
text, and we can conceive that it was regarded with a veneration 
which was not paid by the Hellenizing Jews to the unknown 
tongue of the original. It had, in fact, received the imprimatur 
of the Greek Jews of Alexandria, who claimed the same 
authority as their brethren at Babylon and Tiberias, and spoke 
and wrote a language intelligible to the civilized world; and it 
was connected with the general renown of the grammarians of 
the Museum, and was probably influenced by the contemporary 
school of Aristarchus, for it can hardly be doubted that the 
arrangement of the canonical books in twenty-four parts, which 
was completed about the time when Aristarchus similarly 
divided the Homeric poems according to the number of letters 
in the Greek alphabet, was suggested by this arbitrary method 
of the Alexandrian scholar, and that the subsequent change to 
twenty-two parts, according to the number of letters in the 
Hebrew alphabet,? was merely a correction made by the 
Masorethz to accommodate their subdivision to the rationale 
of the Alexandrian critics, which they had previously adopted 
without understanding its meaning. 

§ 6. It can hardly be said that the Egyptian researches, 





rence that something of the same kind took place with all the publications of the 
Jews after their return from exile. The intimate acquaintance which the writer of 
Daniel shows (in the eleventh chapter) with the history of Egypt under the 
Ptolemies, indicates his connexion with Alexandria. The story about Alexander 
and the book of Daniel (Josephus, Antiqu. XI. 8, ὃ 5, p. 56, 1. 9, Bekker) is a 
transparent fiction. 

1 See below, chapter LITI. § 1. 

2 See the two arrangements.as given by Bishop Beveridge, Works (Anglo- Cathot. 
Libr.) vol. VII. pp. 202, 209. 


THE MATHEMATICIANS. 495 


which produced such important effects on the historical and 
chronological knowledge of the scholars of the Museum, led 
also to the wonderful advance in pure and applied mathematics 
which took place at Alexandria, or was mainly due to the 
learned men who settled in that city. Herodotus, indeed, is 
careful to tell us’ that in his opinion the Greeks derived 
their knowledge of geometry from the Egyptians, just as they 
learned from the Babylonians the concave hemispherical sun- 
dial (πόλος), the means of ascertaining the period of noon 
(γνώμων), and the division of the day into twelve equal parts ; 
a similar belief was entertained by Plato;? and Anticleides made 
Pythagoras only an improver of the geometry of Meeris.* Land- 
surveying was known in Egypt at a very early period,* mathe- 
matics and their applications were discussed in the sacred books 
of Hermes,’ and the hieroglyphics give us some specimens of 
the geometrical knowledge of the people.’ On the other hand, 
we have stories which show that the Greeks were before the 
Egyptians in many applications of exact science. According to 
Hieronymus,’ Thales astonished the Egyptians by the simple 
method of determining the height of the Pyramids from the 
measurement of their shadows. The Pythagorean theorem, as 
it is called, though connected with some mysterious speculations 
of the Egyptians,* may have been discovered geometrically by 
Pythagoras himself, who undoubtedly may claim the demon- 
stration of the musical intervals ;° and the quadrature of the 
lunula and the properties of conic sections seem to belong to 





1 TI. rog. 3 Phedrus, p. 274, C. Ὁ. 

3 Diog. Laért. VIII. 11: τοῦτον καὶ γεωμετρίαν ἐπὶ πέρας ἀγαγεῖν, Μοίριος πρώ- 
Tou εὑρόντος τὰς ἀρχὰς τῶν στοιχείων αὐτῆς, ὥς φησιν. Αντικλείδης ἐν δευτέρῳ περὶ 
᾿Αλεξάνδρου. 4 Genesis XLVII. 20. 

5 This appears from the remarkable passage in Clemens Alex. Strom. VI. pp. 
757 sqq. Potter, on which see the remarks of Lepsius, Chronologie, I. pp. 45, 46. 

6 See Lepsius, dber eine Hieroglyphische Inschrift am Tempel von Edfu, Berlin, 
1855, who shows how the Greek geometry was expressed in the language of ancient 
Egypt. 

7 Apud Diog. Laért. I. 27: ὁ δὲ Ιερώνυμος καὶ ἐκμετρῆσαί φησιν αὐτὸν τὰς πυρα- 
μίδας, ἐκ τῆς σκιᾶς παρατηρήσαντα ὅτε ἡμῖν ἰσομεγέθεις εἰσί. Pliny, H. N. XXXVI. 
12, § 17: ‘mensuram altitudinis earum omnemque similem deprehendere invenit 
Thales Milesius umbram metiendo, qua hora par esse corpori solet.’ 

8 On the γαμήλιον διάγραμμα, see Plut. de Iside et Osir., p. 373 Εἰ, and above, 
ch. XXXITX. § 9. 9 Bickh, Philolaus, pp. 65—8q. 


496 PROSE WRITERS OF ALEXANDRIA. 


Greek geometers. And although Eudoxus of Cnidus visited 
Egypt, and is said to have brought his theory of the planets 
from that country,’ the respect which was paid to his talents in 
the land of the Pharaohs’ shows that he imported at least as 
much knowledge as he carried away with him. At any rate, the 
great geometers of the Ptolemaic period owe their reputation to 
their own original methods of investigation, or to the skill and 
clearness with which they expounded the doctrines of their 
predecessors. They rather brought their science to Egypt than 
found it there. 

The greatest mathematicians of antiquity, Euclid, Apollonius 
of Perga, and at a later period Diophantus, Pappus, Theon, 
and his daughter Hypatia; the most eminent mechanicians, 
Archimedes of Syracuse, Ctesibius of Asora, and Hero of 
Alexandria; the illustrious astronomers, Timochares of Alexan- 
dria, Aristyllus of Samos, and Hipparchus of Nicza; Erato- 
sthenes, the founder of scientific geography, and Claudius 
Ptolemeeus, who systematized his labours, were all connected, 
either indirectly or immediately, with the school of Alexandria. 
We must confine ourselves to a notice of those who occupied 
an initiatory position m regard to specific branches of pure 
mathematics or their applications. 

Evciepes, or, as we call him familiarly, σοι Τρ, the prince 
of geometers, whose name is almost a synonym for the science 
he taught so well, and whose classical work is still a manual of 
instruction in the chief mathematical school of this country, 
furnishes us with few materials for a literary biography. There 
is no distinct statement in the Greek authorities respecting the 
place of his birth. Oriental traditions make him the offspring 
of Greek parents settled at Tyre, perhaps a confusion with 
Cyrene, where Turoporvs had an eminent school of geometry. 
Like his namesake Eucleides of Megara, with whom he used to 
be confounded, he stands in a certain relation to Tuzzretvs,’ 





1 Seneca, Quest: Natur. VII. 3. 

2 This is implied in the story about the ox Apis licking his garment (Diog. Laért. 
VIII. 90, 91.) 

3 It is not at all improbable that the story told by Valerius Maximus (VIII. 12) 
has substituted the name of Euclid either for that of Theztetus, or for that of 
Eudoxus, both of whom were pupils of Plato, and both predecessors, and perhaps 
teachers, of the geometrician of Alexandria. 


EUCLID. 497 


the hero of Plato’s dialogue of that name, which, as we have 
seen, is supposed to be narrated by the Megaric philosopher 
about the time of the battle of Corinth, B.c. 395. This 
Thezetetus, who was remarkable for his personal resemblance to 
Socrates, is said by Plato, and is understood hy Diogenes 
Laértius,' to have had some instructive intercourse with that 
great philosopher just before his death, when Theztetus was a 
mere boy; he was a favourite pupil of Theodorus, the great 
geometrician of Cyrene; and from the language of Proclus,? it 
appears that Euclid, whether or not a Cyrenzan himself, was 
settled at Athens, and not only became an attached disciple of 
Plato, but in a certain sense continued and completed the 
geometrical works of Theztetus, and systematized what had 
been done by Evpoxus of Cnidus. He came to Alexandria in 
the reign of the first Ptolemy, and almost the only incident of 
his life which is known to us is a conversation between him 
and that king; for Ptolemy having asked if there was no easier 
method of learning the science, Euclid is said to have replied 
that ‘ there was no royal path to geometry’ (μὴ εἶναι βασιλικὴν 
ἄτραπον πρὸς γεωμετρίαν). But though we know so little of 
Euclid’s personal history, we cannot doubt that he founded a 
famous school of geometry at Alexandria, and produced the 
greatest influence on men like Eratosthenes and Archimedes, 
the latter of whom refers to him by name. 

The work for which Euclid is most famous is his Elements 
(στοιχεῖα) of Pure Mathematics, which consist of thirteen books 
written by Euclid himself, and two attributed to Hypsicles of 
Alexandria in the second century of our era.‘ The want of a 





1 TI. 29: ὥσπερ τὸν Θεαίτητον περὶ ἐπιστήμης διαλεχθεὶς ἔνθεον ἀπέπεμψε καθὰ 
καὶ Πλάτων φησίν. 

3 Proclus in Zucl. II. 4, p. 19, ed. Basil. 1532: διῆγον δὲ οὗτοι μετ᾽ ἀλλήλων 
ἐν ᾿Ακαδημείᾳ κοινὰς ποιούμενοι Tas ζητήσεις. Ἑρμότιμος δὲ ὁ Κολοφώνιος τὰ ὑπὲρ 
Evddéov προηυπορημένα καὶ Θεαιτήτου προήγαγεν ἐπὶ πλέον καὶ τῶν στοιχείων πολλὰ 
ἀνεῦρε καὶ τῶν τόπων τινὰ συνέγραψεν .. .. .. οὐ πολὺ δὲ τούτων νεώτερός ἐστιν 
Ἐῤκλείδης, ὁ τὰ στοιχεῖα συναγαγὼν, καὶ πολλὰ μὲν τῶν Εὐδόξου συντάξας, πολλὰ δὲ 
τῶν Θεαιτήτου τελεωσάμενος, ἔτι δὲ τὰ μαλακώτερον δεικνύμενα τοῖς ἔμπροσθεν εἰς 
ἀνελέγκτους ἀπεδείξεις ἀναγαγών . . . . . καὶ τῇ προαιρέσει δὲ Πλατωνικός ἐστι καὶ τῇ 
φιλοσοφίᾳ ταύτῃ οἰκεῖος. 

3 Proclus, u.s. 

4 Mr. De Morgan, who concludes that Hypsicles did not write earlier than 
A.D. 550, makes the following remarks respecting the two books of the Elements 


Vou. Il. K K 


498 PROSE WRITERS OF ALEXANDRIA. 


convenient system of arithmetical notation obliged the Greeks 
to treat many subjects geometrically, which we deal with by 
means of our Arabic numerals or algebraical symbols; and in 
all ages it has been a subject of wonder that Euclid and his 
predecessors should have been able in almost every case to 
adopt the best method that is open to the geometrician. The 
first book begins with definitions (ὅροι) and postulates (αἰτή- 
para), containing all the necessary assumptions to which Plato 
refers in his well-known distribution of the domains of thought ;’ 
these are followed by the common notions (κοιναὶ ἔννοιαι), 
which the translators of Euclid have classed with the first 
three of the postulates, and distinguished by the name of 
axioms, common and proper Greek term,’ but not used by 
Euclid in this case. We have then forty-eight propositions 
rising from the simplest constructions to the properties of the 
right-angled triangle. The second book treats of the properties 
of rectangles contained by the parts of divided lines, with tacit 
reference to the doctrine of incommensurables (a\oya). The 
third book treats of the properties of the circle, and the fourth 
of regular rectilineal figures from the triangle to the quin- 
decagon. And thus the first four books contain the doctrine 
of plane figures, and may be supposed by a reasonable con- 
jecture to contain an improved exposition of the geometry of 
Thesetetus. The fifth book, which he is said to have derived 
from Eudoxus,* treats of proportion, and the sixth applies this 





attributed to this mathematician (Smith’s Dictionary, II. p. 542): ‘It is clear 
enough that Euclid did not write them, because they begin with a preface, a 
thing which is not found even at the commencement of the Elements, because 
that preface makes mention of Apollonius, who came after Euclid, and because the 
author states himself to be the pupil of Isidore,’ who, according to Suidas, was 
the teacher of Hypsicles. 

1 De Republ. VI. p. 511 A: τοῦτο τοίνυν νοητὸν μὲν τὸ εἶδος ἔλεγον, ὑποθέσεσι 
δ᾽ ἀναγκαζομένην ψυχὴν χρῆσθαι περὶ τὴν ζήτησιν αὐτοῦ κιτιλ. Μανθάνω, ἔφη, ὅτι 
τὸ ὑπὸ ταῖς γεωμετρίαις τε καὶ ταῖς ταύταις ἀδελφαῖς τέχναις λέγεις. See Dr. 
Whewell’s paper ‘on Plato’s survey of the sciences,’ Trans. of the Cambridge 
Philosoph. Soc. vol. IX. part IV. 

2 Aristot. Analyt. Post. I. ἃ, ὃ 7: ἣν δ᾽ ἀνάγκη ἔχειν τὸν ὁτιοῦν μαθησόμενον, 
ἀξίωμα" ἔστι γὰρ ἔνια τοιαῦτα" τοῦτο γὰρ μάλιστ᾽ ἐπὶ τοῖς τοιούτοις εἰώθαμεν ὄνομα 
λέγειν. 

3 It is attributed to Eudoxus in one of the MSS. See Fabric. Bibl. Gr. IV. 
p- 12, 


EUCLID. 499 


theory to the results of the first four books, discussing the 
doctrine of similar figures, and involving geometrically the rules 
of quadratic equations. The seventh, eighth, and ninth books 
treat of the properties of numbers; the tenth considers in 
detail the question of irrational quantities ;' the eleventh and 
twelfth books give us the elements of solid geometry; and the 
five regular solids are discussed in the last three hooks, two of 
which, as we have said, are attributed to Hypsicles. This 
great work became the subject of special elucidations even in 
ancient times, and the commentaries of Proclus, with extracts 
from the lectures of Theon of Alexandria, have often been 
printed with the Greek editions of the text. 

Next in repute to the Elements stand the Data (δεδομένα) of 
Euclid, a sort of introduction to analytical geometry, consisting 
of ninety-five geometrical propositions, showing that, if certain 
properties or ratios are given, others may be deduced conse- 
quentially. Professor De Morgan speaks slightingly of this 
work,’ but it was a favourite with Sir Isaac Newton. It is 
generally published with a preface (προθεωρία) by Marinus of 
Naples. 

The Phenomena (Pawopeva), or principles of astronomy 
(Apxai ἀστρονομίας), discuss some of the geometrical pro- 
perties of the sphere, especially with reference to the demon- 
stration of the risings and settings of the stars. The work is 
cited as Euclid’s by Pappus, and is highly commended by 
Delambre.’ 

Two treatises on music, namely, the introduction to harmonics 





1 There is a passage in Plato’s Thewtetus which might lead us to conjecture that 
in this part of the work Plato’s friend had furnished Euclid with some of his 
materials. Theztetus is made to say (p. 147 C): κινδυνεύεις ἐρωτᾶν οἷον καὶ αὐτοῖς 
ἡμῖν ἔναγχος εἰσῆλθε διαλεγομένοις, ἐμοί τε καὶ τῷ σῷ ὁμωνύμῳ τούτῳ 
Σωκράτει. Compare the words which follow with the language of Euclid at the 
beginning of his tenth book. Proclus (u.s.) attributes to Plato the introduction of 
the term προμήκης (Thecetet. p. 148 A, Tim. p. 73 D), who may, however, have 
adopted it from Theztetus. 

2 Smith’s Dict. II. p. 68: ‘there is not much more in this book of Data than 
an intelligent student picks up from the Elements themselves, on which account we 
cannot consider it as a great step in geometrical analysis.’ 

3 Hist. de V Astron. Anc. I. p. 51: ‘ce livre est précieux comme monument 
historique, et comme un dépét qui doit étre & peu prés complet des connaissances 
qu’on avait en Gréce ἃ cette époque.’ 

K K 2 


500 PROSE WRITERS OF ALEXANDRIA. 


(εἰσαγωγὴ ἁρμονική), and the division of the scale (κατατομὴ 
κανόνος), and two essays on optics and catoptrics (ὑπτικὰ Kat 
κατοπτρικά), are the only other works still extant in Greek 
which are attributed to Euclid. The first of these is assigned 
in some of the manuscripts to Cleonidas. The others have 
been rejected by various editors, either on account of their 
want of vigour or from other reasons, more or less valid. 

The following works attributed to Euclid are either lost or 
exist only in translations or re-translations from the Arabic. On 
the division of surfaces (περὶ διαιρέσεων), from the Arabic of 
Mohammed of Bagdad ; de levi et ponderoso, a Latin fragment 
only ; four books on conic sections (κωνικῶν βιβλία δ men- 
tioned by Pappus; three books of corollaries or deductions 
(πορισμάτων βιβλία γ᾽} mentioned by Proclus and Pappus, and 


discussed in a special essay by Robert Simson, the celebrated - 


translator of the Elements ;* two books on plane loci (τόπων 
ἐπιπέδων [3') mentioned by Pappus; two books on the relations 
between loci and a given surface (τόπων πρὸς ἐπιφάνειαν βιβλία 
B’) mentioned by Pappus and Eutocius ; and a treatise on fal- 
lacies (περὶ Wevdapiwv) referred to by Proclus. 

ARCHIMEDES, who is scarcely less celebrated than Euclid, 
though much less studied, was a native of Syracuse, and, as it 





1 These two works are printed in Meibomius, Antique Musiew auctores septem, 
Amstel. 1652. Of the κατατομὴ κανόνος, Bockh says (De Arati Canone, p. 102): 
‘constat canonis sectionem, canonices musice opus, nihil esse aliud nisi musicorum 
certi alicujus systematis sonorum in monochordo designationem, que secundum 
longitudinem chordarum instituatur.’ 

2 Montucla (Hist. d. Mathem. I. p. 215) thinks that the Porismata must be 
reckoned as the most profound work of Euclid, and that it would have been most 
honoured, if it had come down complete to our times. 

3 Tractatus de Porismm. ; Roberti Simsoni opera qiuedann reliqua, Glasg. 1776, 

315. 
᾿ 4 This title is rightly rendered by Commandine loci ad swperficiem, for 
ἐπιφάνεια means the upper or illuminated surface of any plane (see Euclid, Zlem. 
I. ἐ: ἐπιφάνεια δὲ ἐστι ὃ μῆκος καὶ πλάτος μόνον ἔχει. Cf. Polyb. VI. 23. 3. 
Aristot. H. 4. 1. 16). Professor De Morgan says (Smith’s Dict. ΤΙ, p. 70): ‘what 
these τόποι π. ἐ. were, neither Pappus nor Eutocius informs us; the latter says 
they derive their name from their own ἰδιότης, which there is no reason to doubt. 
We suspect that the books and the meaning of the title were as much lost in the 
time of Eutocius as now.’ It appears to us that this treatise differed from that on 
plane loci merely in this, that the former discussed the relations of Joci in the same 
plane, this the relations of loci to a given plane. 


— 


ARCHIMEDES. 501 


seems, a man of humble origin.’ He was born, according to 
Tzetzes, in B.c. 287, for he was seventy-five years old when he 
lost his life at the storming of Syracuse by Marcellus in B.c. 
212.’ According to Proclus, he travelled to Egypt at an early 
age, and studied mathematics there in the school of Euclid, or 
under Conon the Samian. At a later period he constructed an 
enormous vessel for Hiero, king of Syracuse, which was pre- 
sented to Ptolemy Euergetes.* This ancient Leviathan was 
launched by means of a screw invented by Archimedes,‘ and a 
water-screw was also contrived by him for pumping the water 
out of the hold. It seems that he sailed to Alexandria in the 
ship, and that he taught the Egyptians the application of his 
water-screw to the annual business of irrigating the Delta.’ 
His connexion with the school of Alexandria is farther shown 
‘by his sending the problem about the oxen of the sun in a 
letter to Eratosthenes.’ The greater part of his life, however, 
was spent at Syracuse, where he not only distinguished himself 
as a pure mathematician and astronomer, and as the founder of 
the theory of Statics, but applied his knowledge to the con- 
struction of machines, and not only those which were of use 
for peaceful purposes, but also and especially of those engines 
of war, the necessity for which applied the first stimulus to the 
mechanical ingenuity of the Greeks. The siege of Samos by 
Pericles is said to have given rise to the first improvement in 
this artillery ;’ it received a special development under Deme- 
trius Poliorcetes, in whose time Dionysius of Alexandria is said 
to have contrived for the Rhodians a catapult for shooting 
volleys of arrows at the same time (πολυβόλος καταπέλτης) ὃ 
But Archimedes has the credit of carrying -this application of 





1 Cic. Tusc. V. 23, § 64: ‘ex e&dem urbe humilem homunculum a pulvere et 
radio excitabo, Archimedem.’ Plutarch seems to have imagined that he was a 
relation of king Hiero. He says (Vit. Marcelli, 14. p. 305 fin.): ᾿Αρχιμήδης Ἱέρωνι 
τῷ βασιλεῖ συγγενὴς ὧν καὶ φίλος. 

3 Tzetzes, Chil. II. tos. 3 Athen. V. p. 206 D. 

4 Id. p. 207 A: κατασκεύασας γὰρ ἕλικα τὸ τηλικοῦτον σκάφος εἰς τὴν θάλασσαν 
κατήγαγε" πρῶτος δ᾽ ᾿Αρχιμήδης εὗρε τὴν τῆς ἕλικος κατασκεύην. 

> Diodor. I. 34. Vitruv. X. 11. 

8 See Hermann, De Archimedis Problemate Bovino, Opusc. IV. pp. 228 sqq. ἡ 

7 Ephorus (Fragm. 117, Miiller) apud Plut. Pericl. 27. See, however, Grote, 
Hist. of Gr. VI. p. 38, note. 

8 Diodor. XX. 48. Philo. in Math. vet. pp. 73, 76. 


502 PROSE WRITERS OF ALEXANDRIA. 


ingenuity much farther than any of his predecessors or con- 
temporaries, and his engines were so powerful that he is said 
to have obliged Marcellus to convert the siege of Syracuse into 
a blockade.’ The story about his burning the enemy’s ships 
by reflections from a mirror is probably a fiction.’ 

The great discoveries of Archimedes were the following :— 
(1) He demonstrated -the first principle of Statics by ‘establish- 
ing, on true grounds, the general proposition concerning a 
straight lever, loaded with two heavy bodies, and resting upon 
a fulcrum.’ The proposition is, that two bodies, so circum- 
stanced, will balance each other, when the distance of the 
smaller body from the fulerum is greater than the distance of 
the other in exactly the same. proportion in which the weight 
of the body is less.’* This theory of the lever, which was the 
foundation of all that was known of Statics till the seventeenth 
century, was fully appreciated, in all its consequences, by 
Archimedes himself, and he is reported to have said: ‘ Give me 
a locus standi, and I will move the whole world with my stil- 
γα. (2) He invented the -planetarium or orrery ; there are 
many references to his contrivance for representing the moye- 
ments of the heavenly bodies, but we have no particular 
description of it.’ (3) He discovered the ratio (1) between the 
area of a great circle and the surface of a sphere, and that (3) 
between the volumes and surfaces of the sphere and circum- 
scribing cylinder. To the latter he attached so much impor- 
tance, that he directed a sphere inscribed in a cylinder to be 
placed on his tomb, and his wish was attended to; for Cicero, 
when queestor in Sicily B.c. 75, found his tomb with this figure 
upon it, overgrown with briars and unknown to the Syracusans” 





1 Plut. Marcell. τ5---τ8. Liv. XXIV. 34. Polyb. VIII. 5—9. 

2 See the authorities quoted in Smith’s Dictionary, I. pp. 270, 271. The possi- 
bility of the story is discussed by Montucla, Hist. d. Math. I. p. 233 564. 

8 It is clear that Aristotle did not understand the principle of the lever, for he 
takes the water as the weight and the rowlock as the fulcrum of the oar (Mechanica, 
Cc. 4). : 

4 Whewell, History of the Inductive Sciences, I. p. 97. 

5 Tzetzes apud Wallis, III. 537, 545 : δὸς ποῦ στῶ καὶ χαριστίωνι τὰν γᾶν κινήσω 
πᾶσαν. 

§ Cic. De Nat. Deorwm, II. 35, § 88. usc. I. 25, § 63. Ovid, Fast. VI. 277. 
Claudian, Epigr. XXI. in spheram Archimedis, το. 


ARCHIMEDES. 503 


themselves, near one of the city gates." (4) He solved the 
theorem of the centre of gravity of a triangle, of the quadrature 
of the parabola, and of the dimensions of the circle. (5) He 
invented the water-organ, the pulley, and the hydraulic screw. 
(6) He discovered the relation between the weight of bodies 
and the displacement of the water in which they are immersed. 
There is a celebrated account of the circumstances which led 
him to this discovery. Hiero suspected that there was an 
admixture of silver in a golden crown which he had received 
from his goldsmith, and Archimedes undertook to ascertain it 
without interfering with the metal of the crown. The method 
of investigation was suggested to him by observing, while in 
the bath, that a body immersed in water loses weight in pro- 
portion to the displaced volume of the water. In his joy he 
rushed, naked as he was, into the street, shouting, ‘I have 
found it, I have found it’ (εὕρηκα, εὕρηκα), words which have 
become proverbial for sudden discoveries.’ 

When Syracuse was taken by surprise Marcellus gave in- 
junctions that Archimedes should be spared. But one of the 
soldiers, finding him engaged in his studies, and irritated by 
his request that his mathematical instruments might not be 
touched, slew him in the heat of the moment. Marcellus 
regretted his death, and treated his family with kindness and 
liberality.’ 

The works of Archimedes, written in the Doric dialect, are 
as follows :* (1) on the sphere and the cylinder in two books ; 
(2) on the dimensions of the circle, in which he shows that the 
ratio of the periphery to the diameter is less than > and greater 
than 55 ; (3) on the equilibrium of planes.and their centres of 
gravity ; (4) on spheroids and conoids, in two books, in which 
he proves that the surface of the ellipse is to that of the cir- 
cumscribed circle as the minor axis is to the major, which is 





1 Cic. Tusc. V. 23, §§ 64—66. He had some of the underwood cleared away, 
and prides himself very much on his discovery. ‘Ita nobilissima Greeciz civitas, 
quondam vero etiam doctissima, sui civis unius acutissimi monumentum ignorasset, 
nisi ab homine Arpinate didicisset.’ 

2 Vitruv. IX. 3. Proclus in Zucl. II. 3. 

3 Plut. Marcell. 19, who gives three accounts of the circumstances of the death 
of Archimedes. 

4 See Torelli’s edition, Oxon. 1792, and Peyrard’s French translation, Paris, 1808, 


504 PROSE WRITERS OF ALEXANDRIA. 


also the diameter of the circle; (5) on spirals; (6) on the quad- 
rature of the parabola; (7) on the number of the sand (Wappi- 
της), m which he shows that it is possible to give a greater 
number to the grains of sand than would be included in a ball, 
bounded by the sphere of the fixed stars; (8) the epigram on 
the number of the oxen of the sun (πρόβλημα βοεικόν). 

The most eminent Alexandrian mathematician of the school 
of Euclid was Arottonivus, born at Perga in Pamphylia, in the 
reign of Euergetes, and distinguished as a writer in the capital 
of Egypt, under Philopator (B.c. 221—204).' His commen- 
tator, Eutocius, calls him ‘the great geometer,’ and he enjoys 
the reputation of having perfected the doctrine of conic’ 
sections.” His predecessors considered the cone as cut by a 
plane perpendicularly to one of its sides, and therefore required 
three distinct cones, right-angled, acute-angled, and obtuse- 
angled, in order to obtain the parabola, ellipse, and hyperbola 
respectively ; whereas Apollonius derived these conclusions 
from the sections of any cone with a circular base by varying 
the inclination of the cutting plane. Of his great work on the 
subject, the conic elements (κωνικὰ στοιχεῖα) in eight books, 
only the first four have come down to us in Greek. The 
eighth is Jost altogether, and the fifth, sixth, and seventh were 
recovered, in the seventeenth century, from two Arabic manu- 
scripts at Leyden and Florence. The eighth has been restored 
by our countryman, Edward Halley,’ from the lemmas of 
Pappus. We are told by Eutocius that Heraclius, in his life 
of Archimedes, accused Apollonius of appropriating the un- 
published conic sections of the great mathematician of Syracuse ; 
but, as Geminus remarked, neither Archimedes nor Apollonius 
discovered conic sections, and no one can deny to the latter* 
the great improvements in the discussion of this branch of 





1 Eutoc. Comm. in Apoll. Con. I. Photius Cod. CXC. 

2 Ruhnken, Oratio de Grecia artium ac doctrinarum inventrice, p. 95: * Archi- 
medi tum alios, si libet, adjicite, tum imprimis prestantem arte sua hominem, 
Apollonium Pergeum, qui primus omnium, quantum scimus, latentes antehae et 
obscuras conicarum sectionum proprietates in lucem protulit et scienter decla- 
ravit.’ 

3 Apollonit Pergai Conicorum, Libr. VILI., Oxon, 1710. 

4 Montucla (Hist. ὦ. Mathem. I. p. 246) does not hesitate to pronounce the Conic 
Sections of Apollonius ‘un des ouvrages les plus précieux de l'antiquité.’ 


ERATOSTHENES. 505. 


mathematics to which we have already adverted. It was 
Apollonius, too, who invented the name of ellipse and 
hyperbola for the sections of the acute-angled and obtuse- 
angled cone. The section of the right-angled cone was 
called parabola by Archimedes,’ who, as we have seen, wrote 
upon its quadrature. It was Apollonius also, who distinguished 
the diameters from the axes of the other two conic sections, 
and restricted the term axis in the parabola to the line which 
passes through the vertex and the focus. 

Besides the conic sections, we are informed by Pappus that 
the following works were written by Apollonius of Perga: (1) 
how to cut segments from two given lines in a given ratio 
(περὶ λόγου ἀποτομῆς), and so as to contain a given rectangle 
(περὶ χωρίου ἀποτομῆς); (2) on the determinate section (περὶ 
διωρισμένης τομῆς); (3) on plane loci (περὶ τόπων ἐπιπέδων): 
these subjects have been discussed by R. Simson, the editor of 
Euclid, who has endeavoured to reproduce the solutions of 
Apollonius ;? (4) on tactions (περὶ ἐπαφῶν); (5) on inclinations 
(περὶ νεύσεων). 

We have already referred in general terms to the diversified 
labours of Eratosthenes, and to his special merits as a chrono- 
loger. Before we attempt to explain what he did in more 
than one application of mathematical science, it will be right 
to state what is known of his personal history. ErarostHEnes, 
the son of Aglaus* of Cyrene, was born B.c. 276, and died 
about 8.0. 196, it is said of voluntary starvation, because his 
sight was growing dim.‘ He was, therefore, a younger con- 





1 Originally παραβολὴ was a general term synonymous with μερισμὸς and signi- 
fying division as opposed to multiplication. It was applied to the division of the 
cone, when there was only one section for the same cone. In later Greek παρα- 
βολὴ signifies any excentric curve: thus we have in Plutarch (Aratus 22): διὰ 
πολλῶν ἑλιγμῶν καὶ παραβολῶν περαίνοντος πρὸς τὸ τεῖχος. The terms ἔλλειψις and 
ὑπερβολὴ are the well known expressions used by Aristotle to denote the two vicious 
extremes of excess and defect (Zth. Nic. 11, 6: τὸ 8 ἴσον μέσον τι ὑπερβολῆς καὶ 
ἐλλείψεως), and it was applied to the two conic sections between which the circle 
was regarded a sort of mean. 

2 περὶ τόπων ἐπιπέδων. <A treatise in two books on Plane Loci. Restored by 
R. Simson. Glasg. 1749. 

ν According to Suidas some called his father Amihroging, but the best authorities 
are in favour of the other name. 

4 Suidas : ἀποσχόμενος τροφῆς διὰ τὸ ἀμβλυώττειν. 


506 PROSE WRITERS OF ALEXANDRIA. 


temporary of Archimedes, who, as we have seen, was his friend 
and correspondent, and he flourished in the reigns of the third, 
fourth, and fifth Ptolemies. He studied philosophy at Athens 
under Ariston of Chios, and the academician Arcesilas, and laid 
the foundations of his grammatical and critical knowledge 
under Lysanias of Cyrene and his countryman Callimachus. 
And he was himself the teacher of Aristophanes of Byzantium, 
and other less known men of letters. It is stated that Ptolemy 
Euergetes summoned him from Athens to Alexandria,’ and he 
became the successor of Callimachus, and the immediate pre- 
decessor of Apollonius of Rhodes, as the head of the library. 
Of all the Alexandrians whom we have mentioned, Erato- 
sthenes stands decidedly the highest. Comparing him with 
Callimachus, who alone can vie with him in the versatility of 
his mind, Strabo says that ‘Callimachus indeed was both a 
poet and a grammarian, but that Eratosthenes was not only 
these, but attained also to the highest excellence in philosophy 
and mathematics.’* He used to be called the second or new 
Plato (δεύτερος ἢ νέος Πλάτων), and certainly no one except 
Aristotle could be compared with him in the compass and 
accuracy of his knowledge.’ He was ‘ the admirable Crichton ἡ 
of ancient learning, and was called ‘the Πένταθλος;,᾽ or ‘ quin- 
tuple athlete,’ from the name of the champion in the public 
games who excelled in all the five manifestations of bodily activity. 
It is said that he was also called Para, because he attained to 
the second place of excellence in all the sciences,’ and if this 





1 Suidas: μετεπέμφθη ἐξ ᾿Αθηνῶν ὑπὸ τοῦ τρίτου Πτολεμαίου καὶ διέτριψε μέχρι 
τοῦ πέμπτου. 

2 XVII. p. 838 A: ὁ μὲν ποιητὴς ἅμα καὶ περὶ γραμματικὴν ἐσπουδακώς" ὁ δὲ καὶ 
ταῦτα καὶ περὶ φιλοσοφίαν καὶ τὰ μαθήματα εἴ τις ἄλλος διαφέρων. 

3 Bernhardy, Hratosthenica, Berol. 1822, pp. XIII. XIV.: ‘sive enim accura- 
tissimum requiras doctrinarum complexum, sive eruditionem minutissima queque 
adhibentem ac suis in locis reponentem, ratione, judicio subtilissimo, sagacitate 
moderatam, sive humanitatem, que in angustiis aut anguli natura concessi aut 
disquisitionum minime defixa, veritatem unice investiget, et ad justam ac liberalem 
gentis humane sese emergat estimationem ; artiorem harum virtutum consocia- 
tionem preter Aristotelem nemo ex antiquis auctoribus Eratosthene perfectius 
instituisse deprehendatur.’ 

4 Suidas, as corrected by Meursius; Artemidor. Ephes. ap. Marc. Heracl. in 
Geogr. min. ed. Hudson, I. p. 62: καὶ μετ᾽ ἐκεῖνον ᾿Ερατοσθένης ὃν βῆτα ἐκάλεσαν 
oi τοῦ Μουσείου προστάντες, Chrestom. ex Strabone, ibid. 11, p. 5: ὅτι Ἔρατο- 


ERATOSTHENES. 507 


was the concession of his envious rivals, it is an admission of 
little less value than that of the different Greek states when 
they agreed to place Themistocles second to their own hero at 
Salamis.’ But it is not certain that this was the meaning of 
the distinctive affix. At any rate, there are two branches of 
science in which Eratosthenes must be regarded as second to 
none. ‘ He founded two sciences, says one of his modern 
admirers,’ ‘both of which he found in their infancy—astro- 
nomical geography, and chronology. His calculation of the 
magnitude of the globe was recognized by modern science as 
the most correct that has ever been made. His investigations 
into the synchronisms of the Olympiads, and his indication of 
the leading points in general Greek history, upwards to the 
return of the Heracleide, and downwards to Alexander the 
Great, became and remained the foundation of all the chrono- 
logical researches of the ancient world. In geography he was 
the guide and authority of Strabo and Ptolemy, in chronology 
of Apollodorus and the later inquirers. He founded the 
historical criticism of the primitive Greek history. As 
Pythagoras was the first who bore the title of ‘ philosopher,’ so 
Eratosthenes was first honoured with the name of ‘ philologer,’ * 
a name which now includes every application of book know- 
ledge, and which, according to one modern writer,’ implies 
the knowledge of the known. But he was also an observer, a 
collector of facts, an inductive philosopher, and his reputation 
depends more on his discoveries, which have been duly recorded 





σθένης οὔτε τῶν ἀπαιδεύτων ἣν, οὔτε τῶν γνησίως φιλοσοφούντων" διὸ καὶ βῆτα 
ἐκαλεῖτο, ὡς τὰ δευτερεῖα φέρειν δοκῶν ἐπὶ πάσῃ παιδείᾳ. Other letters were used 
as surnames ; see Jonsius, Hist. Phil. p. 147; Lehrs. Quest. ep. p. 19, quoted 
by Parthey, Alex. Mus. p. 53, who cites from Simon De Magistris, p. 563, 
two explanations of the Bra: ‘potuit enim Eratosthenes dici βῆτα, quod Serapei 
bibliothecze prasesset, que secunda habebatur, aut Algyptio nomine a Grecis 
delinito, dictus fuit βαϊήθ (ψυχὴ καὶ καρδία). Apollonius of Perga was called 
ε from his fondness for observing the moon, which, in its crescent form, resembled 
that letter. 

1 Herodotus, VIII. 123. 

2 Bunsen, Zgypten, I. p. 158. 

3 Bernhardy, Hratosthenica, p. XIV.; Wyttenbach, ad Plutarch. de audiendis 
Poetis, p. 22 ο. [p. 226]. 

* Steinthal, De pronomine relativo, p. 5: ‘ itaque una viri doctissimi atque cla- 
rissimi Béckhii definitio mihi videtur recta : philologiam esse cogniti cognitionem.’ 


508 PROSE WRITERS OF ALEXANDRIA. 


and transmitted to us, than on his literary labours, which are 
represented only by a few fragments. 

The works of Eratosthenes fell into two main classes, the 
mathematical and the literary; to the former belonged his 
geographical and mathematical treatises, his astronomical poem 
called Hermes, and probably also his poem Erigone; to the 
latter, his treatises on the old comedy and on chronology, a 
dialogue called Arsinoe, a book about Ariston, and a treatise 
on moral philosophy (περὶ ἀγαθῶν καὶ κακών). His epistles, 
too, are often mentioned. The historical works ascribed to 
him, such as the treatise on the Gauls (Γαλατικά), of which 
the thirty-third book is cited by Stephanus,’ were probably 
written by another author of the same name, and the treatises 
‘on freedom from pain’ (περὶ ἀλυπίας), and ‘on riches and 
poverty’ (wept πλούτου καὶ πενίας), may have been parts of 
the work on moral philosophy, which we have already men- 
tioned. : 

The geography of Eratosthenes (γεωγραφικά)" was in three 
books.‘ In the first, after a general survey of the labours of 
his predecessors, he gave his theories respecting the form of 
the globe, and the changes which have taken place on its sur- 
face. In the second, he discussed mathematical geography. 
In the third, he collected all that was known of political 
geography, and all that travellers had stated respecting the 
different countries. This work was accompanied by a map, in 
which he introduced for the first time a system of parallels of 
latitude. The great achievement in this work was the dis- 
covery of a correct method of determining the magnitude of 
theearth.’ This he effected by a combination of geodzsy with 
astronomy, namely, by comparing the distance from Alex- 
andria to Syene with the corresponding are of the meridian. 
He had ascertained the obliquity of the ecliptic by means of 





1 Clem. Alex. Strom. p. 496. 

2s. v. Ὕδρηλα ; see Bernhardy, τ. 5. p. 109. 

3 See the collected fragments in Bernhardy, pp. 1-109. 

4 ‘Geographica Eratosthenes tribus tantum libris complexus est, quorum ulti- 
mum, neque eum totum, regionibus per capita describendis addixerat.’ Bern- 
hardy, u. s. 

> Varenius, Geographia, ed. Newton, Cambridge, 1681, p. 25. 


s 


ERATOSTHENES. 509 


the armille, or great circles, which he induced Ptolemy 
Euergetes to set up in the porch at Alexandria,’ and had stated 
that the interval between the tropics was J of the circum- 
ference? Having learned that deep wells at Syene were illu- 
minated to the bottom at the summer solstice, he concluded 
that this place was on the tropic,’ and assuming that Alexandria 
and Syene were on the same meridian, because the Nile was 
supposed to flow from south to north, he found that as the 
zenith of Alexandria was distant from that of Syene by 4 of 
the circumference, and as the distance of the two places was, 
in round numbers, 5000 stadia, the circumference of the earth 
must be, in round numbers, 250,000 stadia. The exact result 
should have been 216,000 stadia.* The error of Eratosthenes, 
however, was not in his method, which is that still adopted, 
but in his assumptions, for the longitude of Alexandria differs 
3° from that of Syene, and the distance of the two places is 
not exactly measured. Pliny tells us’ that Eratosthenes 
himself altered the result to 252,000 to give an exact number 
of 700 stadia for the degree, which increased the error, for the 
degree is 694: stadia.© He made another oversight in 
neglecting the diameter of the sun’s image in the well. But 
besides hitting on the right method, his results were much 
nearer the truth than those of Aristotle’ and Archimedes,’® who 
made the periphery 400,000 stadia, and 300,000 stadia re- 
spectively. 

The mathematical treatises of Eratosthenes are for the most 
part lost. We have still his letters to Ptolemy, with the 
accompanying epigram, on the solution of the Delian problem, 





1 Whewell, History of the Inductive Sciences, I. p. 210. 

3 Dr. Whewell says (ἃ. 8, p. 215): ‘it is probable that his observation gave him 
47% degrees. The fraction τὶς τῆς Toho “33 which is very nearly = 

3 The lat. of Syene, the modern Assouan, is 24° 10’ N,, and its long. 32° 59! Εἰ. 
See De Morgan in Smith’s Dictionary II. p. 45. 

4 Parthey, Alex. Mus. p. 193. 

5 H, N. ΤΙ. 108, § 247: ‘universum autem circuitum Eratosthenes in omnium 
quidem litterarum subtilitate, et in hac utique preter ceteros sollers, quem cunctis 
probari video CCLITI. milium stadiorum prodidit.’ 

6 De Morgan, u. s. 7 De Colo 11. 14 fin, 

8 Aren. II. init. 


510 PROSE WRITERS OF ALEXANDRIA. 


or the duplication of the cube,’ and Nicomachus’ has described 
his ingenious arithmetical contrivance called ‘the sieve’ 
(κόσκινον), for detecting the prime numbers. 

In the poem called Hermes, Eratosthenes used the mythology 
of this Greek deity, in combination with that of his Egyptian 
representative Thoth, as a convenient vehicle for the exposition 
of the descriptive astronomy and its bearing on the calculation 
of time, which were said by the Egyptian priests to have been 
first taught by that divinity.2 The work called καταστερισμοί, 
which is still extant, is a compilation from Hyginus,‘ who 
probably made use of the Hermes of Eratosthenes. Erigone, 
who gave her name to the constellation Virgo, was also in all 
probability the subject of an astronomical poem. 

Of the purely literary works, the most important were the 
Chronographies, of which we have already spoken,’ and the 
treatise on the old comedy, in twelve books, which, following 
critically in the steps of Lycophron and Callimachus, not only 
investigated with the greatest accuracy the history of the 
authors and the arguments of the plays, but gave details re- 
specting the arrangements of the theatre, the costume of the 
actors, and the whole mise en scéne, which we are now obliged 
to derive from secondary sources.’ Of his works referring to 
the philosophy of the Athenian schools, we must regret the 
loss of the book which he wrote about his own teacher, Ariston 
of Chios, from which Athenzeus’ quotes the lively expression of 
Eratosthenes, ‘I have already detected this man (the stoic 
philosopher), who digs a hole in the party-wall between 





1 Eutocius ad Archimedis spheram et cylindrum, pp. 21, 22, ed. Basil. Bern- 
hardy, Eratosthenica, p. 175 566. 

2 Arithmet. p. 17, Wechel. Bernhardy, p. 173. 

3 Catasterism. c. 20: τὸ πρῶτον στοιχεῖον ‘Epuod θέντος ὃς τὸν Sitaxoomoy τῶν 
ἄστρων ἐποιήσατο. ‘Ex opinione modo memorataé, que non omnino ab Erato- 
sthene conficta esse videtur sed potius secundum A®gyptiorum disciplinam 
numinis Thot inventa Grecanico deo magnam imposuit partem.’ Bernhardy, 

χε, 
᾿ 4 ‘His inter se collatis et perpensis liquere opinor non Hyginum Catasterismos 
expilasse, sed illi hos originem debere.’ Bernhardy, p. 129. 

5 Above, p. 483 [323]. 

6 Meineke, Hist. Crit. Com. Gr. p. 11. Bernhardy, p. 203 sqq. 

7 Athen. VII. p. 281 C.: ἤδη δέ wore καὶ τοῦτον πεφώρακα τὸν τῆς ἡδονῆς καὶ 
ἀρετῆς μεσότοιχον διορύττοντα καὶ ἀναφαινόμενον παρὰ τῇ ἡδονῃ. 


HIPPARCHUS. 511 


pleasure and virtue, and makes his appearance in the abode of 
the former.’ ; 

From the founder of mathematical geography, we pass to 
the father of exact astronomy, and we have in this case also to 
repeat the regret that his greatest works are known to us only 
at second hand. MHrprarcuus of Nica, in Bithynia, who 
flourished in the middle of the second century B.c., and died 
about B.c. 125, some seventy years after Eratosthenes,’ spent 
the greater part of his life at Rhodes. His connexion with 
the school of Alexandria, which has been generally taken for 
granted, and which is not improbable in itself, cannot be 
established by direct evidence.? It is certain that his imme- 
diate forerunners, Timochares of Alexandria, and Conon of 
Samos, were connected with the court of the Ptolemies, and 
this is also surmised with regard to Aristyllus. Hipparchus 
must have been influenced more or less directly by the 
works of Eratosthenes,* and one of his earliest works, which is 
still extant, namely, a commentary on the Phenomena of 
Aratus, is a book of the Alexandrian order, and indicates a 
course of study not unlike that of the Museum.‘ His great 
work, the catalogue of the fixed stars,° may have borne a 
similar relation to the Hermes of Eratosthenes, and the dis- 
covery of the precession of the equinoxes, to which it led him, 
had been anticipated in a rude way by the Egyptian astro- 
nomers,’ from whom the Pythagoreans borrowed it.’ But if 





1 Suidas: Ἵππαρχος, Νικαεύς, φιλόσοφος, γεγονὼς ἐπὶ τῶν ὑπάτων. On which 
Reinesius observes: ‘melius dixisset, floruisse Perseo Romanis capto et tempore 
belli Punici 3. et Numantini. Voss. de Scient. Mathem. c. 33.’ It seems that the text 
of Suidas omits the names of the consuls (ὕπατοι), by whose year of office his birth 
was fixed. ‘ 

2 See Delambre, Histoire de [' Astronomie ancienne, I., Discowrs préliminaire, pp. 
xxi. xxiv. IT., p. 108. 

3 A commentary on Aratus, written neither by Eratosthenes nor by Hipparchus, 
is attributed by some to the former, by others to the latter. Delambre supposes 
that it may have been an extract from a work by Eratosthenes (Hist. de [ Astr. 
anc. I. p. 173). 

4 See a full analysis of this commentary in Delambre, Hist. de Τ᾽ Astr. anc. L., 
pp. 106 sqq. 

5 Delambre τι. s., pp. 290—3. He was the first author of the planisphere: Jd. 
p- 315. 

ὁ Lepsius, Chronologie der Zgypten, pp. 196 sqq. 

7 Id. ibid. p. 206. 


512 PROSE WRITERS OF ALEXANDRIA. 


we had less reason than we have for numbering Hipparchus 
among those who derived their training from the school of 
Alexandria, we owe our acquaintance with his discoveries so 
entirely to the work of Claudius Ptolemzeus, in which they are 
incorporated, that we can hardly place him in any other con- 
nexion. As a question of Greek literature, the system of 
Hipparchus must be treated in connexion with that of Ptolemy;' 
a full account of his discoveries belongs to the history of 
mathematics, astronomy, or the inductive sciences in general, 
and he has been duly honoured by the greatest writers on 
these subjects, Montucla, Delambre, and Whewell. It will be 
sufficient in this place to mention briefly what were the 
general results of his labours. 

Hipparchus discovered by his own observations, which ex- 
tended from 8.0. 162,? when he first observed the autumnal 
equinox, to B.c. 127,° assisted by those of Aristarchus of Samos, 
that the ordinary solar year of 3654 days was five minutes too 
long, and corrected the period of Callippus by deducting the 
day of excess from the 304 years. He was the first to observe 
accurately the anomaly of the sun’s motion, and constructed 
solar tables by means of which the sun’s place with respect to 
the stars could be correctly found at any time. In connexion 
with this he established the theory of epicycles, or, what is 
much the same thing, determined the orbit called the eccentric. 
He made some progress in similar calculations with regard 
to the path of the moon. By an ingenious contrivance, known 
as the Diagramma Hipparchi, he determined the magnitude and 
relative distance of the heavenly bodies. It was he, as we 
have already mentioned, who first undertook a catalogue of the 
fixed stars. He thus enumerated 1080, and indicated their 





1 Below, chapter LVI., § 1. 

2 He observed the autumnal equinox on the 30th of Mesore in the 17th year of 
the third Callippic period = 27th Sept., 162 B.c. Clinton, F. H. III. p. 87. 

3 According to Ptolemy (Syntaxis III. pp. 111, 112) he took observations 
at Rhodes on the 22nd March, B.c. 128, on the 4th Aug., B.c. 128, on the 
and May, B.c. 127, and on the 7th July, B.c. 127. See Clinton, 7. H. 111. 

. ITQ. 

: 5 Pliny in a remarkable passage (7. NV. II. 26, § 95) says that Hipparchus was 
led to form this catalogue from the observation of a new moving star, probably a 
comet. 


HIPPARCHUS. 513 


places in a καταστερισμὸς, or celestial map.’ It was in the 
course of this labour that he determined, what was previously 
known to the old astronomers,’ the precession of the equinoxes,? 
and he wrote a special treatise on this subject. At first he 
confined this movement to the stars in and near the zodiac, 
but he eventually found that it was general. Having only 
the imperfect observations of Timochares and Aristyllus to 
compare with his own,* he was obliged to content himself with 
fixing the minimum of this movement at 36” per annum, in- 
stead of 50” 12, at which it is now estimated. He com- 
pleted the method of determining the latitude and longitude 
of places, to which Eratosthenes had made a first approxi- 
mation; he calculated longitude by the eclipses of the moon, 
and gave rules for predicting the eclipses both of the moon 
and of the sun. Of the instruments with which he performed 
all these observations, Ptolemy gives us no account. But it is 
clear that he had few, if any, of the resources of a modern 
observatory,’ and the Greek system of arithmetical notation 
must have increased his difficulties in no slight measure. 
What steps he took to obviate this inconvenience is not known, 
but it may be inferred from an incidental notice in Plutarch 
that he had drawn up a system of arithmetic, or had written 
on the subject.© The operations undertaken by Hippar- 
chus show that he was acquainted with stereographic projec. 
tions, and with the methods of plane and spherical trigo- 





1 He intended that his celestial map should represent the concavity of the 
sphere, Delambre (Hist. de l’Astr. anc. I. p. 111) says: ‘ Attalusa voulu disculper 
Aratus, en disant que le Dragon était peint tel qu’on le verrait de dehors, 
Hipparque rejette cette excuse, en disant qu’on dessine les constellations pour 
notre usage, telles que nous les voyons et tournées vers nous, ce qui est ἃ 
remarquer.’ 

2 Lepsius, Chronologie der digypten, pp. 196209. 

3 Delambre ἃ. 5, I. 175, II. 103. 

4 Ptolem. Synt. VII. c. 14. Ideler, Handbuch, I. pp. 27, 193. 

5 Ruhnen (de Grecia, &e., p. 96): ‘ erudita illa Grecorum gens ultra, quo 
progrederetur, vix habuit, tum aliis caussis impedita, tum omni fere supellectile, 
que sideribus observandis inserviat, destituta.’ And he adds: ‘quo magis 
seepenumero veterum sagacitatem admiror, qui, que recentiores tuborum ope cog- 
norint, eadem, tanquam divini, raré et singulari ingenii vi conjecerint.’ 

8 De repugnantiis Stoicis, p. 1047 Ὁ, V. I. p. 269, Wyttenb.: Χρύσιππον δὲ 
πάντες ἐλέγχουσιν οἱ ἀριθμητικοί, ὧν καὶ Ἵππαρχός ἐστιν, ἀποδεικνύων τὸ 
διάπτωμα τοῦ λογισμοῦ παμμέγεθες αὐτῷ γεγονός. 


Vou. II. 1 


514 PROSE WRITERS OF ALEXANDRIA. 


nometry ;' and as no mention is made of these branches of pure 
mathematics before his time, he must have the honour of the 
discovery. 

The only extant works of Hipparchus are his juvenile com- 
mentary on Aratus and Eudoxus (τῶν ᾿Αράτου καὶ ᾿Εὐδόξου 
Φαινομένων ἐξηγήσεων βιβλία y’), to which we have already re- 
ferred, and which may be compared, in some respects, with 
Newton’s first publication—the reprint of the Geography of 
Varenius :* and the catalogue of the fixed stars (ἔκθεσις aorept- 
σμῶν, OY περὶ τῶν ἀπλανῶν ἀναγραφαῖ), Which is quoted verbatim 
in Ptolemy’s Syntavis.’ The following works are mentioned, but 
are entirely lost: (1) on the magnitude and distances of the sun 
and moon (περὶ μεγεθῶν καὶ ἀποστημάτων) “ we know that he 
fixed the sun’s distance from the earth at 1200 radii of the earth ; 
that of the moon at 59 radii; the diameter of the sun was 53 
diameters of the earth, and the diameter of the earth was 32 
diameters of the moon; (2) on the movement of the moon in 
latitude (περὶ τῆς κατὰ πλάτος μηνιαίας τῆς σελήνης κινήσεως) ;° 
(3) on the length of the month (περὶ μηνιαίου χρόνου) ;° (4) on 
the length of the year (περὶ ἐνιαυσίου μεγέθους) ;’ (5) on the 
retrogradation of the solstitial and equinoctial points (περὶ τῆς 
μεταπτώσεως τῶν τροπικῶν Kal ἰσημερινῶν σημείων) ; (6) on 
intercalated months and days (περὶ ἐμβολίμων μηνῶν τε καὶ 
ἡμερῶν) ; ;° (7) on the theory of the straight lines in a circle 
(περὶ τῆς πραγματείας τῶν ἐν κύκλῳ εὐθειῶν), probably a 
treatise on plane trigonometry ;” (8) on gravitation (περὶ τῶν 
διὰ βάρος κάτω φερομένων) ;" (9) on eclipses of the sun (περὶ 
ἐκλείψεων ἡλίου κατὰ τὰ ἕπτα KAtmara);” (10) acriticism on the 
geography of Eratosthenes, of which Strabo quotes the second 





1 See Delambre, Hist. de l’Astr. anc. I. p. 117. 

* Berhn. Vareni Geographia generalis, ab Isaaco ΠΥ ΤΙ Math. Prof. Lucas. 
apud Cantabrigienses, ed. II. Cantabr. 1681. 

3 Ptolemy, VII: 5. Perhaps this work included the two mentioned by Suidas as : 
περὶ τῆς τ. ἀ. συντάξεως καὶ καταστερισμοῦ. 

4 Ptolemy, ἐδέά. 5 Mentioned by Suidas and Eudocia. 

6 Mentioned by Galen. 7 Ptolemy, ITI. 2. 8 Id. 

9 Ptolemy, Syntaxis, III. 2, p. 63, quoted by Clinton, F. H. II. p. 339, note 
v., who has shown how nearly Hipparchus approximated to the true time. 

10 Theon, Comment. in Almagest. I. 9. 

14 Simplicius, de Calo, I. p. 61 B. 

12 Achilles Tatius, Isagog. in Arat. Phenom. 19. p. 139. Cf. Plin. H. N, IL. 12. 





HIPPARCHUS. 515 


book.‘ The diligence and accuracy of this review are highly 
commended by Pliny,’ but Strabo thinks that Hipparchus was 
somewhat unfair in bringing his accurate geometry to bear on 
the rough and general views of his illustrious predecessor. 

Such was the great Hipparchus, of whom Pliny says that he 
is never sufficiently praised,‘ and whom he places by the side of 
Thales, as ἃ man of more than human ability : whom even the 
fastidious Delambre considers ‘one of the most extraordinary 
men of antiquity, the very greatest in the sciences which require 
a combination of observation with geometry.’® If the patronage 
of the Ptolemies had produced no result beyond the encourage- 
ment which it afforded to labours like his and those of 
Eratosthenes, we must regard it as the best bestowed muni- 
ficence that ever graced the throne of a military sovereign. 
And Alexandria may thus claim, in addition to its services in 
furnishing warehouse-room for the literature of Greece, and 
mustering a troop of careful editors and commentators, the 
distinction of having encouraged the first beginnings of the 
greatest of inductive sciences. It is only to be regretted that 
we have so often saved from the ruins of the library the results 
of scholastic industry and ingenuity, instead of those efforts of 
original genius which have left their impress on the intellectual 
world. 

235. p. 69. 

3 H. N. 11. 108, ὃ 247: ‘Hipparchus et in coarguendo eo et in reliqué omni 
diligentia mirus.’ 

3 II. p. 79: ἀγνωμονεῖν δὴ δόξειεν ἂν ὁ Ἵππαρχος πρὸς Thy τοιαύτην ὁλοσχέρειαν 
γεωμετρικῶς ἀντιλέγων. 

4 H. N. II. 26, ὃ 95 : ‘idem Hipparchus, nunquam satis laudatus, ut quo nemo 
magis adprobaverit cognationem cum homine siderum animasque nostras partem 
esse ceeli,’ For the sentiment, cf. IT, 12, §§ 54, 55, and 11, ὃ 49. 

5 H. N. 12, §§ 53—55. 

® The words of Delambre deserve to be quoted in the original (Hist. de I’ Astr. 
anc, I. pp. 185, 6): ‘quand on réunit tout ce qu’il a inventé ou perfectionné, 
qu'on songe au nombre de ses ouvrages, ἃ la quantité de calculs qu’ils supposent, 
on trouve dans Hipparque un des hommes les plus étonnans de I’antiquité, et le 
plus grand de tous dans les sciences qui ne sont pas purement spéculatives, et qui 
démandent qu’aux connaissances géométriques on réunisse des connaissances de 
faits particuliers et de phénoménes dont Vobservation exige beaucoup d’assiduité 


et des instrumens perfectionnés.’ For the value of this praise, see Whewell’s 
History of the Inductive Sciences, I. p. 191. 





END OF VOL. 11. 











Lo “ . 
λ ͵ ῳ 
at = ger x ᾿ - & 
4 * κ: ~ . ᾿ ἐ é 
| ι πο δνὰ f Ὰ ; x :. 
= " ‘ ἕ 4 "" 























University of Toronto 














Acme Library Card Pocket 
LOWE-MARTIN CO. LIMITED 














‘ALVG 





"TAMOAAOT AO ANVN : | 


“@°T°A «= *ueSpTeuog Aq penuyy 
—uoo ‘[uosptTeuog pue stmey fq *I4] feoeern 
qUSefous JO singzeteyTT eyy yo A1048TH 
P8TTFIO Trey ‘TOTO 
OS9STT 


| 
| 














a 
SP eS emg Ἣν 


dee ee 








: pao Ὁ Se a eat μονα 
ὃ : A ee Sire “ Seanbictimbrcieal tae cr Sarees 
4 “ ‘ s SA ge ont ey SV see τ τέ νας. ee reece ΤΙΣ ἃς 
ἘΞ : ᾿ “erie eet Ex ace tar a danhatedieapediociaas pe 
Ξ ΞΞ mz ἘΞ : ; ας γα ον ταν Seka : 
2 Sa tae τὸν ᾿ ; | 



































ons 
; sate ene =A : 

ἘΞ ΞΟΣ τα ees , Ξ eee 

πα at ara ees wt Sie oS 

ree = - τ : τς: ἐν 


ΒΗ